冷冻胚胎、意外怀孕和人工子宫:哪些选择在道德上是合法的?

IF 0.1 0 RELIGION
I. Alexander
{"title":"冷冻胚胎、意外怀孕和人工子宫:哪些选择在道德上是合法的?","authors":"I. Alexander","doi":"10.1353/nov.2021.0064","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In a previous article, I defended why embryo adoption is illicit. More precisely, it is the act of arti;cially impregnating a woman that is contrary to the natural moral order and renders the practice an illicit one, and not the “praiseworthy” intention to save a human life. While I do not intend to repeat that argument in detail here, in sum, my reasoning proceeds from ;rst re-examining the underlying rationale that the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (CDF) applies in its 2008 Dignitatis Personae and its 1987 Donum Vitae for other arti;cial reproductive technologies such as in vitro fertilization (IVF), arti;cial insemination, surrogacy, and the transfer of embryos for infertile couples (an embryo adoption of some kind), all of which were condemned in these two documents as either formally “illicit” or “not ethically acceptable.” When moral theologians listen with care and renewed attention to the underlying rationale in these documents, a single common thread emerges: the reality of what I call “conjugal agency,” namely, that licit actions in reproductive bioethics must respect the role of the spouses in being agent causes of procreation and pregnancy and that this agency must be exercised through conjugal union. ?e determining criteria for what constitutes a licit clinical procedure versus an illicit one emerges very clearly in these documents once theologians grasp this logic at its root. When this logic is then applied to the question of embryo adoption, it becomes clear that it is illicit for an agent other than the spouse to impregnate his wife and that, in addition, it is illicit for such impregnation to take place outside of conjugal","PeriodicalId":43446,"journal":{"name":"Nova et Vetera-English Edition","volume":"18 1","pages":"1111 - 1145"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1000,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Frozen Embryos, Unwanted Pregnancies, and Artificial Wombs: Which Options Are Morally Licit?\",\"authors\":\"I. Alexander\",\"doi\":\"10.1353/nov.2021.0064\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"In a previous article, I defended why embryo adoption is illicit. More precisely, it is the act of arti;cially impregnating a woman that is contrary to the natural moral order and renders the practice an illicit one, and not the “praiseworthy” intention to save a human life. While I do not intend to repeat that argument in detail here, in sum, my reasoning proceeds from ;rst re-examining the underlying rationale that the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (CDF) applies in its 2008 Dignitatis Personae and its 1987 Donum Vitae for other arti;cial reproductive technologies such as in vitro fertilization (IVF), arti;cial insemination, surrogacy, and the transfer of embryos for infertile couples (an embryo adoption of some kind), all of which were condemned in these two documents as either formally “illicit” or “not ethically acceptable.” When moral theologians listen with care and renewed attention to the underlying rationale in these documents, a single common thread emerges: the reality of what I call “conjugal agency,” namely, that licit actions in reproductive bioethics must respect the role of the spouses in being agent causes of procreation and pregnancy and that this agency must be exercised through conjugal union. ?e determining criteria for what constitutes a licit clinical procedure versus an illicit one emerges very clearly in these documents once theologians grasp this logic at its root. When this logic is then applied to the question of embryo adoption, it becomes clear that it is illicit for an agent other than the spouse to impregnate his wife and that, in addition, it is illicit for such impregnation to take place outside of conjugal\",\"PeriodicalId\":43446,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Nova et Vetera-English Edition\",\"volume\":\"18 1\",\"pages\":\"1111 - 1145\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.1000,\"publicationDate\":\"2021-12-23\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Nova et Vetera-English Edition\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1353/nov.2021.0064\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"RELIGION\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Nova et Vetera-English Edition","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/nov.2021.0064","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"RELIGION","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

在之前的一篇文章中,我为为什么胚胎收养是非法的进行了辩护。更确切地说,人工使妇女怀孕的行为违背了自然的道德秩序,使这种做法成为非法的,而不是拯救人类生命的“值得称赞”的意图。虽然我不打算在这里详细重复这个论点,但总的来说,我的推理是从以下方面开始的:首先,重新审视信仰教义部(CDF)在其2008年的《人格尊严》(Dignitatis Personae)和1987年的《生命恩赐》(Donum Vitae)中对其他人工生殖技术的基本原理,如体外受精(IVF)、人工授精、代孕和不孕夫妇的胚胎移植(某种形式的胚胎收养)。在这两份文件中,所有这些行为都被谴责为“非法”或“道德上不可接受”。当道德神学家仔细聆听并重新关注这些文件中潜在的基本原理时,一条共同的线索出现了:我称之为“夫妻代理”的现实,即生殖生物伦理学中的合法行为必须尊重配偶作为生育和怀孕的代理原因的角色,这种代理必须通过夫妻结合来行使。一旦神学家从根本上掌握了这个逻辑,确定什么是合法的临床程序与非法的临床程序的标准就会在这些文件中非常清楚地出现。当这一逻辑应用于胚胎收养问题时,很明显,配偶以外的代理人使其妻子怀孕是非法的,此外,在夫妻关系之外进行这种怀孕也是非法的
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Frozen Embryos, Unwanted Pregnancies, and Artificial Wombs: Which Options Are Morally Licit?
In a previous article, I defended why embryo adoption is illicit. More precisely, it is the act of arti;cially impregnating a woman that is contrary to the natural moral order and renders the practice an illicit one, and not the “praiseworthy” intention to save a human life. While I do not intend to repeat that argument in detail here, in sum, my reasoning proceeds from ;rst re-examining the underlying rationale that the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (CDF) applies in its 2008 Dignitatis Personae and its 1987 Donum Vitae for other arti;cial reproductive technologies such as in vitro fertilization (IVF), arti;cial insemination, surrogacy, and the transfer of embryos for infertile couples (an embryo adoption of some kind), all of which were condemned in these two documents as either formally “illicit” or “not ethically acceptable.” When moral theologians listen with care and renewed attention to the underlying rationale in these documents, a single common thread emerges: the reality of what I call “conjugal agency,” namely, that licit actions in reproductive bioethics must respect the role of the spouses in being agent causes of procreation and pregnancy and that this agency must be exercised through conjugal union. ?e determining criteria for what constitutes a licit clinical procedure versus an illicit one emerges very clearly in these documents once theologians grasp this logic at its root. When this logic is then applied to the question of embryo adoption, it becomes clear that it is illicit for an agent other than the spouse to impregnate his wife and that, in addition, it is illicit for such impregnation to take place outside of conjugal
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
50.00%
发文量
23
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信