证据的局限性

D. Black
{"title":"证据的局限性","authors":"D. Black","doi":"10.1353/PBM.1998.0017","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Karl Popper's most distinctive contribution to the episte­ mology of science was his contention (itself an hypothesis) that sound scientific knowledge is based on the develop­ ment of testable hypotheses, that may then be falsified by the new evidence that emerges from the process of testing. His Logik der Forschung (1934) has been both translated1 and elucidated for the general reader2 by Popper himself, and vested with elegance and plausibility by Peter Medawar in Pluto's Republic*. Imaginative hypothesis followed by meticulous testing for concordance with what is already known, or ascertainable by trial (Popper's 'hypotheticodeductive process') is probably closer to the reality of scien­ tific discovery than the alternative model of Baconian induction from raw facts. It is also appealing, in asserting the importance of imagination in science, in contrast to the 'dry-as-dust' stereotype that is all too prevalent among those whose acquaintance with actual scientists is limited. The story of science blazes with what Michael Polanyi called 'passion and controversy\"1. Moreover, Popper's model emphasises the provisional or contingent nature of scientif­ ic knowledge even a Newton awaits his Einstein, and any beautiful theory is vulnerable to an ugly fact. A scientist who embraces hubris is living beyond his intellectual means. Nevertheless, total surrender to the scepticism that is theoretically demanded of the scientist is in itself unwise; there are degrees of probability so high that pragmatically, though not in absolute theory, they carry virtual certainty as Henry Harris puts it: 'I do not believe that it will ever be shown that the blood of animals does not circulate; that anthrax is not caused by a bacterium; that proteins are not chains of amino-acids'5. Of course, these examples are matters of direct observation (once you know how), and not to be confused with the broad paradigms that concern the philosopher of science, and which are subject to radical changes, or 'revolutions'6 at (fortunately) long intervals. Active scientists are in general indifferent to the origin and even the validity of the conceptual framework that they accept and within which they work as Medawar pithily puts it: 'the history of science bores most scientists stiff. A great many highly creative scientists... take it quite for granted, though they are usually too polite or too ashamed to say so, that an interest in the history of science is a sign of failing or of unawakened powers'3. Happily, a flawed framework does not prevent all accretion of knowledge through observation. The Greeks could add to physical science within a framework tom between Leucippus' atoms in a void and the four elements of Empedocles; somewhat","PeriodicalId":76057,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the Royal College of Physicians of London","volume":"32 1","pages":"23 - 26"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2015-01-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1353/PBM.1998.0017","citationCount":"88","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The Limitations of Evidence\",\"authors\":\"D. Black\",\"doi\":\"10.1353/PBM.1998.0017\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Karl Popper's most distinctive contribution to the episte­ mology of science was his contention (itself an hypothesis) that sound scientific knowledge is based on the develop­ ment of testable hypotheses, that may then be falsified by the new evidence that emerges from the process of testing. His Logik der Forschung (1934) has been both translated1 and elucidated for the general reader2 by Popper himself, and vested with elegance and plausibility by Peter Medawar in Pluto's Republic*. Imaginative hypothesis followed by meticulous testing for concordance with what is already known, or ascertainable by trial (Popper's 'hypotheticodeductive process') is probably closer to the reality of scien­ tific discovery than the alternative model of Baconian induction from raw facts. It is also appealing, in asserting the importance of imagination in science, in contrast to the 'dry-as-dust' stereotype that is all too prevalent among those whose acquaintance with actual scientists is limited. The story of science blazes with what Michael Polanyi called 'passion and controversy\\\"1. Moreover, Popper's model emphasises the provisional or contingent nature of scientif­ ic knowledge even a Newton awaits his Einstein, and any beautiful theory is vulnerable to an ugly fact. A scientist who embraces hubris is living beyond his intellectual means. Nevertheless, total surrender to the scepticism that is theoretically demanded of the scientist is in itself unwise; there are degrees of probability so high that pragmatically, though not in absolute theory, they carry virtual certainty as Henry Harris puts it: 'I do not believe that it will ever be shown that the blood of animals does not circulate; that anthrax is not caused by a bacterium; that proteins are not chains of amino-acids'5. Of course, these examples are matters of direct observation (once you know how), and not to be confused with the broad paradigms that concern the philosopher of science, and which are subject to radical changes, or 'revolutions'6 at (fortunately) long intervals. Active scientists are in general indifferent to the origin and even the validity of the conceptual framework that they accept and within which they work as Medawar pithily puts it: 'the history of science bores most scientists stiff. A great many highly creative scientists... take it quite for granted, though they are usually too polite or too ashamed to say so, that an interest in the history of science is a sign of failing or of unawakened powers'3. Happily, a flawed framework does not prevent all accretion of knowledge through observation. The Greeks could add to physical science within a framework tom between Leucippus' atoms in a void and the four elements of Empedocles; somewhat\",\"PeriodicalId\":76057,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of the Royal College of Physicians of London\",\"volume\":\"32 1\",\"pages\":\"23 - 26\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2015-01-07\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1353/PBM.1998.0017\",\"citationCount\":\"88\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of the Royal College of Physicians of London\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1353/PBM.1998.0017\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of the Royal College of Physicians of London","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/PBM.1998.0017","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 88

摘要

卡尔·波普尔对科学认识论最独特的贡献是他的论点(本身就是一个假设),即可靠的科学知识是建立在可检验假设的发展基础上的,而这些假设可能会被检验过程中出现的新证据所证伪。他的《Forschung的逻辑学》(1934)由波普尔亲自为普通读者翻译和阐释,并由彼得·梅达沃在《普路托的理想国》中赋予其优雅和合理性。富有想象力的假设,再经过细致的测试,以与已知的东西保持一致,或者通过试验确定(波普尔的“假设演绎过程”),可能比从原始事实中进行培根归纳的替代模型更接近科学发现的现实。在断言想象力在科学中的重要性方面,它也很有吸引力,这与“像灰尘一样干燥”的刻板印象形成了对比,这种刻板印象在那些与真正的科学家认识有限的人中太普遍了。科学的故事充满了迈克尔·波兰尼所说的“激情与争议”。此外,波普尔的模型强调了科学知识的临时性或偶然性,即使牛顿也在等待他的爱因斯坦,任何美丽的理论都容易受到丑陋事实的影响。狂妄自大的科学家的生活超出了他的智力能力。然而,完全屈服于理论上要求科学家提出的怀疑主义本身就是不明智的;有些可能性的程度是如此之高,以至于在实用上,尽管不是在绝对的理论中,它们实际上具有确定性,正如亨利·哈里斯所说:“我不相信有证据表明动物的血液不循环;炭疽不是由细菌引起的;蛋白质不是氨基酸链。当然,这些例子都是可以直接观察到的(只要你知道如何观察),不要把它们与科学哲学家的广泛范例混淆起来,这些范例每隔很长一段时间(幸好)就会发生根本的变化或“革命”。活跃的科学家通常对他们所接受并在其中工作的概念框架的起源甚至有效性漠不关心,正如梅达沃简洁地指出的那样:“科学史使大多数科学家感到厌烦。”许多极具创造力的科学家……把对科学史感兴趣是一种失败或未觉醒的力量的标志,这是理所当然的,尽管他们通常是出于礼貌或羞于这样说。令人高兴的是,一个有缺陷的框架并不妨碍通过观察来积累知识。希腊人可以在留基伯的“虚空中的原子”和恩培多克勒的“四元素”之间的框架内为物理科学增添新的内容;有些
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The Limitations of Evidence
Karl Popper's most distinctive contribution to the episte­ mology of science was his contention (itself an hypothesis) that sound scientific knowledge is based on the develop­ ment of testable hypotheses, that may then be falsified by the new evidence that emerges from the process of testing. His Logik der Forschung (1934) has been both translated1 and elucidated for the general reader2 by Popper himself, and vested with elegance and plausibility by Peter Medawar in Pluto's Republic*. Imaginative hypothesis followed by meticulous testing for concordance with what is already known, or ascertainable by trial (Popper's 'hypotheticodeductive process') is probably closer to the reality of scien­ tific discovery than the alternative model of Baconian induction from raw facts. It is also appealing, in asserting the importance of imagination in science, in contrast to the 'dry-as-dust' stereotype that is all too prevalent among those whose acquaintance with actual scientists is limited. The story of science blazes with what Michael Polanyi called 'passion and controversy"1. Moreover, Popper's model emphasises the provisional or contingent nature of scientif­ ic knowledge even a Newton awaits his Einstein, and any beautiful theory is vulnerable to an ugly fact. A scientist who embraces hubris is living beyond his intellectual means. Nevertheless, total surrender to the scepticism that is theoretically demanded of the scientist is in itself unwise; there are degrees of probability so high that pragmatically, though not in absolute theory, they carry virtual certainty as Henry Harris puts it: 'I do not believe that it will ever be shown that the blood of animals does not circulate; that anthrax is not caused by a bacterium; that proteins are not chains of amino-acids'5. Of course, these examples are matters of direct observation (once you know how), and not to be confused with the broad paradigms that concern the philosopher of science, and which are subject to radical changes, or 'revolutions'6 at (fortunately) long intervals. Active scientists are in general indifferent to the origin and even the validity of the conceptual framework that they accept and within which they work as Medawar pithily puts it: 'the history of science bores most scientists stiff. A great many highly creative scientists... take it quite for granted, though they are usually too polite or too ashamed to say so, that an interest in the history of science is a sign of failing or of unawakened powers'3. Happily, a flawed framework does not prevent all accretion of knowledge through observation. The Greeks could add to physical science within a framework tom between Leucippus' atoms in a void and the four elements of Empedocles; somewhat
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信