德沃金的谬误,或语言哲学无法教会我们的关于法律的东西

IF 2.4 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW
Michael S. Green
{"title":"德沃金的谬误,或语言哲学无法教会我们的关于法律的东西","authors":"Michael S. Green","doi":"10.2307/3202369","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Although philosophers of law display an impressive diversity of opinion, they usually agree about one thing: Their discipline is closely connected to the philosophy of language. The extent of agreement on this point can be seen in the recent flood of books and articles exploring the connections between the two fields. In this Essay, I will argue that much of this literature is based upon a mistake. The philosophy of language generally has no jurisprudential consequences. The fact that so many philosophers of law have thought otherwise has seriously hampered progress in the field, and not just because time, effort, and paper have been wasted. Theories about the law have been accepted or rejected for the wrong reasons - on the basis of arguments about language that fail to support or undermine these theories at all. The philosophy of language appears to have jurisprudential consequences because of a mistake, which I will call Dworkin's fallacy in honor of the most famous philosopher of law to have succumbed to it. This Essay will analyze the fallacy and describe its negative effects. In Part I, I will describe an example of a debate in the philosophy of language that has wrongly been thought to have jurisprudential consequences. This debate concerns realism about reference. Can words refer in ways that transcend our current beliefs? For example, can the word law refer to something that people do not currently believe is law? In Part II, I will provide two examples of philosophers of law - Ronald Dworkin and Michael Moore - who misderive jurisprudential conclusions from this debate. In Part III, I will describe a second example of a debate in the philosophy of language that has wrongly been thought to have jurisprudential consequences. This debate, which is inspired by Ludwig Wittgenstein's remarkable discussion of rule-following, concerns the fundamental question: How is it that we can intend to use a word in one way rather than another? How can we make law mean law instead of, say, Nilla Wafers? In Part IV, I will provide two examples of philosophers of law - Dennis Patterson and Margaret Radin - who misderive jurisprudential conclusions from this second debate. Although Dworkin, Moore, Patterson, and Radin agree about little in the philosophies of language and law, Dworkin's fallacy causes each to see a relationship between the two disciplines. Given the pervasiveness of the fallacy, we should be skeptical whenever a philosopher of law relies on the philosophy of language. Chances are, she is discussing issues that are irrelevant to her true concerns. I will end the Essay with a brief discussion of three situations to which Dworkin's fallacy does not apply and in which the philosophy of language has genuine, if limited, relevance for the philosophy of law.","PeriodicalId":47840,"journal":{"name":"Virginia Law Review","volume":"89 1","pages":"1897"},"PeriodicalIF":2.4000,"publicationDate":"2003-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/3202369","citationCount":"19","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Dworkin's Fallacy, or What the Philosophy of Language Can't Teach Us About the Law\",\"authors\":\"Michael S. Green\",\"doi\":\"10.2307/3202369\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Although philosophers of law display an impressive diversity of opinion, they usually agree about one thing: Their discipline is closely connected to the philosophy of language. The extent of agreement on this point can be seen in the recent flood of books and articles exploring the connections between the two fields. In this Essay, I will argue that much of this literature is based upon a mistake. The philosophy of language generally has no jurisprudential consequences. The fact that so many philosophers of law have thought otherwise has seriously hampered progress in the field, and not just because time, effort, and paper have been wasted. Theories about the law have been accepted or rejected for the wrong reasons - on the basis of arguments about language that fail to support or undermine these theories at all. The philosophy of language appears to have jurisprudential consequences because of a mistake, which I will call Dworkin's fallacy in honor of the most famous philosopher of law to have succumbed to it. This Essay will analyze the fallacy and describe its negative effects. In Part I, I will describe an example of a debate in the philosophy of language that has wrongly been thought to have jurisprudential consequences. This debate concerns realism about reference. Can words refer in ways that transcend our current beliefs? For example, can the word law refer to something that people do not currently believe is law? In Part II, I will provide two examples of philosophers of law - Ronald Dworkin and Michael Moore - who misderive jurisprudential conclusions from this debate. In Part III, I will describe a second example of a debate in the philosophy of language that has wrongly been thought to have jurisprudential consequences. This debate, which is inspired by Ludwig Wittgenstein's remarkable discussion of rule-following, concerns the fundamental question: How is it that we can intend to use a word in one way rather than another? How can we make law mean law instead of, say, Nilla Wafers? In Part IV, I will provide two examples of philosophers of law - Dennis Patterson and Margaret Radin - who misderive jurisprudential conclusions from this second debate. Although Dworkin, Moore, Patterson, and Radin agree about little in the philosophies of language and law, Dworkin's fallacy causes each to see a relationship between the two disciplines. Given the pervasiveness of the fallacy, we should be skeptical whenever a philosopher of law relies on the philosophy of language. Chances are, she is discussing issues that are irrelevant to her true concerns. I will end the Essay with a brief discussion of three situations to which Dworkin's fallacy does not apply and in which the philosophy of language has genuine, if limited, relevance for the philosophy of law.\",\"PeriodicalId\":47840,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Virginia Law Review\",\"volume\":\"89 1\",\"pages\":\"1897\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.4000,\"publicationDate\":\"2003-12-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/3202369\",\"citationCount\":\"19\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Virginia Law Review\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"90\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.2307/3202369\",\"RegionNum\":2,\"RegionCategory\":\"社会学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"LAW\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Virginia Law Review","FirstCategoryId":"90","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2307/3202369","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"LAW","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 19

摘要

尽管法律哲学家表现出令人印象深刻的观点多样性,但他们通常在一件事上是一致的:他们的学科与语言哲学密切相关。从最近大量探讨这两个领域之间联系的书籍和文章中可以看出,人们在这一点上的一致程度。在这篇文章中,我将论证这些文献大多是基于一个错误。语言哲学通常没有法理上的结果。如此多的法律哲学家持不同的观点,这一事实严重阻碍了这一领域的进步,这不仅仅是因为浪费了时间、精力和纸张。关于法律的理论因错误的理由而被接受或拒绝——基于对语言的争论,这些争论根本不能支持或破坏这些理论。语言哲学之所以会产生法理学上的后果,是因为一个错误,我将其称为德沃金的谬误,以纪念最著名的法律哲学家德沃金的谬误。本文将分析这一谬论,并描述其负面影响。在第一部分中,我将描述一个语言哲学辩论的例子,该辩论被错误地认为具有法理学后果。这场争论涉及到关于指称的现实主义。词语能以超越我们当前信仰的方式表达吗?例如,law这个词可以指人们目前认为不是法律的东西吗?在第二部分中,我将提供两个法律哲学家的例子——罗纳德·德沃金和迈克尔·摩尔——他们从这场辩论中错误地得出了法理学结论。在第三部分中,我将描述语言哲学辩论的第二个例子,该辩论被错误地认为具有法理学后果。这场辩论受到路德维希·维特根斯坦(Ludwig Wittgenstein)关于规则遵循的杰出讨论的启发,它关注的是一个基本问题:我们是如何打算以一种方式而不是另一种方式使用一个词的?我们怎么能让法律变成真正的法律,而不是,比如说,尼拉薄饼?在第四部分,我将提供两个法律哲学家的例子——丹尼斯·帕特森和玛格丽特·雷丁——他们从第二次辩论中错误地得出了法理学结论。尽管德沃金、摩尔、帕特森和雷丁在语言哲学和法律哲学上几乎没有什么共识,但德沃金的谬论使他们每个人都看到了这两个学科之间的关系。鉴于这种谬论的普遍性,每当法律哲学家依赖于语言哲学时,我们都应该持怀疑态度。很有可能,她正在讨论的问题与她真正关心的问题无关。在这篇文章的最后,我将简要讨论三种情况,其中德沃金的谬论不适用,在这些情况下,语言哲学与法律哲学有着真正的(如果有限的话)相关性。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Dworkin's Fallacy, or What the Philosophy of Language Can't Teach Us About the Law
Although philosophers of law display an impressive diversity of opinion, they usually agree about one thing: Their discipline is closely connected to the philosophy of language. The extent of agreement on this point can be seen in the recent flood of books and articles exploring the connections between the two fields. In this Essay, I will argue that much of this literature is based upon a mistake. The philosophy of language generally has no jurisprudential consequences. The fact that so many philosophers of law have thought otherwise has seriously hampered progress in the field, and not just because time, effort, and paper have been wasted. Theories about the law have been accepted or rejected for the wrong reasons - on the basis of arguments about language that fail to support or undermine these theories at all. The philosophy of language appears to have jurisprudential consequences because of a mistake, which I will call Dworkin's fallacy in honor of the most famous philosopher of law to have succumbed to it. This Essay will analyze the fallacy and describe its negative effects. In Part I, I will describe an example of a debate in the philosophy of language that has wrongly been thought to have jurisprudential consequences. This debate concerns realism about reference. Can words refer in ways that transcend our current beliefs? For example, can the word law refer to something that people do not currently believe is law? In Part II, I will provide two examples of philosophers of law - Ronald Dworkin and Michael Moore - who misderive jurisprudential conclusions from this debate. In Part III, I will describe a second example of a debate in the philosophy of language that has wrongly been thought to have jurisprudential consequences. This debate, which is inspired by Ludwig Wittgenstein's remarkable discussion of rule-following, concerns the fundamental question: How is it that we can intend to use a word in one way rather than another? How can we make law mean law instead of, say, Nilla Wafers? In Part IV, I will provide two examples of philosophers of law - Dennis Patterson and Margaret Radin - who misderive jurisprudential conclusions from this second debate. Although Dworkin, Moore, Patterson, and Radin agree about little in the philosophies of language and law, Dworkin's fallacy causes each to see a relationship between the two disciplines. Given the pervasiveness of the fallacy, we should be skeptical whenever a philosopher of law relies on the philosophy of language. Chances are, she is discussing issues that are irrelevant to her true concerns. I will end the Essay with a brief discussion of three situations to which Dworkin's fallacy does not apply and in which the philosophy of language has genuine, if limited, relevance for the philosophy of law.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.70
自引率
3.80%
发文量
0
期刊介绍: The Virginia Law Review is a journal of general legal scholarship published by the students of the University of Virginia School of Law. The continuing objective of the Virginia Law Review is to publish a professional periodical devoted to legal and law-related issues that can be of use to judges, practitioners, teachers, legislators, students, and others interested in the law. First formally organized on April 23, 1913, the Virginia Law Review today remains one of the most respected and influential student legal periodicals in the country.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信