Woojin Chung, Kevin Dorst, M. Mandelkern, Salvador Mascarenhas
{"title":"连词谬误:确认还是相关?","authors":"Woojin Chung, Kevin Dorst, M. Mandelkern, Salvador Mascarenhas","doi":"10.1080/13546783.2024.2374545","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The conjunction fallacy is the well-documented empirical finding that subjects sometimes rate a conjunction A & B as more probable than one of its conjuncts, A . Most explanations appeal in some way to the fact that B has a high probability. But Tentori et al. (2013) have recently challenged such approaches, reporting experiments which find that (1) when B is confirmed by relevant evidence despite having low probability, the fallacy is common, and (2) when B has a high probability but has not been confirmed by relevant evidence, the fallacy is less common. They conclude that degree of confirmation, rather than probability, is the central determinant of the conjunction fallacy. In this paper, we address a confound in these experiments: Tentori et al. (2013) failed to control for the fact that their (1)-situations make B conversationally relevant, while their (2)-situations do not. Hence their results are consistent with the hypothesis that con-versationally relevant high probability is an important driver of the conjunction fallacy. Inspired by recent theoretical work that appeals to conversational relevance to explain the conjunction fallacy, we report on two experiments that control for this issue by making B relevant without changing its degree of probability or confirmation. We find that doing so increases the rate of the fallacy in (2)-situations, and leads to comparable fallacy-rates as (1)-situations. This suggests that (non-probabilistic) conversational relevance indeed plays a role in the conjunction fallacy, and paves the way toward further work on the interplay between relevance and confirmation.","PeriodicalId":243948,"journal":{"name":"Thinking & Reasoning","volume":"7 7","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2024-07-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The conjunction fallacy: confirmation or relevance?\",\"authors\":\"Woojin Chung, Kevin Dorst, M. Mandelkern, Salvador Mascarenhas\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/13546783.2024.2374545\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"The conjunction fallacy is the well-documented empirical finding that subjects sometimes rate a conjunction A & B as more probable than one of its conjuncts, A . Most explanations appeal in some way to the fact that B has a high probability. But Tentori et al. (2013) have recently challenged such approaches, reporting experiments which find that (1) when B is confirmed by relevant evidence despite having low probability, the fallacy is common, and (2) when B has a high probability but has not been confirmed by relevant evidence, the fallacy is less common. They conclude that degree of confirmation, rather than probability, is the central determinant of the conjunction fallacy. In this paper, we address a confound in these experiments: Tentori et al. (2013) failed to control for the fact that their (1)-situations make B conversationally relevant, while their (2)-situations do not. Hence their results are consistent with the hypothesis that con-versationally relevant high probability is an important driver of the conjunction fallacy. Inspired by recent theoretical work that appeals to conversational relevance to explain the conjunction fallacy, we report on two experiments that control for this issue by making B relevant without changing its degree of probability or confirmation. We find that doing so increases the rate of the fallacy in (2)-situations, and leads to comparable fallacy-rates as (1)-situations. This suggests that (non-probabilistic) conversational relevance indeed plays a role in the conjunction fallacy, and paves the way toward further work on the interplay between relevance and confirmation.\",\"PeriodicalId\":243948,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Thinking & Reasoning\",\"volume\":\"7 7\",\"pages\":\"\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-07-12\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Thinking & Reasoning\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/13546783.2024.2374545\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Thinking & Reasoning","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/13546783.2024.2374545","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
摘要
连词谬误是有据可查的经验发现,受试者有时会认为连词 A 和 B 的可能性大于其中一个连词 A 的可能性。 大多数解释都以某种方式诉诸于 B 可能性高这一事实。但 Tentori 等人(2013 年)最近对这种方法提出了质疑,他们报告的实验发现:(1) 当 B 的可能性较低但却被相关证据证实时,谬误很常见;(2) 当 B 的可能性较高但却未被相关证据证实时,谬误不太常见。他们的结论是,连词谬误的核心决定因素是确认程度,而不是概率。在本文中,我们将讨论这些实验中的一个混淆因素:Tentori 等人(2013 年)未能控制以下事实:他们的(1)情境使 B 具有会话相关性,而他们的(2)情境则没有。因此,他们的结果与会话相关的高概率是连词谬误的重要驱动因素这一假设是一致的。最近有理论研究呼吁用会话相关性来解释连词谬误,受此启发,我们报告了两个实验,通过在不改变 B 的概率或确认程度的情况下使其相关来控制这个问题。我们发现,这样做会增加(2)情境中的谬误率,并导致与(1)情境相当的谬误率。这表明(非概率性的)会话相关性确实在连词谬误中起了作用,并为进一步研究相关性和确认之间的相互作用铺平了道路。
The conjunction fallacy: confirmation or relevance?
The conjunction fallacy is the well-documented empirical finding that subjects sometimes rate a conjunction A & B as more probable than one of its conjuncts, A . Most explanations appeal in some way to the fact that B has a high probability. But Tentori et al. (2013) have recently challenged such approaches, reporting experiments which find that (1) when B is confirmed by relevant evidence despite having low probability, the fallacy is common, and (2) when B has a high probability but has not been confirmed by relevant evidence, the fallacy is less common. They conclude that degree of confirmation, rather than probability, is the central determinant of the conjunction fallacy. In this paper, we address a confound in these experiments: Tentori et al. (2013) failed to control for the fact that their (1)-situations make B conversationally relevant, while their (2)-situations do not. Hence their results are consistent with the hypothesis that con-versationally relevant high probability is an important driver of the conjunction fallacy. Inspired by recent theoretical work that appeals to conversational relevance to explain the conjunction fallacy, we report on two experiments that control for this issue by making B relevant without changing its degree of probability or confirmation. We find that doing so increases the rate of the fallacy in (2)-situations, and leads to comparable fallacy-rates as (1)-situations. This suggests that (non-probabilistic) conversational relevance indeed plays a role in the conjunction fallacy, and paves the way toward further work on the interplay between relevance and confirmation.