反事实(“but for”)与因果推理之间的关系:实验结果及其对陪审员决定的启示

Q2 Social Sciences
Barbara A. Spellman, Alexandra Kincannon
{"title":"反事实(“but for”)与因果推理之间的关系:实验结果及其对陪审员决定的启示","authors":"Barbara A. Spellman, Alexandra Kincannon","doi":"10.2307/1192297","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"BARBARA A. SPELLMAN [*] ALEXANDRA KINCANNON [**] I INTRODUCTION People often try to discover the causes of the events around them: Why did their child behave a certain way? Why did their football team lose? Why does their computer crash at critical moments? People also often trust other people to make causal decisions for them. We allow scientists to tell us that smoking causes lung cancer and that eggs are bad for us (some years, anyway). We also allow, or rather we require, jurors to make decisions about causality in many kinds of cases. Another kind of reasoning people do is to imagine the world other than it is and play out the consequences. For example, if the child had not watched so much television, if the quarterback had not thrown that interception, or if grandfather had quit smoking, might the world be a happier place? This kind of reasoning is called \"counterfactual reasoning.\" In its most common guise, people imagine an early event (\"antecedent\") as being different (for example, no interception), leading to an outcome (\"consequent\") that may also be different (for example, winning the game). A. Counterfactual Reasoning as \"but for\" Causal Reasoning in the Law The legal system often asks jurors to use counterfactual reasoning to make decisions about causation. Obviously, the idea of causality is essential in law: Generally, we do not wish to punish or impose liability on someone unless he or she caused the damage at issue. Both criminal and civil codes (especially in the context of negligence) spend many pages defining what it means to be a cause. In both kinds of cases, to be considered a cause, the potential cause in question must fulfill two requirements: It must be a \"but for\" cause (also called \"cause in-fact\" or \"factual cause or sine qua non\") of the outcome; and it must be a legal cause (also called \"proximate cause\") of the outcome. The legal cause requirement limits the infinite number of \"but for\" causes to those for which it makes sense to hold people liable. The definition of \"but for\" cause can be seen in the Model Penal Code (\"MPC\"), the Restatement (Second) of Torts, and in common civil jury instructions. In the MPC's general definition of \"causal relationship,\" the \"but for\" requirement is stated as follows: Conduct is the cause of a result when: (a) it is an antecedent but for which the result in question would not have occurred...[1] In negligence cases in California, the Book of Approved Jury Instructions (\"BAJI\") recommended the following \"standard\" jury instruction for many years: A proximate cause of injury is a cause which... produces the injury and without which the injury would not have occurred.[2] Thus, jurors' causal judgments require counterfactual reasoning and a finding that changing the antecedent would have changed the outcome in question. B. Present Questions The legal system obviously assumes that people can reason counterfactually by making this type of reasoning essential for judgments of causation. What does the psychological literature say about people's capacity for counterfactual and causal reasoning and the relation between them? This article describes the existing body of psychological research on counterfactual and causal reasoning. It then focuses on research dealing with two specific questions regarding their relation that is relevant to legal causal judgments. First, is counterfactual reasoning really the basis for causal judgments? We show how psychology's answer to that question has changed over time, and present research involving cases of multiple sufficient causes that demonstrates that counterfactual reasoning cannot, in fact, be the basis for all causal judgments. Second, in what way does counterfactual reasoning affect causal reasoning? We review research that shows that making a counterfactual judgment can affect later causal judgments; we then make suggestions as to when and why it does so--and should do so. …","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"37 1","pages":"241-264"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2001-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"57","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The Relation between Counterfactual (\\\"but for\\\") and Causal Reasoning: Experimental Findings and Implications for Jurors' Decisions\",\"authors\":\"Barbara A. Spellman, Alexandra Kincannon\",\"doi\":\"10.2307/1192297\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"BARBARA A. SPELLMAN [*] ALEXANDRA KINCANNON [**] I INTRODUCTION People often try to discover the causes of the events around them: Why did their child behave a certain way? Why did their football team lose? Why does their computer crash at critical moments? People also often trust other people to make causal decisions for them. We allow scientists to tell us that smoking causes lung cancer and that eggs are bad for us (some years, anyway). We also allow, or rather we require, jurors to make decisions about causality in many kinds of cases. Another kind of reasoning people do is to imagine the world other than it is and play out the consequences. For example, if the child had not watched so much television, if the quarterback had not thrown that interception, or if grandfather had quit smoking, might the world be a happier place? This kind of reasoning is called \\\"counterfactual reasoning.\\\" In its most common guise, people imagine an early event (\\\"antecedent\\\") as being different (for example, no interception), leading to an outcome (\\\"consequent\\\") that may also be different (for example, winning the game). A. Counterfactual Reasoning as \\\"but for\\\" Causal Reasoning in the Law The legal system often asks jurors to use counterfactual reasoning to make decisions about causation. Obviously, the idea of causality is essential in law: Generally, we do not wish to punish or impose liability on someone unless he or she caused the damage at issue. Both criminal and civil codes (especially in the context of negligence) spend many pages defining what it means to be a cause. In both kinds of cases, to be considered a cause, the potential cause in question must fulfill two requirements: It must be a \\\"but for\\\" cause (also called \\\"cause in-fact\\\" or \\\"factual cause or sine qua non\\\") of the outcome; and it must be a legal cause (also called \\\"proximate cause\\\") of the outcome. The legal cause requirement limits the infinite number of \\\"but for\\\" causes to those for which it makes sense to hold people liable. The definition of \\\"but for\\\" cause can be seen in the Model Penal Code (\\\"MPC\\\"), the Restatement (Second) of Torts, and in common civil jury instructions. In the MPC's general definition of \\\"causal relationship,\\\" the \\\"but for\\\" requirement is stated as follows: Conduct is the cause of a result when: (a) it is an antecedent but for which the result in question would not have occurred...[1] In negligence cases in California, the Book of Approved Jury Instructions (\\\"BAJI\\\") recommended the following \\\"standard\\\" jury instruction for many years: A proximate cause of injury is a cause which... produces the injury and without which the injury would not have occurred.[2] Thus, jurors' causal judgments require counterfactual reasoning and a finding that changing the antecedent would have changed the outcome in question. B. Present Questions The legal system obviously assumes that people can reason counterfactually by making this type of reasoning essential for judgments of causation. What does the psychological literature say about people's capacity for counterfactual and causal reasoning and the relation between them? This article describes the existing body of psychological research on counterfactual and causal reasoning. It then focuses on research dealing with two specific questions regarding their relation that is relevant to legal causal judgments. First, is counterfactual reasoning really the basis for causal judgments? We show how psychology's answer to that question has changed over time, and present research involving cases of multiple sufficient causes that demonstrates that counterfactual reasoning cannot, in fact, be the basis for all causal judgments. Second, in what way does counterfactual reasoning affect causal reasoning? We review research that shows that making a counterfactual judgment can affect later causal judgments; we then make suggestions as to when and why it does so--and should do so. …\",\"PeriodicalId\":39484,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Law and Contemporary Problems\",\"volume\":\"37 1\",\"pages\":\"241-264\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2001-09-22\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"57\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Law and Contemporary Problems\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192297\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q2\",\"JCRName\":\"Social Sciences\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Law and Contemporary Problems","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192297","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"Social Sciences","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 57

摘要

人们经常试图发现周围事件的原因:为什么他们的孩子会有某种行为?他们的足球队为什么输了?为什么他们的电脑会在关键时刻死机?人们也常常相信别人会替他们做因果决定。我们听任科学家告诉我们,吸烟会导致肺癌,鸡蛋对我们有害(反正要过几年)。我们也允许,或者更确切地说,我们要求陪审员在许多案件中对因果关系作出决定。人们做的另一种推理是想象世界的另一种情况,并设想其后果。例如,如果孩子没有看那么多电视,如果四分卫没有扔出那个拦截球,或者如果祖父戒烟了,这个世界可能会更快乐吗?这种推理被称为“反事实推理”。在其最常见的伪装下,人们想象一个早期事件(“先行”)是不同的(例如,没有拦截),导致一个可能也不同的结果(“结果”)(例如,赢得游戏)。A.反事实推理作为法律中的因果推理的“but for”法律制度经常要求陪审员使用反事实推理来作出因果关系的决定。显然,因果关系的概念在法律中是必不可少的:一般来说,我们不希望惩罚或强加责任给某人,除非他或她造成了争议中的损害。刑事和民事法典(特别是在过失的背景下)都花了很多页来定义什么是原因。在这两种情况下,要被认为是原因,所讨论的潜在原因必须满足两个条件:它必须是结果的“但是”原因(也称为“事实原因”或“事实原因”或“必要条件”);它必须是导致结果的法律原因(也称为“近因”)。法律原因要求将无限数量的“但是”原因限制在那些有理由让人们承担责任的原因上。“但是”原因的定义可以在《示范刑法典》(MPC)、《侵权重述(第二版)》和普通民事陪审团指示中看到。在MPC对“因果关系”的一般定义中,“除非”的要求如下:行为是结果的原因,当:(a)它是一个先决条件,否则所讨论的结果不会发生……[1]在加州的过失案件中,经批准的陪审团指导手册(“BAJI”)多年来一直推荐以下“标准”陪审团指导:伤害的近因是…造成伤害,如果没有它,伤害就不会发生。[2]因此,陪审员的因果判断需要反事实推理,并发现改变前因会改变所讨论的结果。法律体系显然假设人们可以反事实推理,从而使这种推理对因果关系的判断至关重要。关于反事实推理和因果推理的能力以及它们之间的关系,心理学文献是怎么说的?本文介绍了现有的反事实推理和因果推理的心理学研究。然后重点研究处理与法律因果判断相关的两个具体问题。首先,反事实推理真的是因果判断的基础吗?我们展示了心理学对这个问题的答案是如何随着时间的推移而变化的,目前的研究涉及多个充分原因的案例,这些案例表明,事实上,反事实推理不能成为所有因果判断的基础。第二,反事实推理以何种方式影响因果推理?我们回顾了一些研究,这些研究表明,做出反事实判断会影响后来的因果判断;然后,我们提出建议,说明它何时以及为什么会这样做——以及应该这样做。…
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The Relation between Counterfactual ("but for") and Causal Reasoning: Experimental Findings and Implications for Jurors' Decisions
BARBARA A. SPELLMAN [*] ALEXANDRA KINCANNON [**] I INTRODUCTION People often try to discover the causes of the events around them: Why did their child behave a certain way? Why did their football team lose? Why does their computer crash at critical moments? People also often trust other people to make causal decisions for them. We allow scientists to tell us that smoking causes lung cancer and that eggs are bad for us (some years, anyway). We also allow, or rather we require, jurors to make decisions about causality in many kinds of cases. Another kind of reasoning people do is to imagine the world other than it is and play out the consequences. For example, if the child had not watched so much television, if the quarterback had not thrown that interception, or if grandfather had quit smoking, might the world be a happier place? This kind of reasoning is called "counterfactual reasoning." In its most common guise, people imagine an early event ("antecedent") as being different (for example, no interception), leading to an outcome ("consequent") that may also be different (for example, winning the game). A. Counterfactual Reasoning as "but for" Causal Reasoning in the Law The legal system often asks jurors to use counterfactual reasoning to make decisions about causation. Obviously, the idea of causality is essential in law: Generally, we do not wish to punish or impose liability on someone unless he or she caused the damage at issue. Both criminal and civil codes (especially in the context of negligence) spend many pages defining what it means to be a cause. In both kinds of cases, to be considered a cause, the potential cause in question must fulfill two requirements: It must be a "but for" cause (also called "cause in-fact" or "factual cause or sine qua non") of the outcome; and it must be a legal cause (also called "proximate cause") of the outcome. The legal cause requirement limits the infinite number of "but for" causes to those for which it makes sense to hold people liable. The definition of "but for" cause can be seen in the Model Penal Code ("MPC"), the Restatement (Second) of Torts, and in common civil jury instructions. In the MPC's general definition of "causal relationship," the "but for" requirement is stated as follows: Conduct is the cause of a result when: (a) it is an antecedent but for which the result in question would not have occurred...[1] In negligence cases in California, the Book of Approved Jury Instructions ("BAJI") recommended the following "standard" jury instruction for many years: A proximate cause of injury is a cause which... produces the injury and without which the injury would not have occurred.[2] Thus, jurors' causal judgments require counterfactual reasoning and a finding that changing the antecedent would have changed the outcome in question. B. Present Questions The legal system obviously assumes that people can reason counterfactually by making this type of reasoning essential for judgments of causation. What does the psychological literature say about people's capacity for counterfactual and causal reasoning and the relation between them? This article describes the existing body of psychological research on counterfactual and causal reasoning. It then focuses on research dealing with two specific questions regarding their relation that is relevant to legal causal judgments. First, is counterfactual reasoning really the basis for causal judgments? We show how psychology's answer to that question has changed over time, and present research involving cases of multiple sufficient causes that demonstrates that counterfactual reasoning cannot, in fact, be the basis for all causal judgments. Second, in what way does counterfactual reasoning affect causal reasoning? We review research that shows that making a counterfactual judgment can affect later causal judgments; we then make suggestions as to when and why it does so--and should do so. …
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Law and Contemporary Problems
Law and Contemporary Problems Social Sciences-Law
CiteScore
2.00
自引率
0.00%
发文量
1
期刊介绍: Law and Contemporary Problems was founded in 1933 and is the oldest journal published at Duke Law School. It is a quarterly, interdisciplinary, faculty-edited publication of Duke Law School. L&CP recognizes that many fields in the sciences, social sciences, and humanities can enhance the development and understanding of law. It is our purpose to seek out these areas of overlap and to publish balanced symposia that enlighten not just legal readers, but readers from these other disciplines as well. L&CP uses a symposium format, generally publishing one symposium per issue on a topic of contemporary concern. Authors and articles are selected to ensure that each issue collectively creates a unified presentation of the contemporary problem under consideration. L&CP hosts an annual conference at Duke Law School featuring the authors of one of the year’s four symposia.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信