{"title":"皮尔斯的思辨语法:作为符号学的逻辑","authors":"A. K. Atkin","doi":"10.1080/01445340.2021.2017112","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Copernican revolution) instantiates the Husserlian principle of going back to the things themselves. Focusing on mathematical notions can shore up two weaknesses of Hartimo’s reading. It provides a better account of mathematicians’ goals, as distinct from their practices, and it can strengthen Hartimo’s pluralistic interpretation of Husserl’s approach. Giving primacy to mathematical notions increases the defensibility of a pluralistic position that is not anti-realistic.","PeriodicalId":55053,"journal":{"name":"History and Philosophy of Logic","volume":"43 1","pages":"398 - 400"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5000,"publicationDate":"2022-01-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Peirce's Speculative Grammar: Logic as Semiotics\",\"authors\":\"A. K. Atkin\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/01445340.2021.2017112\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Copernican revolution) instantiates the Husserlian principle of going back to the things themselves. Focusing on mathematical notions can shore up two weaknesses of Hartimo’s reading. It provides a better account of mathematicians’ goals, as distinct from their practices, and it can strengthen Hartimo’s pluralistic interpretation of Husserl’s approach. Giving primacy to mathematical notions increases the defensibility of a pluralistic position that is not anti-realistic.\",\"PeriodicalId\":55053,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"History and Philosophy of Logic\",\"volume\":\"43 1\",\"pages\":\"398 - 400\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.5000,\"publicationDate\":\"2022-01-09\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"History and Philosophy of Logic\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"98\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/01445340.2021.2017112\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"History and Philosophy of Logic","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/01445340.2021.2017112","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
Copernican revolution) instantiates the Husserlian principle of going back to the things themselves. Focusing on mathematical notions can shore up two weaknesses of Hartimo’s reading. It provides a better account of mathematicians’ goals, as distinct from their practices, and it can strengthen Hartimo’s pluralistic interpretation of Husserl’s approach. Giving primacy to mathematical notions increases the defensibility of a pluralistic position that is not anti-realistic.
期刊介绍:
History and Philosophy of Logic contains articles, notes and book reviews dealing with the history and philosophy of logic. ’Logic’ is understood to be any volume of knowledge which was regarded as logic at the time in question. ’History’ refers back to ancient times and also to work in this century; however, the Editor will not accept articles, including review articles, on very recent work on a topic. ’Philosophy’ refers to broad and general questions: specialist articles which are now classed as ’philosophical logic’ will not be published.
The Editor will consider articles on the relationship between logic and other branches of knowledge, but the component of logic must be substantial. Topics with no temporal specification are to be interpreted both historically and philosophically. Each topic includes its own metalogic where appropriate.