理性:它是什么,为什么稀缺,为什么重要

IF 1.7 3区 经济学 Q2 ECONOMICS
Enrico Petracca
{"title":"理性:它是什么,为什么稀缺,为什么重要","authors":"Enrico Petracca","doi":"10.1080/1350178X.2022.2075139","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Periodically, by a rough estimate twice per decade, a new popular book aspires to shake our common understanding of rationality. Since this concept is not only the backbone of normative analysis in the behavioral sciences but also of the way people more generally understand normativity, the stakes are particularly high. Among past successful attempts to rethink rationality are, so to refresh the memory, books of the caliber of Gigerenzer (2007), Kahneman (2011), and more recently Mercier and Sperber (2017). Because of its straightforward title, Rationality, and one enticing part of its subtitle, the promise to tell us What it is, Steven Pinker’s latest work aspires to be one of those ground-breaking books. There are two reasons, however, why readers might resist the temptation to consider Pinker’s book a foundational one. One reason is that in most of its parts it reads like a pamphlet, in which a world-renowned public intellectual attempts to shake the conscience of a world too dramatically lacking in reason and rationality (Pinker dispenses evidence of this masterfully). The public intellectual posture was to be expected, since Pinker has recently been in the vortex of inflamed debates over sensitive societal topics, and this book is in many regards a learned continuation of those debates. Pinker presents himself as a staunch advocate of freedom of speech and critical thinking, seen as requirements for democratic societies whose degree of rationality he deems to depend on a society’s capacity to deal with its ‘taboos’. Because of this posture, the book may risk being underestimated by those looking for a pristine foundational discussion. But another reason not to regard this book as foundational is the fact that Pinker does not present in it a novel idea of rationality. The readership of economists is certainly the most well equipped to understand that. The book’s central part, seven-elevenths of the total, is a superbly accessible guide to the edifice of rationality from the ground floor of logic (chapter 3) up to probability (chapter 4), Bayesian reasoning (chapter 5), rational choice theory (chapter 6), statistical decision theory (chapter 7), game theory (chapter 8), and the distinction between correlation and causation (chapter 9). The other four-elevenths are a demonstration that humans do not master these subjects – let alone apply them correctly to life – and a plea for why we should. This shows that Pinker does not really venture into a quest for the essence of rationality; what rationality is seems uncontroversial from the start: ‘My own position on rationality’, he says more as an adept than as a pioneer, ‘is “I’m for it”’ (p. 36). His true goal is to convince people to embrace rationality, challenge their belief that it is something ‘uncool’ and ‘cerebral’ that would turn one into a ‘nerd’, a ‘wonk’, a ‘geek’, or a ‘brainiac’ (p. 35, italics in original), not to challenge the classical idea of rationality. But even if one might think that the polemicist’s tone and the support of a classical idea of rationality would hinder the book from being epoch-making, it would be a real mistake not to identify a genuine foundational intent in it. To uncover and assess such an intent is devoted the rest of this review. The starting point to understand the novelty of Pinker’s intent is to acknowledge that he is a cognitive psychologist: a cognitive psychologist who accepts the rationality toolbox of logic, probability, and rational choice theory as a normative benchmark. This may immediately remind economists of two other cognitive psychologists, Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky, who believe that humans should measure their rationality against what Pinker is not afraid to call ‘godlike reason’ (p. 320). But unlike Kahneman and Tversky, Pinker is far more optimistic on the descriptive side. He does","PeriodicalId":46507,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Economic Methodology","volume":"57 1","pages":"335 - 339"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7000,"publicationDate":"2022-05-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"24","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Rationality: What it is, why it seems scarce, why it matters\",\"authors\":\"Enrico Petracca\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/1350178X.2022.2075139\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Periodically, by a rough estimate twice per decade, a new popular book aspires to shake our common understanding of rationality. Since this concept is not only the backbone of normative analysis in the behavioral sciences but also of the way people more generally understand normativity, the stakes are particularly high. Among past successful attempts to rethink rationality are, so to refresh the memory, books of the caliber of Gigerenzer (2007), Kahneman (2011), and more recently Mercier and Sperber (2017). Because of its straightforward title, Rationality, and one enticing part of its subtitle, the promise to tell us What it is, Steven Pinker’s latest work aspires to be one of those ground-breaking books. There are two reasons, however, why readers might resist the temptation to consider Pinker’s book a foundational one. One reason is that in most of its parts it reads like a pamphlet, in which a world-renowned public intellectual attempts to shake the conscience of a world too dramatically lacking in reason and rationality (Pinker dispenses evidence of this masterfully). The public intellectual posture was to be expected, since Pinker has recently been in the vortex of inflamed debates over sensitive societal topics, and this book is in many regards a learned continuation of those debates. Pinker presents himself as a staunch advocate of freedom of speech and critical thinking, seen as requirements for democratic societies whose degree of rationality he deems to depend on a society’s capacity to deal with its ‘taboos’. Because of this posture, the book may risk being underestimated by those looking for a pristine foundational discussion. But another reason not to regard this book as foundational is the fact that Pinker does not present in it a novel idea of rationality. The readership of economists is certainly the most well equipped to understand that. The book’s central part, seven-elevenths of the total, is a superbly accessible guide to the edifice of rationality from the ground floor of logic (chapter 3) up to probability (chapter 4), Bayesian reasoning (chapter 5), rational choice theory (chapter 6), statistical decision theory (chapter 7), game theory (chapter 8), and the distinction between correlation and causation (chapter 9). The other four-elevenths are a demonstration that humans do not master these subjects – let alone apply them correctly to life – and a plea for why we should. This shows that Pinker does not really venture into a quest for the essence of rationality; what rationality is seems uncontroversial from the start: ‘My own position on rationality’, he says more as an adept than as a pioneer, ‘is “I’m for it”’ (p. 36). His true goal is to convince people to embrace rationality, challenge their belief that it is something ‘uncool’ and ‘cerebral’ that would turn one into a ‘nerd’, a ‘wonk’, a ‘geek’, or a ‘brainiac’ (p. 35, italics in original), not to challenge the classical idea of rationality. But even if one might think that the polemicist’s tone and the support of a classical idea of rationality would hinder the book from being epoch-making, it would be a real mistake not to identify a genuine foundational intent in it. To uncover and assess such an intent is devoted the rest of this review. The starting point to understand the novelty of Pinker’s intent is to acknowledge that he is a cognitive psychologist: a cognitive psychologist who accepts the rationality toolbox of logic, probability, and rational choice theory as a normative benchmark. This may immediately remind economists of two other cognitive psychologists, Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky, who believe that humans should measure their rationality against what Pinker is not afraid to call ‘godlike reason’ (p. 320). But unlike Kahneman and Tversky, Pinker is far more optimistic on the descriptive side. He does\",\"PeriodicalId\":46507,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Economic Methodology\",\"volume\":\"57 1\",\"pages\":\"335 - 339\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2022-05-13\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"24\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Economic Methodology\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"96\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2022.2075139\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"经济学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q2\",\"JCRName\":\"ECONOMICS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Economic Methodology","FirstCategoryId":"96","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2022.2075139","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"ECONOMICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 24

摘要

定期地,粗略估计每十年两次,一本新的流行书籍渴望动摇我们对理性的共同理解。由于这一概念不仅是行为科学规范分析的支柱,也是人们更普遍地理解规范性的方式,因此风险特别高。为了刷新记忆,在过去成功的重新思考理性的尝试中,有吉igerenzer (2007), Kahneman(2011)以及最近的Mercier和Sperber(2017)的书。因为书名直白,《理性》(Rationality),以及副标题中诱人的部分——承诺告诉我们理性是什么,史蒂文·平克(Steven Pinker)的最新作品有望成为那些开创性的书之一。然而,有两个原因可以解释为什么读者可能会抵制将平克的书视为一本基础著作的诱惑。其中一个原因是,这本书的大部分内容读起来就像一本小册子,一位世界知名的公共知识分子试图动摇一个极度缺乏理性和理性的世界的良知(平克巧妙地提供了这方面的证据)。公众知识分子的姿态是意料之中的,因为平克最近一直处于关于敏感社会话题的激烈辩论的漩涡中,这本书在很多方面都是这些辩论的博学的延续。平克自称是言论自由和批判性思维的坚定倡导者,他认为这是民主社会的必要条件,他认为民主社会的理性程度取决于社会处理“禁忌”的能力。由于这种姿态,这本书可能会被那些寻找原始基础讨论的人低估。但不把这本书视为基础的另一个原因是,平克并没有在书中提出一种新的理性观念。经济学家的读者当然是最能理解这一点的。本书的中心部分,占全书的十一分之七,是一本非常容易理解的理性大厦指南,从逻辑(第3章)到概率论(第4章),贝叶斯推理(第5章),理性选择理论(第6章),统计决策理论(第7章),博弈论(第8章),以及相关性和因果关系之间的区别(第9章)。另外的11分之4则证明了人类并没有掌握这些学科——更不用说把它们正确地应用到生活中了——并恳求我们为什么应该掌握这些学科。这表明,平克并没有真正冒险探索理性的本质;理性是什么似乎从一开始就没有争议:“我自己对理性的立场”,他更像是一个行家而不是一个先驱者,“是‘我支持它’”(第36页)。他的真正目标是说服人们接受理性,挑战他们的信念,即“不酷”和“理智”的东西会把一个人变成“书呆子”、“工作人员”、“极客”或“聪明人”(第35页,原文斜体),而不是挑战理性的经典观念。但是,即使有人可能会认为,辩论家的语气和对古典理性思想的支持会阻碍这本书成为划时代的作品,但如果不找出其中真正的基本意图,那将是一个真正的错误。揭示和评估这样的意图是本文的剩余部分。理解Pinker意图的新颖性的出发点是承认他是一个认知心理学家:一个接受逻辑、概率和理性选择理论作为规范基准的理性工具箱的认知心理学家。这可能会立即让经济学家想起另外两位认知心理学家丹尼尔·卡尼曼(Daniel Kahneman)和阿莫斯·特沃斯基(Amos Tversky),他们认为人类应该用平克毫不畏惧地称之为“上帝般的理性”来衡量自己的理性(第320页)。但与卡尼曼和特沃斯基不同,平克在描述方面要乐观得多。他所做的
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Rationality: What it is, why it seems scarce, why it matters
Periodically, by a rough estimate twice per decade, a new popular book aspires to shake our common understanding of rationality. Since this concept is not only the backbone of normative analysis in the behavioral sciences but also of the way people more generally understand normativity, the stakes are particularly high. Among past successful attempts to rethink rationality are, so to refresh the memory, books of the caliber of Gigerenzer (2007), Kahneman (2011), and more recently Mercier and Sperber (2017). Because of its straightforward title, Rationality, and one enticing part of its subtitle, the promise to tell us What it is, Steven Pinker’s latest work aspires to be one of those ground-breaking books. There are two reasons, however, why readers might resist the temptation to consider Pinker’s book a foundational one. One reason is that in most of its parts it reads like a pamphlet, in which a world-renowned public intellectual attempts to shake the conscience of a world too dramatically lacking in reason and rationality (Pinker dispenses evidence of this masterfully). The public intellectual posture was to be expected, since Pinker has recently been in the vortex of inflamed debates over sensitive societal topics, and this book is in many regards a learned continuation of those debates. Pinker presents himself as a staunch advocate of freedom of speech and critical thinking, seen as requirements for democratic societies whose degree of rationality he deems to depend on a society’s capacity to deal with its ‘taboos’. Because of this posture, the book may risk being underestimated by those looking for a pristine foundational discussion. But another reason not to regard this book as foundational is the fact that Pinker does not present in it a novel idea of rationality. The readership of economists is certainly the most well equipped to understand that. The book’s central part, seven-elevenths of the total, is a superbly accessible guide to the edifice of rationality from the ground floor of logic (chapter 3) up to probability (chapter 4), Bayesian reasoning (chapter 5), rational choice theory (chapter 6), statistical decision theory (chapter 7), game theory (chapter 8), and the distinction between correlation and causation (chapter 9). The other four-elevenths are a demonstration that humans do not master these subjects – let alone apply them correctly to life – and a plea for why we should. This shows that Pinker does not really venture into a quest for the essence of rationality; what rationality is seems uncontroversial from the start: ‘My own position on rationality’, he says more as an adept than as a pioneer, ‘is “I’m for it”’ (p. 36). His true goal is to convince people to embrace rationality, challenge their belief that it is something ‘uncool’ and ‘cerebral’ that would turn one into a ‘nerd’, a ‘wonk’, a ‘geek’, or a ‘brainiac’ (p. 35, italics in original), not to challenge the classical idea of rationality. But even if one might think that the polemicist’s tone and the support of a classical idea of rationality would hinder the book from being epoch-making, it would be a real mistake not to identify a genuine foundational intent in it. To uncover and assess such an intent is devoted the rest of this review. The starting point to understand the novelty of Pinker’s intent is to acknowledge that he is a cognitive psychologist: a cognitive psychologist who accepts the rationality toolbox of logic, probability, and rational choice theory as a normative benchmark. This may immediately remind economists of two other cognitive psychologists, Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky, who believe that humans should measure their rationality against what Pinker is not afraid to call ‘godlike reason’ (p. 320). But unlike Kahneman and Tversky, Pinker is far more optimistic on the descriptive side. He does
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
3.20
自引率
8.30%
发文量
23
期刊介绍: The Journal of Economic Methodology is a valuable forum which publishes the most current and exciting work in the broad field of economic methodology. The Journal of Economic Methodology addresses issues such as: ■Methodological analysis of the theory and practice of contemporary economics ■Analysis of the methodological implications of new developments in economic theory and practice ■The methodological writings and practice of earlier economic theorists (mainstream or heterodox) ■Research in the philosophical foundations of economics ■Studies in the rhetoric, sociology, or economics of economics
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信