孩子会用连词来解释“或”吗?

IF 1.6 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY
Dimitrios Skordos, Roman Feiman, Alan C. Bale, D. Barner
{"title":"孩子会用连词来解释“或”吗?","authors":"Dimitrios Skordos, Roman Feiman, Alan C. Bale, D. Barner","doi":"10.1093/JOS/FFZ022","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Preschoolers often struggle to compute scalar implicatures (SI) involving disjunction (or), in which they are required to strengthen an utterance by negating stronger alternatives, e.g., to infer that, “The girl has an apple or an orange” likely means she doesn’t have both. However, recent reports surprisingly find that a substantial subset of children interpret disjunction as conjunction, concluding instead that the girl must have both fruits. According to these studies, children arrive at conjunctive readings not because they have a non-adult-like semantics, but because they lack access to the stronger scalar alternative and, and employ doubly exhaustified disjuncts when computing implicatures. Using stimuli modeled on previous studies, we test English-speaking preschoolers and replicate the finding that many children interpret or conjunctively. However, we speculate that conditions which replicate this finding may be pragmatically infelicitous, such that results do not offer a valid test of children’s semantic competence. We show that when disjunctive statements are uttered in contexts that render the speaker’s intended question more transparent, conjunctive readings disappear almost entirely. INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 4 Older preschoolers and kindergarteners often struggle to compute scalar implicatures (SIs) involving quantifiers like some (Smith, 1980; Noveck, 2001; Papafragou & Musolino, 2003) and logical operators like disjunction (Braine & Rumain, 1981; Chierchia et al., 2001). For example, when presented with an utterance containing some like the one in (1a), many children fail to derive the implicature in (1c). Similarly, when presented with a sentence like the one in (2a) many children fail to derive an exclusive interpretation of or characterized by (2c): (1) a. The boy took some of the bananas. b. The boy took all of the bananas. c. The boy took some, but not all of the bananas. (2) a. The girl has an apple or an orange. b. The girl has an apple and an orange. c. The girl has an apple or an orange, but not both. On most accounts, deriving a scalar implicature involves accessing a stronger alternative statement that is generated by replacing one scalar term (e.g., some, or) with another, stronger, one (e.g., all, and). For example, to derive an implicature for the sentence containing some in (1a), children must access and negate the stronger alternative in (1b). Likewise, to derive the implicature for the sentence containing or in (2a), children must access and negate the stronger alternative in (2b). On standard accounts of disjunction, a failure to do so should result in an inclusive interpretation, wherein the listener concludes that the utterance in (2a) is acceptable even when the girl has both an apple and an orange (Crain & Khlentzos, 2010; Gazdar, 1979; McCawly, 1993; Pelletier, 1977). INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 5 Children’s difficulties with SI have been variously attributed to general processing limitations (Chierchia et al., 2001; Reinhart, 2004; Pouscoulous et al., 2007), difficulty in understanding the communicative goals of the experimenters (Musolino & Papafragou, 2003; Papafragou & Tantalou, 2004), and a tendency to be more tolerant of pragmatic infelicity (Katsos & Bishop, 2011). More recently, evidence has begun to accumulate in support of an account focusing on children’s access to relevant linguistic alternatives that are necessary to derive an SI (Barner et al., 2011; Barner & Bachrach, 2010; Chierchia et al., 2001; Foppolo et al., 2012; Hochstein et al., 2014; Tieu et al., 2016; Skordos & Papafragou, 2016). These accounts argue that difficulties in accessing necessary linguistic alternatives might explain why children fail to derive implicatures, whether such difficulties are due to a lack of associations between scale mates, a failure to detect which alternatives are contextually relevant, or a lack of working memory capacity to compute the contribution of alternatives while simultaneously considering a sentence’s basic meaning. While most studies in support of the “access to alternatives” view have focused on conditions under which children derive weak vs. strong interpretations of utterances, both of which are available to adults, two recent studies have argued for this account by pointing to an entirely different form of evidence, namely the interpretation of disjunction as conjunction. Specifically, these studies report that, given an utterance like (2a) above, some children conclude that the girl must have both types of fruit. In one study documenting this phenomenon, Singh et al. (2016) tested 4and 5-year-old English-speaking children (N=31) using a modified Truth Value Judgment task (Crain & Thornton, 1998). Surprisingly, they found that children accepted disjunctive statements (e.g., The boy has an apple or a banana) only about 35% of the time when one of the disjuncts was true (henceforth 1-Disjunct-True trials), but 76% of the time when both INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 6 disjuncts were true (henceforth 2-Disjunct-True-trials). In addition, children displayed a similar behavior with disjunction embedded under a universal quantifier (e.g., Every boy has an apple or a banana), accepting 1-Disjunct-True trials about 45% of the time and 2-Disjunct-True trials, 75% of the time. This pattern of responses is particularly surprising when seen from the standard perspective that children often do not derive implicatures at all; if that were the case, they should generally be inclusive and be equally likely to accept disjunction in 1-Disjunct true and 2Disjunct-True trials. Critically, Singh et al. classified children according to their individual response patterns: Four children performed in an adult-like manner, accepting 1-Disjunct-True utterances while rejecting 2-Disjunct-True utterances (henceforth “Exclusive”). Another four children showed the pattern of failure often reported in previous studies, accepting both 1Disjunct-True and 2-Disjunct-True trials (henceforth “Inclusive”). Finally, 21 out of 31 children (or 67%) responded as if or was and, rejecting 1-Disjunct-True utterances while accepting 2Disjunct-True trials (henceforth “Conjunctive”). Adopting the “access to alternatives” account, Singh et al. argue that children in their study arrive at conjunctive interpretations because they lack access to stronger alternative statements 1 Against this hypothesis that children simply think or always means and, Singh and colleagues (2016) point out that children do not derive conjunctive meanings in downward entailing environments, such as when disjunction is embedded under the scope of negation (Gualmini & Crain, 2002; Goro & Akiba, 2004; Jing, Crain & Hsu, 2005), when it occurs in the antecedent of conditionals (Su, 2014), and when it is in the nuclear scope of only, before, not every, etc. (Goro, Minai & Crain, 2005; Jing, Crain & Hsu, 2005; Gualmini & Crain, 2002; Notley, Zhou, Jensen & Crain, 2012; cf. Tieu et al., 2017; Singh et al., 2016, for discussion). INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 7 derived by replacing or with and. Consequently, they are restricted to deriving implicatures from alternatives that are contained within the original assertion – i.e., the individual disjuncts. Also, and critical to their account, Singh et al. adopt the grammatical view of implicature (Fox, 2007; Chierchia, et al., 2009), and propose that children’s disjunctive alternatives are exhaustified before being negated, resulting in multiple exhaustification (for additional discussion of this account, see Crnič, Chemla, & Fox, 2015; Fox & Katzir, 2011; Franke, 2011; Katzir, 2007; Spector, 2016). Specifically, when children hear a disjunctive statement like (3a), they compute alternatives by exhaustifying each separate disjunct in (3b) and (3c), resulting in the statements in (3d) and (3e): (3) a. The girl has an apple or an orange. b. The girl has an apple. c. The girl has an orange. d. The girl has an apple but not an orange (i.e., only an apple). e. The girl has an orange but not an apple (i.e., only an orange). The original disjunctive statement is then strengthened by negating these exhaustified alternatives, resulting in the statements in (4a) and (4b), which, when combined with the original statement result in a conjunctive meaning, in (4c). (4) a. It’s not the case that the girl has only an apple. b. It’s not the case that the girl has only an orange. c. The girl has an apple or an orange (6a), but doesn’t have only an apple, and doesn’t have only an orange (7a & 7b) (i.e., the girl has both an apple and an orange). According to this theory, adults do not derive the implication in (4c) because they have access to the alternative with and – i.e., “The girl has an apple and an orange.” The inclusion of INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 8 this alternative, since it is stronger than the plain disjunctive statement, leads to its negation, and the corresponding inference that the girl does not have both. This inference directly contradicts the inference in (4c). Since contradictory inferences are not permitted by the exhaustification operator, the derivation of (4c) is blocked (see Fox’s 2007 discussion of innocent exclusion for details). Thus, on Singh et al.’s analysis, their study simultaneously supports the idea that access to alternatives limits children’s implicatures, as well as the idea that children’s implicatures can involve multiple iterations of exhaustification. As they note, such an analysis integrates work on acquisition (e.g., Paris 1973; Braine & Rumain 1981; Tieu et al. 2017) with a broader account of multiple exhaustification, which previous studies have used to explain other forms of implicature, including so-called “free choice” inferences (see Fox, 2007; Chierchia et al. 2009; see also Geurts, 2010; Franke 2011; Meyer, forthcoming, for accounts that do not employ multiple exhaustification). The power of this unifying account depends on the reliability of the deve","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"35 1","pages":"247-267"},"PeriodicalIF":1.6000,"publicationDate":"2020-05-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"5","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Do Children Interpret 'or' Conjunctively?\",\"authors\":\"Dimitrios Skordos, Roman Feiman, Alan C. Bale, D. Barner\",\"doi\":\"10.1093/JOS/FFZ022\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Preschoolers often struggle to compute scalar implicatures (SI) involving disjunction (or), in which they are required to strengthen an utterance by negating stronger alternatives, e.g., to infer that, “The girl has an apple or an orange” likely means she doesn’t have both. However, recent reports surprisingly find that a substantial subset of children interpret disjunction as conjunction, concluding instead that the girl must have both fruits. According to these studies, children arrive at conjunctive readings not because they have a non-adult-like semantics, but because they lack access to the stronger scalar alternative and, and employ doubly exhaustified disjuncts when computing implicatures. Using stimuli modeled on previous studies, we test English-speaking preschoolers and replicate the finding that many children interpret or conjunctively. However, we speculate that conditions which replicate this finding may be pragmatically infelicitous, such that results do not offer a valid test of children’s semantic competence. We show that when disjunctive statements are uttered in contexts that render the speaker’s intended question more transparent, conjunctive readings disappear almost entirely. INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 4 Older preschoolers and kindergarteners often struggle to compute scalar implicatures (SIs) involving quantifiers like some (Smith, 1980; Noveck, 2001; Papafragou & Musolino, 2003) and logical operators like disjunction (Braine & Rumain, 1981; Chierchia et al., 2001). For example, when presented with an utterance containing some like the one in (1a), many children fail to derive the implicature in (1c). Similarly, when presented with a sentence like the one in (2a) many children fail to derive an exclusive interpretation of or characterized by (2c): (1) a. The boy took some of the bananas. b. The boy took all of the bananas. c. The boy took some, but not all of the bananas. (2) a. The girl has an apple or an orange. b. The girl has an apple and an orange. c. The girl has an apple or an orange, but not both. On most accounts, deriving a scalar implicature involves accessing a stronger alternative statement that is generated by replacing one scalar term (e.g., some, or) with another, stronger, one (e.g., all, and). For example, to derive an implicature for the sentence containing some in (1a), children must access and negate the stronger alternative in (1b). Likewise, to derive the implicature for the sentence containing or in (2a), children must access and negate the stronger alternative in (2b). On standard accounts of disjunction, a failure to do so should result in an inclusive interpretation, wherein the listener concludes that the utterance in (2a) is acceptable even when the girl has both an apple and an orange (Crain & Khlentzos, 2010; Gazdar, 1979; McCawly, 1993; Pelletier, 1977). INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 5 Children’s difficulties with SI have been variously attributed to general processing limitations (Chierchia et al., 2001; Reinhart, 2004; Pouscoulous et al., 2007), difficulty in understanding the communicative goals of the experimenters (Musolino & Papafragou, 2003; Papafragou & Tantalou, 2004), and a tendency to be more tolerant of pragmatic infelicity (Katsos & Bishop, 2011). More recently, evidence has begun to accumulate in support of an account focusing on children’s access to relevant linguistic alternatives that are necessary to derive an SI (Barner et al., 2011; Barner & Bachrach, 2010; Chierchia et al., 2001; Foppolo et al., 2012; Hochstein et al., 2014; Tieu et al., 2016; Skordos & Papafragou, 2016). These accounts argue that difficulties in accessing necessary linguistic alternatives might explain why children fail to derive implicatures, whether such difficulties are due to a lack of associations between scale mates, a failure to detect which alternatives are contextually relevant, or a lack of working memory capacity to compute the contribution of alternatives while simultaneously considering a sentence’s basic meaning. While most studies in support of the “access to alternatives” view have focused on conditions under which children derive weak vs. strong interpretations of utterances, both of which are available to adults, two recent studies have argued for this account by pointing to an entirely different form of evidence, namely the interpretation of disjunction as conjunction. Specifically, these studies report that, given an utterance like (2a) above, some children conclude that the girl must have both types of fruit. In one study documenting this phenomenon, Singh et al. (2016) tested 4and 5-year-old English-speaking children (N=31) using a modified Truth Value Judgment task (Crain & Thornton, 1998). Surprisingly, they found that children accepted disjunctive statements (e.g., The boy has an apple or a banana) only about 35% of the time when one of the disjuncts was true (henceforth 1-Disjunct-True trials), but 76% of the time when both INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 6 disjuncts were true (henceforth 2-Disjunct-True-trials). In addition, children displayed a similar behavior with disjunction embedded under a universal quantifier (e.g., Every boy has an apple or a banana), accepting 1-Disjunct-True trials about 45% of the time and 2-Disjunct-True trials, 75% of the time. This pattern of responses is particularly surprising when seen from the standard perspective that children often do not derive implicatures at all; if that were the case, they should generally be inclusive and be equally likely to accept disjunction in 1-Disjunct true and 2Disjunct-True trials. Critically, Singh et al. classified children according to their individual response patterns: Four children performed in an adult-like manner, accepting 1-Disjunct-True utterances while rejecting 2-Disjunct-True utterances (henceforth “Exclusive”). Another four children showed the pattern of failure often reported in previous studies, accepting both 1Disjunct-True and 2-Disjunct-True trials (henceforth “Inclusive”). Finally, 21 out of 31 children (or 67%) responded as if or was and, rejecting 1-Disjunct-True utterances while accepting 2Disjunct-True trials (henceforth “Conjunctive”). Adopting the “access to alternatives” account, Singh et al. argue that children in their study arrive at conjunctive interpretations because they lack access to stronger alternative statements 1 Against this hypothesis that children simply think or always means and, Singh and colleagues (2016) point out that children do not derive conjunctive meanings in downward entailing environments, such as when disjunction is embedded under the scope of negation (Gualmini & Crain, 2002; Goro & Akiba, 2004; Jing, Crain & Hsu, 2005), when it occurs in the antecedent of conditionals (Su, 2014), and when it is in the nuclear scope of only, before, not every, etc. (Goro, Minai & Crain, 2005; Jing, Crain & Hsu, 2005; Gualmini & Crain, 2002; Notley, Zhou, Jensen & Crain, 2012; cf. Tieu et al., 2017; Singh et al., 2016, for discussion). INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 7 derived by replacing or with and. Consequently, they are restricted to deriving implicatures from alternatives that are contained within the original assertion – i.e., the individual disjuncts. Also, and critical to their account, Singh et al. adopt the grammatical view of implicature (Fox, 2007; Chierchia, et al., 2009), and propose that children’s disjunctive alternatives are exhaustified before being negated, resulting in multiple exhaustification (for additional discussion of this account, see Crnič, Chemla, & Fox, 2015; Fox & Katzir, 2011; Franke, 2011; Katzir, 2007; Spector, 2016). Specifically, when children hear a disjunctive statement like (3a), they compute alternatives by exhaustifying each separate disjunct in (3b) and (3c), resulting in the statements in (3d) and (3e): (3) a. The girl has an apple or an orange. b. The girl has an apple. c. The girl has an orange. d. The girl has an apple but not an orange (i.e., only an apple). e. The girl has an orange but not an apple (i.e., only an orange). The original disjunctive statement is then strengthened by negating these exhaustified alternatives, resulting in the statements in (4a) and (4b), which, when combined with the original statement result in a conjunctive meaning, in (4c). (4) a. It’s not the case that the girl has only an apple. b. It’s not the case that the girl has only an orange. c. The girl has an apple or an orange (6a), but doesn’t have only an apple, and doesn’t have only an orange (7a & 7b) (i.e., the girl has both an apple and an orange). According to this theory, adults do not derive the implication in (4c) because they have access to the alternative with and – i.e., “The girl has an apple and an orange.” The inclusion of INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 8 this alternative, since it is stronger than the plain disjunctive statement, leads to its negation, and the corresponding inference that the girl does not have both. This inference directly contradicts the inference in (4c). Since contradictory inferences are not permitted by the exhaustification operator, the derivation of (4c) is blocked (see Fox’s 2007 discussion of innocent exclusion for details). Thus, on Singh et al.’s analysis, their study simultaneously supports the idea that access to alternatives limits children’s implicatures, as well as the idea that children’s implicatures can involve multiple iterations of exhaustification. As they note, such an analysis integrates work on acquisition (e.g., Paris 1973; Braine & Rumain 1981; Tieu et al. 2017) with a broader account of multiple exhaustification, which previous studies have used to explain other forms of implicature, including so-called “free choice” inferences (see Fox, 2007; Chierchia et al. 2009; see also Geurts, 2010; Franke 2011; Meyer, forthcoming, for accounts that do not employ multiple exhaustification). The power of this unifying account depends on the reliability of the deve\",\"PeriodicalId\":15055,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Biomedical Semantics\",\"volume\":\"35 1\",\"pages\":\"247-267\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.6000,\"publicationDate\":\"2020-05-07\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"5\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Biomedical Semantics\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"5\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1093/JOS/FFZ022\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"工程技术\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","FirstCategoryId":"5","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1093/JOS/FFZ022","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5

摘要

学龄前儿童通常很难计算涉及分离(或)的标量含义(SI),在这种情况下,他们被要求通过否定更强的替代来加强话语,例如,推断“这个女孩有一个苹果或一个橘子”可能意味着她没有两个。然而,最近的报告令人惊讶地发现,相当一部分儿童将分离解释为结合,得出结论认为女孩必须同时拥有两个水果。根据这些研究,孩子们得出连词阅读不是因为他们有非成人的语义,而是因为他们无法获得更强的标量替代和,并且在计算含义时使用双重耗尽的分离。使用先前研究的刺激模型,我们测试了说英语的学龄前儿童,并重复了许多儿童解释或连词的发现。然而,我们推测,重复这一发现的条件可能在语用上是不恰当的,因此结果不能提供对儿童语义能力的有效测试。我们表明,当在使说话人的意图问题更加清晰的上下文中说出析取语句时,连词阅读几乎完全消失。年龄较大的学龄前儿童和幼儿园儿童经常难以计算涉及量词的标量含义(si),比如一些(Smith, 1980;诺韦克,2001;Papafragou & Musolino, 2003)以及像析取这样的逻辑运算符(Braine & Rumain, 1981;Chierchia et al., 2001)。例如,当呈现一个包含(1a)中类似内容的话语时,许多儿童无法推导出(1c)中的含义。同样,当看到(2a)这样的句子时,许多孩子不能得出(2c)的排他性解释或特征:(1)a.男孩拿了一些香蕉。男孩把所有的香蕉都拿走了。男孩拿了一些,但不是所有的香蕉。这个女孩有一个苹果或一个橘子。这个女孩有一个苹果和一个橘子。这个女孩有一个苹果或一个橘子,但不是两个都有。在大多数情况下,推导标量蕴涵涉及访问通过用另一个更强的标量项(例如,some, or)替换一个标量项(例如,all, and)而生成的更强的替代语句。例如,为了推导出(1a)中包含some的句子的含义,儿童必须访问并否定(1b)中更强的选项。同样,为了推导出(2a)中包含或的句子的含义,儿童必须访问并否定(2b)中更强的选项。在脱节的标准解释中,不这样做应该导致包容性解释,其中听者得出结论,即使女孩既有苹果又有橙子,(2a)中的话语也是可以接受的(Crain & Khlentzos, 2010;Gazdar, 1979;McCawly, 1993;佩尔蒂埃,1977)。对分离现象的解释5儿童的SI障碍被不同地归因于一般的处理限制(Chierchia等人,2001;莱因哈特,2004;Pouscoulous et al., 2007),难以理解实验者的交际目标(Musolino & Papafragou, 2003;Papafragou & Tantalou, 2004),以及对语用错误更宽容的倾向(Katsos & Bishop, 2011)。最近,越来越多的证据开始支持这样一种说法,即关注儿童获得相关语言替代品的机会,这些替代品是推导SI所必需的(Barner et al., 2011;Barner & Bachrach, 2010;Chierchia et al., 2001;Foppolo et al., 2012;Hochstein et al., 2014;Tieu et al., 2016;sk鄂尔多斯& Papafragou, 2016)。这些说法认为,获取必要的语言选择的困难可能解释了为什么儿童无法推导出含义,无论这种困难是由于缺乏尺度伴侣之间的联系,未能检测到哪些选择是上下文相关的,还是缺乏在考虑句子基本含义的同时计算选择的贡献的工作记忆能力。虽然大多数支持“获得替代”观点的研究都集中在儿童对话语的弱和强解释的条件上,这两种情况对成年人来说都是可行的,但最近的两项研究通过指出一种完全不同的证据形式来支持这一说法,即将分离解释为连接。具体来说,这些研究报告说,给出像上面(2a)这样的话语,一些孩子得出结论,女孩肯定吃了两种水果。在一项记录这一现象的研究中,Singh等人(2016)使用修改的真值判断任务(crain&thornton, 1998)测试了4岁和5岁的英语儿童(N=31)。令人惊讶的是,他们发现孩子们接受了析取语句(例如:
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Do Children Interpret 'or' Conjunctively?
Preschoolers often struggle to compute scalar implicatures (SI) involving disjunction (or), in which they are required to strengthen an utterance by negating stronger alternatives, e.g., to infer that, “The girl has an apple or an orange” likely means she doesn’t have both. However, recent reports surprisingly find that a substantial subset of children interpret disjunction as conjunction, concluding instead that the girl must have both fruits. According to these studies, children arrive at conjunctive readings not because they have a non-adult-like semantics, but because they lack access to the stronger scalar alternative and, and employ doubly exhaustified disjuncts when computing implicatures. Using stimuli modeled on previous studies, we test English-speaking preschoolers and replicate the finding that many children interpret or conjunctively. However, we speculate that conditions which replicate this finding may be pragmatically infelicitous, such that results do not offer a valid test of children’s semantic competence. We show that when disjunctive statements are uttered in contexts that render the speaker’s intended question more transparent, conjunctive readings disappear almost entirely. INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 4 Older preschoolers and kindergarteners often struggle to compute scalar implicatures (SIs) involving quantifiers like some (Smith, 1980; Noveck, 2001; Papafragou & Musolino, 2003) and logical operators like disjunction (Braine & Rumain, 1981; Chierchia et al., 2001). For example, when presented with an utterance containing some like the one in (1a), many children fail to derive the implicature in (1c). Similarly, when presented with a sentence like the one in (2a) many children fail to derive an exclusive interpretation of or characterized by (2c): (1) a. The boy took some of the bananas. b. The boy took all of the bananas. c. The boy took some, but not all of the bananas. (2) a. The girl has an apple or an orange. b. The girl has an apple and an orange. c. The girl has an apple or an orange, but not both. On most accounts, deriving a scalar implicature involves accessing a stronger alternative statement that is generated by replacing one scalar term (e.g., some, or) with another, stronger, one (e.g., all, and). For example, to derive an implicature for the sentence containing some in (1a), children must access and negate the stronger alternative in (1b). Likewise, to derive the implicature for the sentence containing or in (2a), children must access and negate the stronger alternative in (2b). On standard accounts of disjunction, a failure to do so should result in an inclusive interpretation, wherein the listener concludes that the utterance in (2a) is acceptable even when the girl has both an apple and an orange (Crain & Khlentzos, 2010; Gazdar, 1979; McCawly, 1993; Pelletier, 1977). INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 5 Children’s difficulties with SI have been variously attributed to general processing limitations (Chierchia et al., 2001; Reinhart, 2004; Pouscoulous et al., 2007), difficulty in understanding the communicative goals of the experimenters (Musolino & Papafragou, 2003; Papafragou & Tantalou, 2004), and a tendency to be more tolerant of pragmatic infelicity (Katsos & Bishop, 2011). More recently, evidence has begun to accumulate in support of an account focusing on children’s access to relevant linguistic alternatives that are necessary to derive an SI (Barner et al., 2011; Barner & Bachrach, 2010; Chierchia et al., 2001; Foppolo et al., 2012; Hochstein et al., 2014; Tieu et al., 2016; Skordos & Papafragou, 2016). These accounts argue that difficulties in accessing necessary linguistic alternatives might explain why children fail to derive implicatures, whether such difficulties are due to a lack of associations between scale mates, a failure to detect which alternatives are contextually relevant, or a lack of working memory capacity to compute the contribution of alternatives while simultaneously considering a sentence’s basic meaning. While most studies in support of the “access to alternatives” view have focused on conditions under which children derive weak vs. strong interpretations of utterances, both of which are available to adults, two recent studies have argued for this account by pointing to an entirely different form of evidence, namely the interpretation of disjunction as conjunction. Specifically, these studies report that, given an utterance like (2a) above, some children conclude that the girl must have both types of fruit. In one study documenting this phenomenon, Singh et al. (2016) tested 4and 5-year-old English-speaking children (N=31) using a modified Truth Value Judgment task (Crain & Thornton, 1998). Surprisingly, they found that children accepted disjunctive statements (e.g., The boy has an apple or a banana) only about 35% of the time when one of the disjuncts was true (henceforth 1-Disjunct-True trials), but 76% of the time when both INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 6 disjuncts were true (henceforth 2-Disjunct-True-trials). In addition, children displayed a similar behavior with disjunction embedded under a universal quantifier (e.g., Every boy has an apple or a banana), accepting 1-Disjunct-True trials about 45% of the time and 2-Disjunct-True trials, 75% of the time. This pattern of responses is particularly surprising when seen from the standard perspective that children often do not derive implicatures at all; if that were the case, they should generally be inclusive and be equally likely to accept disjunction in 1-Disjunct true and 2Disjunct-True trials. Critically, Singh et al. classified children according to their individual response patterns: Four children performed in an adult-like manner, accepting 1-Disjunct-True utterances while rejecting 2-Disjunct-True utterances (henceforth “Exclusive”). Another four children showed the pattern of failure often reported in previous studies, accepting both 1Disjunct-True and 2-Disjunct-True trials (henceforth “Inclusive”). Finally, 21 out of 31 children (or 67%) responded as if or was and, rejecting 1-Disjunct-True utterances while accepting 2Disjunct-True trials (henceforth “Conjunctive”). Adopting the “access to alternatives” account, Singh et al. argue that children in their study arrive at conjunctive interpretations because they lack access to stronger alternative statements 1 Against this hypothesis that children simply think or always means and, Singh and colleagues (2016) point out that children do not derive conjunctive meanings in downward entailing environments, such as when disjunction is embedded under the scope of negation (Gualmini & Crain, 2002; Goro & Akiba, 2004; Jing, Crain & Hsu, 2005), when it occurs in the antecedent of conditionals (Su, 2014), and when it is in the nuclear scope of only, before, not every, etc. (Goro, Minai & Crain, 2005; Jing, Crain & Hsu, 2005; Gualmini & Crain, 2002; Notley, Zhou, Jensen & Crain, 2012; cf. Tieu et al., 2017; Singh et al., 2016, for discussion). INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 7 derived by replacing or with and. Consequently, they are restricted to deriving implicatures from alternatives that are contained within the original assertion – i.e., the individual disjuncts. Also, and critical to their account, Singh et al. adopt the grammatical view of implicature (Fox, 2007; Chierchia, et al., 2009), and propose that children’s disjunctive alternatives are exhaustified before being negated, resulting in multiple exhaustification (for additional discussion of this account, see Crnič, Chemla, & Fox, 2015; Fox & Katzir, 2011; Franke, 2011; Katzir, 2007; Spector, 2016). Specifically, when children hear a disjunctive statement like (3a), they compute alternatives by exhaustifying each separate disjunct in (3b) and (3c), resulting in the statements in (3d) and (3e): (3) a. The girl has an apple or an orange. b. The girl has an apple. c. The girl has an orange. d. The girl has an apple but not an orange (i.e., only an apple). e. The girl has an orange but not an apple (i.e., only an orange). The original disjunctive statement is then strengthened by negating these exhaustified alternatives, resulting in the statements in (4a) and (4b), which, when combined with the original statement result in a conjunctive meaning, in (4c). (4) a. It’s not the case that the girl has only an apple. b. It’s not the case that the girl has only an orange. c. The girl has an apple or an orange (6a), but doesn’t have only an apple, and doesn’t have only an orange (7a & 7b) (i.e., the girl has both an apple and an orange). According to this theory, adults do not derive the implication in (4c) because they have access to the alternative with and – i.e., “The girl has an apple and an orange.” The inclusion of INTERPRETATION OF DISJUNCTION 8 this alternative, since it is stronger than the plain disjunctive statement, leads to its negation, and the corresponding inference that the girl does not have both. This inference directly contradicts the inference in (4c). Since contradictory inferences are not permitted by the exhaustification operator, the derivation of (4c) is blocked (see Fox’s 2007 discussion of innocent exclusion for details). Thus, on Singh et al.’s analysis, their study simultaneously supports the idea that access to alternatives limits children’s implicatures, as well as the idea that children’s implicatures can involve multiple iterations of exhaustification. As they note, such an analysis integrates work on acquisition (e.g., Paris 1973; Braine & Rumain 1981; Tieu et al. 2017) with a broader account of multiple exhaustification, which previous studies have used to explain other forms of implicature, including so-called “free choice” inferences (see Fox, 2007; Chierchia et al. 2009; see also Geurts, 2010; Franke 2011; Meyer, forthcoming, for accounts that do not employ multiple exhaustification). The power of this unifying account depends on the reliability of the deve
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Journal of Biomedical Semantics
Journal of Biomedical Semantics MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY-
CiteScore
4.20
自引率
5.30%
发文量
28
审稿时长
30 weeks
期刊介绍: Journal of Biomedical Semantics addresses issues of semantic enrichment and semantic processing in the biomedical domain. The scope of the journal covers two main areas: Infrastructure for biomedical semantics: focusing on semantic resources and repositories, meta-data management and resource description, knowledge representation and semantic frameworks, the Biomedical Semantic Web, and semantic interoperability. Semantic mining, annotation, and analysis: focusing on approaches and applications of semantic resources; and tools for investigation, reasoning, prediction, and discoveries in biomedicine.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信