理性选择与政治权力特刊编辑

IF 2.6 Q1 POLITICAL SCIENCE
William Bosworth,
{"title":"理性选择与政治权力特刊编辑","authors":"William Bosworth,","doi":"10.1080/2158379x.2021.1900468","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The literature on power is something of a wormhole between the worlds of political philosophy and political science. It ranges over empirical strategies for measuring power through to the debate surrounding its normative implications. Empirical political scientists engage with Marx’s moral imperatives and normative philosophers pick holes in survey methodology. There are few literatures that are so splendidly cross-disciplinary in nature – and few books that captures it better than Keith Dowding’s Rational Choice and Political Power. The contributions to this special issue, designed to engage with the book’s recently published second edition, all reflect this. From Greg Whitfield’s article on the normative project of public reason, through Pamela Pansardi’s reflections on conceptual analysis, to Jim Johnson’s critique of Dowding’s use of formal modelling for empirical explanation, the issue sports a wide range of perspectives that stand testament to the book’s breadth. While diverse, they all touch on the major challenge Dowding tackles for traversing both the empirical and normative domains: distinguishing what is the case from what one wants it to be. It is easy, for example, to say a political party is powerful when you want the party to be held to account and powerless when you do not. Along these lines, Dowding (2019, p. 173) suggests in the new Postscript that ‘the original idea for RCPP came from my critique of Steven Lukes’s three dimensions of power. I thought the collective action problem could explain everything which he thought required adding dimensions of power’. Workers may not push for legislation in their interest because they are crippled by collective action problems, the critique goes, not because a power elite is controlling them. Marx’s prophecy of a Communist revolution assumes that once the proletariat wakes up to their real interest individual workers will revolt and smash the means of production. But where violence takes effort and in the short term runs the risk of incarceration, it is presuming a lot to think large groups can coordinate in the face of free-riding incentives. While we might rightly want to hold capitalists responsible for their privilege, their power is underlain by the collective action problem faced by the many. Steven Lukes responds in the issue with his article ‘Power and Rational Choice’. He agrees that we do not need to impute the power of outsiders to explain a group’s lack of power, calling it the ‘paranoid fallacy’, and questions ‘just how far [he and Dowding] do part ways’ (Lukes, 2021). There are cases though that do appear to stir rival judgements between the two. One of the more contentious is in what sense sexual or racial bias constitutes an exercise of power. When an individual unconsciously gains from this kind of bias, such as when a male mechanic is judged more authoritative than a female engineer purely because they are male, Dowding would describe the judgement as the male mechanic’s luck that he might then use as a source of power. Lukes argues this would overlook the mechanisms that sustain and reproduce the power structure. When JOURNAL OF POLITICAL POWER 2021, VOL. 14, NO. 2, 277–280 https://doi.org/10.1080/2158379X.2021.1900468","PeriodicalId":45560,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Political Power","volume":"14 1","pages":"277 - 280"},"PeriodicalIF":2.6000,"publicationDate":"2021-05-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/2158379x.2021.1900468","citationCount":"2","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Editorial to special issue on rational choice and political power\",\"authors\":\"William Bosworth,\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/2158379x.2021.1900468\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"The literature on power is something of a wormhole between the worlds of political philosophy and political science. It ranges over empirical strategies for measuring power through to the debate surrounding its normative implications. Empirical political scientists engage with Marx’s moral imperatives and normative philosophers pick holes in survey methodology. There are few literatures that are so splendidly cross-disciplinary in nature – and few books that captures it better than Keith Dowding’s Rational Choice and Political Power. The contributions to this special issue, designed to engage with the book’s recently published second edition, all reflect this. From Greg Whitfield’s article on the normative project of public reason, through Pamela Pansardi’s reflections on conceptual analysis, to Jim Johnson’s critique of Dowding’s use of formal modelling for empirical explanation, the issue sports a wide range of perspectives that stand testament to the book’s breadth. While diverse, they all touch on the major challenge Dowding tackles for traversing both the empirical and normative domains: distinguishing what is the case from what one wants it to be. It is easy, for example, to say a political party is powerful when you want the party to be held to account and powerless when you do not. Along these lines, Dowding (2019, p. 173) suggests in the new Postscript that ‘the original idea for RCPP came from my critique of Steven Lukes’s three dimensions of power. I thought the collective action problem could explain everything which he thought required adding dimensions of power’. Workers may not push for legislation in their interest because they are crippled by collective action problems, the critique goes, not because a power elite is controlling them. Marx’s prophecy of a Communist revolution assumes that once the proletariat wakes up to their real interest individual workers will revolt and smash the means of production. But where violence takes effort and in the short term runs the risk of incarceration, it is presuming a lot to think large groups can coordinate in the face of free-riding incentives. While we might rightly want to hold capitalists responsible for their privilege, their power is underlain by the collective action problem faced by the many. Steven Lukes responds in the issue with his article ‘Power and Rational Choice’. He agrees that we do not need to impute the power of outsiders to explain a group’s lack of power, calling it the ‘paranoid fallacy’, and questions ‘just how far [he and Dowding] do part ways’ (Lukes, 2021). There are cases though that do appear to stir rival judgements between the two. One of the more contentious is in what sense sexual or racial bias constitutes an exercise of power. When an individual unconsciously gains from this kind of bias, such as when a male mechanic is judged more authoritative than a female engineer purely because they are male, Dowding would describe the judgement as the male mechanic’s luck that he might then use as a source of power. Lukes argues this would overlook the mechanisms that sustain and reproduce the power structure. When JOURNAL OF POLITICAL POWER 2021, VOL. 14, NO. 2, 277–280 https://doi.org/10.1080/2158379X.2021.1900468\",\"PeriodicalId\":45560,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Political Power\",\"volume\":\"14 1\",\"pages\":\"277 - 280\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.6000,\"publicationDate\":\"2021-05-04\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/2158379x.2021.1900468\",\"citationCount\":\"2\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Political Power\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/2158379x.2021.1900468\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Political Power","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/2158379x.2021.1900468","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2

摘要

关于权力的文献有点像政治哲学和政治科学世界之间的虫洞。它涵盖了衡量权力的经验策略,一直到围绕其规范含义的辩论。经验政治学家参与了马克思的道德要求,而规范哲学家则在调查方法中挑毛病。很少有文献能在本质上如此出色地跨学科,也很少有书能比基思·道丁的《理性选择与政治权力》更好地抓住这一点。这期特刊旨在与该书最近出版的第二版合作,所有的贡献都反映了这一点。从格雷格·惠特菲尔德(Greg Whitfield)关于公共理性规范项目的文章,到帕梅拉·潘萨迪(Pamela Pansardi)对概念分析的反思,再到吉姆·约翰逊(Jim Johnson)对道丁(Dowding)使用形式建模进行实证解释的批评,这一问题展现了广泛的视角,证明了这本书的广度。虽然它们多种多样,但都涉及到道丁在跨越经验和规范领域时所面临的主要挑战:区分情况和希望的情况。例如,当你希望政党承担责任时,很容易说政党是强大的,而当你不希望政党承担责任时,则很容易说它是无能为力的。沿着这些思路,Dowding(2019,第173页)在新的后记中指出,“RCPP的最初想法来自于我对Steven Lukes的权力三个维度的批判。我认为集体行动问题可以解释他认为需要增加权力维度的一切。批评称,工人们可能不会为了自己的利益而推动立法,因为他们受到集体行动问题的影响,而不是因为权力精英在控制他们。马克思关于共产主义革命的预言假设,一旦无产阶级意识到他们的真正利益,个体工人就会反抗并粉碎生产资料。但是,在暴力需要付出努力,并且在短期内有被监禁的风险的情况下,认为大型团体可以在搭便车的激励措施面前进行协调,这是一种很大的假设。虽然我们可能理所当然地想让资本家为他们的特权负责,但他们的权力是由许多人面临的集体行动问题所决定的。Steven Lukes在他的文章《权力与理性选择》中回应了这个问题。他同意,我们不需要用局外人的力量来解释一个群体的权力不足,称之为“偏执谬论”,并质疑“他和道丁在多大程度上分道扬镳”(Lukes,2021)。不过,也有一些案例似乎确实激起了两人之间的对立判断。其中一个更具争议的问题是,在什么意义上,性或种族偏见构成了权力的行使。当一个人无意识地从这种偏见中获益时,比如当男性机修工纯粹因为是男性而被认为比女性工程师更有权威时,道丁会将这种判断描述为男性机修工的运气,然后他可能会将其作为权力来源。Lukes认为,这将忽视维持和复制权力结构的机制。《2021年政治权力杂志》第14卷第2期,277–280https://doi.org/10.1080/2158379X.2021.1900468
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Editorial to special issue on rational choice and political power
The literature on power is something of a wormhole between the worlds of political philosophy and political science. It ranges over empirical strategies for measuring power through to the debate surrounding its normative implications. Empirical political scientists engage with Marx’s moral imperatives and normative philosophers pick holes in survey methodology. There are few literatures that are so splendidly cross-disciplinary in nature – and few books that captures it better than Keith Dowding’s Rational Choice and Political Power. The contributions to this special issue, designed to engage with the book’s recently published second edition, all reflect this. From Greg Whitfield’s article on the normative project of public reason, through Pamela Pansardi’s reflections on conceptual analysis, to Jim Johnson’s critique of Dowding’s use of formal modelling for empirical explanation, the issue sports a wide range of perspectives that stand testament to the book’s breadth. While diverse, they all touch on the major challenge Dowding tackles for traversing both the empirical and normative domains: distinguishing what is the case from what one wants it to be. It is easy, for example, to say a political party is powerful when you want the party to be held to account and powerless when you do not. Along these lines, Dowding (2019, p. 173) suggests in the new Postscript that ‘the original idea for RCPP came from my critique of Steven Lukes’s three dimensions of power. I thought the collective action problem could explain everything which he thought required adding dimensions of power’. Workers may not push for legislation in their interest because they are crippled by collective action problems, the critique goes, not because a power elite is controlling them. Marx’s prophecy of a Communist revolution assumes that once the proletariat wakes up to their real interest individual workers will revolt and smash the means of production. But where violence takes effort and in the short term runs the risk of incarceration, it is presuming a lot to think large groups can coordinate in the face of free-riding incentives. While we might rightly want to hold capitalists responsible for their privilege, their power is underlain by the collective action problem faced by the many. Steven Lukes responds in the issue with his article ‘Power and Rational Choice’. He agrees that we do not need to impute the power of outsiders to explain a group’s lack of power, calling it the ‘paranoid fallacy’, and questions ‘just how far [he and Dowding] do part ways’ (Lukes, 2021). There are cases though that do appear to stir rival judgements between the two. One of the more contentious is in what sense sexual or racial bias constitutes an exercise of power. When an individual unconsciously gains from this kind of bias, such as when a male mechanic is judged more authoritative than a female engineer purely because they are male, Dowding would describe the judgement as the male mechanic’s luck that he might then use as a source of power. Lukes argues this would overlook the mechanisms that sustain and reproduce the power structure. When JOURNAL OF POLITICAL POWER 2021, VOL. 14, NO. 2, 277–280 https://doi.org/10.1080/2158379X.2021.1900468
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Journal of Political Power
Journal of Political Power POLITICAL SCIENCE-
CiteScore
4.50
自引率
14.30%
发文量
44
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信