孤独的异见者

IF 0.1 Q3 HISTORY
Charles J. Cooper
{"title":"孤独的异见者","authors":"Charles J. Cooper","doi":"10.1111/jsch.12269","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The dissenting opinion plays a paradoxical role in American law. On the one hand, it weakens what Judge Learned Hand, an avowed opponent of dissenting opinions, called the “monolithic solidarity on which the authority of a bench of judges so largely depends.”1 On the other hand, according to Justice William J. Brennan, a vigorous defender of the dissenting opinion, it “safeguards the integrity of the judicial decisionmaking process by keeping the majority accountable for the rationale and consequences of its decision.”2 The paradox of the dissenting opinion is inherent in the unique nature of the judiciary among the three branches of the federal government. Unlike the legislative and executive branches, the judiciary does not command obedience by the threat of force but instead seeks to persuade through the power of reason. Our courts do not act; they speak. Like the prophets of the Old Testament, the power of the Court is in its voice. This has been recognized since the very beginning. It is why Hamilton emphasized, in that famous passage in Federalist 78, that the judiciary “may truly be said to have neither force nor will, but merely judgment.”3 And it is surely why Chief Justice John Marshall— in words no less familiar to lawyers than Hamilton’s—justified the function of judicial review by his emphatic reference to the “duty of the judicial department to say”— to say—“what the law is.”4 This is what Professor Alexander Bickel called “the mystic function” of the Supreme Court. When it speaks through its opinions, it provides the symbolic “voice of the Constitution,” by articulating and defending “a coherent body of principled rules” of law that stand above ordinary politics.5 Indeed, when the Court is interpreting and enforcing the rules established by the Constitution—the supreme law of the land—its rulings even stand above, and can nullify, ordinary laws enacted through the democratic process established in Article I. So, it is critical that the Court get it right. Because the Court’s authority is ultimately dependent on its ability, through its written opinions, to win the assent of the political branches of government, we can see why the Court’s credibility is at its zenith when the Court speaks as one. The Marshallian postulate that it is the “duty of","PeriodicalId":41873,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Supreme Court History","volume":"46 2","pages":"229-240"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1000,"publicationDate":"2021-10-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The Lone Dissenter\",\"authors\":\"Charles J. Cooper\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/jsch.12269\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"The dissenting opinion plays a paradoxical role in American law. On the one hand, it weakens what Judge Learned Hand, an avowed opponent of dissenting opinions, called the “monolithic solidarity on which the authority of a bench of judges so largely depends.”1 On the other hand, according to Justice William J. Brennan, a vigorous defender of the dissenting opinion, it “safeguards the integrity of the judicial decisionmaking process by keeping the majority accountable for the rationale and consequences of its decision.”2 The paradox of the dissenting opinion is inherent in the unique nature of the judiciary among the three branches of the federal government. Unlike the legislative and executive branches, the judiciary does not command obedience by the threat of force but instead seeks to persuade through the power of reason. Our courts do not act; they speak. Like the prophets of the Old Testament, the power of the Court is in its voice. This has been recognized since the very beginning. It is why Hamilton emphasized, in that famous passage in Federalist 78, that the judiciary “may truly be said to have neither force nor will, but merely judgment.”3 And it is surely why Chief Justice John Marshall— in words no less familiar to lawyers than Hamilton’s—justified the function of judicial review by his emphatic reference to the “duty of the judicial department to say”— to say—“what the law is.”4 This is what Professor Alexander Bickel called “the mystic function” of the Supreme Court. When it speaks through its opinions, it provides the symbolic “voice of the Constitution,” by articulating and defending “a coherent body of principled rules” of law that stand above ordinary politics.5 Indeed, when the Court is interpreting and enforcing the rules established by the Constitution—the supreme law of the land—its rulings even stand above, and can nullify, ordinary laws enacted through the democratic process established in Article I. So, it is critical that the Court get it right. Because the Court’s authority is ultimately dependent on its ability, through its written opinions, to win the assent of the political branches of government, we can see why the Court’s credibility is at its zenith when the Court speaks as one. The Marshallian postulate that it is the “duty of\",\"PeriodicalId\":41873,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Supreme Court History\",\"volume\":\"46 2\",\"pages\":\"229-240\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.1000,\"publicationDate\":\"2021-10-13\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Supreme Court History\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jsch.12269\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"HISTORY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Supreme Court History","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jsch.12269","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"HISTORY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

反对意见在美国法律中扮演着自相矛盾的角色。一方面,它削弱了公开反对不同意见的法官Learned hand所说的“法官团的权威在很大程度上依赖的整体团结”。1另一方面,反对意见的有力捍卫者William J.Brennan法官表示,它“通过让多数人对其决定的理由和后果负责,来保障司法决策过程的完整性。”2反对意见的悖论是联邦政府三个部门中司法机构的独特性质所固有的。与立法和行政部门不同,司法部门不会通过武力威胁来命令服从,而是通过理性的力量来寻求说服。我们的法院不采取行动;他们说话。就像《旧约》中的先知一样,法庭的力量在于它的声音。这一点从一开始就得到了承认。这就是为什么汉密尔顿在《联邦党人78》中的那篇著名文章中强调,司法机构“可以说既没有力量也没有意愿,而只是判断。”。“3当然,这就是为什么首席大法官约翰·马歇尔(John Marshall)——用律师们不亚于汉密尔顿(Hamilton)的话来说——通过强调“司法部门有义务说”——说——“法律是什么”来证明司法审查的职能是正当的。4这就是亚历山大·比克尔(Alexander Bickel)教授所说的最高法院的“神秘职能”。当法院通过自己的意见发表意见时,它通过阐明和捍卫凌驾于普通政治之上的“一套连贯的原则性规则”,提供了象征性的“宪法之声”,通过第一条规定的民主程序制定的普通法律。因此,法院正确处理这一问题至关重要。因为最高法院的权威最终取决于其通过书面意见赢得政府政治部门同意的能力,我们可以理解为什么当最高法院作为一个整体发言时,最高法院的信誉达到了顶峰。马歇尔假定这是“
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。

The Lone Dissenter

The Lone Dissenter
The dissenting opinion plays a paradoxical role in American law. On the one hand, it weakens what Judge Learned Hand, an avowed opponent of dissenting opinions, called the “monolithic solidarity on which the authority of a bench of judges so largely depends.”1 On the other hand, according to Justice William J. Brennan, a vigorous defender of the dissenting opinion, it “safeguards the integrity of the judicial decisionmaking process by keeping the majority accountable for the rationale and consequences of its decision.”2 The paradox of the dissenting opinion is inherent in the unique nature of the judiciary among the three branches of the federal government. Unlike the legislative and executive branches, the judiciary does not command obedience by the threat of force but instead seeks to persuade through the power of reason. Our courts do not act; they speak. Like the prophets of the Old Testament, the power of the Court is in its voice. This has been recognized since the very beginning. It is why Hamilton emphasized, in that famous passage in Federalist 78, that the judiciary “may truly be said to have neither force nor will, but merely judgment.”3 And it is surely why Chief Justice John Marshall— in words no less familiar to lawyers than Hamilton’s—justified the function of judicial review by his emphatic reference to the “duty of the judicial department to say”— to say—“what the law is.”4 This is what Professor Alexander Bickel called “the mystic function” of the Supreme Court. When it speaks through its opinions, it provides the symbolic “voice of the Constitution,” by articulating and defending “a coherent body of principled rules” of law that stand above ordinary politics.5 Indeed, when the Court is interpreting and enforcing the rules established by the Constitution—the supreme law of the land—its rulings even stand above, and can nullify, ordinary laws enacted through the democratic process established in Article I. So, it is critical that the Court get it right. Because the Court’s authority is ultimately dependent on its ability, through its written opinions, to win the assent of the political branches of government, we can see why the Court’s credibility is at its zenith when the Court speaks as one. The Marshallian postulate that it is the “duty of
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
22
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信