黑格尔的世纪:革命时代的异化与认同

Q1 Arts and Humanities
John H. Zammito
{"title":"黑格尔的世纪:革命时代的异化与认同","authors":"John H. Zammito","doi":"10.1080/17496977.2022.2088928","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"historians ought to do research, how archives transform the historian’s character and how he became the model of what a historian is supposed to be (88, 97, 104); and, finally, Georg Waitz’s concern with researching the character of the writers of sources, to find out their moral and epistemic virtues and vices (107–8, 112–13). The question remains whether these historians and their moral and political project are actually “modern”. For, when we look more closely, it is clear that many of these historians focus on “reasonable human beings” (28, 61, 64), and that the “folly of men” could be prevented or mended by means of history. These historians used empirical knowledge to inform and improve human knowledge and morality. In other words, it is about progress of human nature. That is essentially the traditional Enlightened theory of humanity: there is a sharp distinction between an (unreasonable) past and a (reasonable) present; by learning from past errors, progress is achieved; such learning is possible because human nature is capable of learning as long as it is reasonable. In other words, human nature includes reason and therefore the capacity to learn. That is exactly why historicists considered the Enlightened view of history to be generalizing and judgemental and not historical, instead urging historians to refrain from judgement, to focus on the individual context, and most of all to “feel into” the past, while simultaneously becoming aware that the present is a product of the past. Of course, this debate is essentially on the flexibility and adaptability of notions like historicism, professionalization, Enlightenment and modernity, as well as the (dis)agreements on periodization, selection and perspective. Even though Eskildsen seems to employ a rather restricted view of historicism, Enlightenment and modernity, this does not diminish the achievement of his concise yet skilfully written and researched study of the Enlightened foundation of modern German historical scholarship. It is an original addition to the debate about the foundation of historical scholarship, and it contributes particularly to the field of moral and epistemic virtues and its role in Enlightened German historical scholarship.","PeriodicalId":39827,"journal":{"name":"Intellectual History Review","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2022-06-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Hegel’s century: alienation and recognition in a time of revolution\",\"authors\":\"John H. Zammito\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/17496977.2022.2088928\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"historians ought to do research, how archives transform the historian’s character and how he became the model of what a historian is supposed to be (88, 97, 104); and, finally, Georg Waitz’s concern with researching the character of the writers of sources, to find out their moral and epistemic virtues and vices (107–8, 112–13). The question remains whether these historians and their moral and political project are actually “modern”. For, when we look more closely, it is clear that many of these historians focus on “reasonable human beings” (28, 61, 64), and that the “folly of men” could be prevented or mended by means of history. These historians used empirical knowledge to inform and improve human knowledge and morality. In other words, it is about progress of human nature. That is essentially the traditional Enlightened theory of humanity: there is a sharp distinction between an (unreasonable) past and a (reasonable) present; by learning from past errors, progress is achieved; such learning is possible because human nature is capable of learning as long as it is reasonable. In other words, human nature includes reason and therefore the capacity to learn. That is exactly why historicists considered the Enlightened view of history to be generalizing and judgemental and not historical, instead urging historians to refrain from judgement, to focus on the individual context, and most of all to “feel into” the past, while simultaneously becoming aware that the present is a product of the past. Of course, this debate is essentially on the flexibility and adaptability of notions like historicism, professionalization, Enlightenment and modernity, as well as the (dis)agreements on periodization, selection and perspective. Even though Eskildsen seems to employ a rather restricted view of historicism, Enlightenment and modernity, this does not diminish the achievement of his concise yet skilfully written and researched study of the Enlightened foundation of modern German historical scholarship. It is an original addition to the debate about the foundation of historical scholarship, and it contributes particularly to the field of moral and epistemic virtues and its role in Enlightened German historical scholarship.\",\"PeriodicalId\":39827,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Intellectual History Review\",\"volume\":\" \",\"pages\":\"\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2022-06-30\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Intellectual History Review\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/17496977.2022.2088928\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"Arts and Humanities\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Intellectual History Review","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17496977.2022.2088928","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"Arts and Humanities","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Hegel’s century: alienation and recognition in a time of revolution
historians ought to do research, how archives transform the historian’s character and how he became the model of what a historian is supposed to be (88, 97, 104); and, finally, Georg Waitz’s concern with researching the character of the writers of sources, to find out their moral and epistemic virtues and vices (107–8, 112–13). The question remains whether these historians and their moral and political project are actually “modern”. For, when we look more closely, it is clear that many of these historians focus on “reasonable human beings” (28, 61, 64), and that the “folly of men” could be prevented or mended by means of history. These historians used empirical knowledge to inform and improve human knowledge and morality. In other words, it is about progress of human nature. That is essentially the traditional Enlightened theory of humanity: there is a sharp distinction between an (unreasonable) past and a (reasonable) present; by learning from past errors, progress is achieved; such learning is possible because human nature is capable of learning as long as it is reasonable. In other words, human nature includes reason and therefore the capacity to learn. That is exactly why historicists considered the Enlightened view of history to be generalizing and judgemental and not historical, instead urging historians to refrain from judgement, to focus on the individual context, and most of all to “feel into” the past, while simultaneously becoming aware that the present is a product of the past. Of course, this debate is essentially on the flexibility and adaptability of notions like historicism, professionalization, Enlightenment and modernity, as well as the (dis)agreements on periodization, selection and perspective. Even though Eskildsen seems to employ a rather restricted view of historicism, Enlightenment and modernity, this does not diminish the achievement of his concise yet skilfully written and researched study of the Enlightened foundation of modern German historical scholarship. It is an original addition to the debate about the foundation of historical scholarship, and it contributes particularly to the field of moral and epistemic virtues and its role in Enlightened German historical scholarship.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Intellectual History Review
Intellectual History Review Arts and Humanities-History
CiteScore
0.90
自引率
0.00%
发文量
46
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信