财产与自决

IF 0.4 Q3 LAW
J. Penner
{"title":"财产与自决","authors":"J. Penner","doi":"10.1017/cjlj.2022.13","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The central claim of Hanoch Dagan’s A Liberal Theory of Property is that property law mostly does and should provide alternative property ‘types’ (xii, 6-7) in each ‘sphere’ of property relations (91-96, 104), and that these ‘types’ are “partial functional substitutes” for each other (6-7). Dagan calls this ‘property’s structural pluralism’. So, for example, in the sphere of residential property, types such as freehold estates, residential tenancies, condominiums, co-ops, and common interest communities count as partial functional substitutes. In providing a range of types, property law serves the self-determination1 of individuals, providing them with meaningful choices amongst legal relationships and thereby allowing them better to realise their life-plans than would be the case if a one-size-fits-all approach were taken by the law. So Dagan’s functionalism relates the inputs of different values that self-determining people might choose, such as personhood, community, and utility, in varying degrees, to the outputs of partial functional substitutes (50-58). This book is something of a companion piece to Dagan and Heller’s The Choice Theory of Contracts,2 whose intellectual structure is similar and with which it overlaps in significant respects. Dagan thinks that the cogency of the main claim turns upon a number of other theses, which will be the main focus of this notice. These are (1) Dagan’s characterisation of ‘mainstream liberalism’ and ‘relational justice’; (2) his critique of the ‘Blackstonian’ or ‘dominion’ theory of property; (3) his claim that property is ‘power-conferring’ and that the relation of owners to non-owners is a kind of authority relation; and (4) property’s ‘legitimacy challenge’. My conclusion will be that none of these theses are really relevant to the central claim, and that a person might support the latter without endorsing any of the former. But first we must examine the nature of the central claim.","PeriodicalId":43817,"journal":{"name":"Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence","volume":"35 1","pages":"537 - 558"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4000,"publicationDate":"2022-07-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Property and Self-Determination\",\"authors\":\"J. Penner\",\"doi\":\"10.1017/cjlj.2022.13\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"The central claim of Hanoch Dagan’s A Liberal Theory of Property is that property law mostly does and should provide alternative property ‘types’ (xii, 6-7) in each ‘sphere’ of property relations (91-96, 104), and that these ‘types’ are “partial functional substitutes” for each other (6-7). Dagan calls this ‘property’s structural pluralism’. So, for example, in the sphere of residential property, types such as freehold estates, residential tenancies, condominiums, co-ops, and common interest communities count as partial functional substitutes. In providing a range of types, property law serves the self-determination1 of individuals, providing them with meaningful choices amongst legal relationships and thereby allowing them better to realise their life-plans than would be the case if a one-size-fits-all approach were taken by the law. So Dagan’s functionalism relates the inputs of different values that self-determining people might choose, such as personhood, community, and utility, in varying degrees, to the outputs of partial functional substitutes (50-58). This book is something of a companion piece to Dagan and Heller’s The Choice Theory of Contracts,2 whose intellectual structure is similar and with which it overlaps in significant respects. Dagan thinks that the cogency of the main claim turns upon a number of other theses, which will be the main focus of this notice. These are (1) Dagan’s characterisation of ‘mainstream liberalism’ and ‘relational justice’; (2) his critique of the ‘Blackstonian’ or ‘dominion’ theory of property; (3) his claim that property is ‘power-conferring’ and that the relation of owners to non-owners is a kind of authority relation; and (4) property’s ‘legitimacy challenge’. My conclusion will be that none of these theses are really relevant to the central claim, and that a person might support the latter without endorsing any of the former. But first we must examine the nature of the central claim.\",\"PeriodicalId\":43817,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence\",\"volume\":\"35 1\",\"pages\":\"537 - 558\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.4000,\"publicationDate\":\"2022-07-05\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1017/cjlj.2022.13\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"LAW\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/cjlj.2022.13","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"LAW","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

Hanoch Dagan的《自由主义财产论》的核心主张是,财产法在财产关系的每个“领域”(91-96,104)中基本上都提供了并且应该提供可选择的财产“类型”(xii, 6-7),并且这些“类型”是彼此的“部分功能替代品”(6-7)。达甘称之为“财产的结构多元化”。因此,举例来说,在住宅物业领域,永久业权地产、住宅租赁、共管公寓、合作公寓和共同利益社区等类型都可以算作部分功能替代品。财产法提供了一系列类型,为个人的自决服务,为他们在法律关系中提供有意义的选择,从而使他们能够更好地实现自己的人生计划,而不是法律采取一刀切的方法。因此,达甘的功能主义将自我决定的人可能选择的不同价值的输入,如人格、社区和效用,在不同程度上与部分功能替代品的输出联系起来(50-58)。这本书是达根和海勒的《契约选择理论》的配套作品,后者的知识结构相似,并在许多方面重叠。达甘认为,主要主张的说服力取决于其他一些论点,这将是本通知的主要焦点。这些是(1)达根对“主流自由主义”和“关系正义”的描述;(2)他对“布莱克斯通”或“统治”财产理论的批判;(3)他主张财产是“赋予权力的”,所有者与非所有者的关系是一种权力关系;(4)财产的“合法性挑战”。我的结论是,这些论点都没有真正与中心主张相关,一个人可能会支持后者,而不赞同前者。但首先我们必须检查中心主张的性质。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Property and Self-Determination
The central claim of Hanoch Dagan’s A Liberal Theory of Property is that property law mostly does and should provide alternative property ‘types’ (xii, 6-7) in each ‘sphere’ of property relations (91-96, 104), and that these ‘types’ are “partial functional substitutes” for each other (6-7). Dagan calls this ‘property’s structural pluralism’. So, for example, in the sphere of residential property, types such as freehold estates, residential tenancies, condominiums, co-ops, and common interest communities count as partial functional substitutes. In providing a range of types, property law serves the self-determination1 of individuals, providing them with meaningful choices amongst legal relationships and thereby allowing them better to realise their life-plans than would be the case if a one-size-fits-all approach were taken by the law. So Dagan’s functionalism relates the inputs of different values that self-determining people might choose, such as personhood, community, and utility, in varying degrees, to the outputs of partial functional substitutes (50-58). This book is something of a companion piece to Dagan and Heller’s The Choice Theory of Contracts,2 whose intellectual structure is similar and with which it overlaps in significant respects. Dagan thinks that the cogency of the main claim turns upon a number of other theses, which will be the main focus of this notice. These are (1) Dagan’s characterisation of ‘mainstream liberalism’ and ‘relational justice’; (2) his critique of the ‘Blackstonian’ or ‘dominion’ theory of property; (3) his claim that property is ‘power-conferring’ and that the relation of owners to non-owners is a kind of authority relation; and (4) property’s ‘legitimacy challenge’. My conclusion will be that none of these theses are really relevant to the central claim, and that a person might support the latter without endorsing any of the former. But first we must examine the nature of the central claim.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.10
自引率
16.70%
发文量
32
期刊介绍: The Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence serves as a forum for special and general jurisprudence and legal philosophy. It publishes articles that address the nature of law, that engage in philosophical analysis or criticism of legal doctrine, that examine the form and nature of legal or judicial reasoning, that investigate issues concerning the ethical aspects of legal practice, and that study (from a philosophical perspective) concrete legal issues facing contemporary society. The journal does not use case notes, nor does it publish articles focussing on issues particular to the laws of a single nation. The Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence is published on behalf of the Faculty of Law, Western University.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信