{"title":"哪些 \"本体论悖论 \"是悖论?","authors":"Neil Tennant","doi":"10.1007/s10992-024-09761-8","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>We begin with a brief explanation of our proof-theoretic criterion of paradoxicality—its motivation, its methods, and its results so far. It is a proof-theoretic account of paradoxicality that can be given in addition to, or alongside, the more familiar semantic account of Kripke. It is a question for further research whether the two accounts agree in general on what is to count as a paradox. It is also a question for further research whether and, if so, how the so-called Ekman problem bears on the investigations here of the intensional paradoxes. Possible exceptions to the proof-theoretic criterion are Prior’s Theorem and Russell’s Paradox of Propositions—the two best-known ‘intensional’ paradoxes. We have not yet addressed them. We do so here. The results are encouraging. §1 studies Prior’s Theorem. In the literature on the paradoxes of intensionality, it does not enjoy rigorous formal proof of a <i>Gentzenian</i> kind—the kind that lends itself to proof-theoretic analysis of recondite features that might escape the attention of logicians using non-Gentzenian systems of logic. We make good that lack, both to render the criterion applicable to the formal proof, and to see whether the criterion gets it right. Prior’s Theorem is a theorem in an <i>unfree</i>, classical, quantified propositional logic. But if one were to insist that the logic employed be <i>free</i>, then Prior’s Theorem would not be a <i>theorem</i> at all. Its proof would have an <i>undischarged assumption</i>—the ‘existential presupposition’ that the proposition <span>\\(\\forall p(Qp\\!\\rightarrow \\!\\lnot p)\\)</span> exists. Call this proposition <span>\\(\\vartheta \\)</span>. §2 focuses on <span>\\(\\vartheta \\)</span>. We analyse a Priorean <i>reductio</i> of <span>\\(\\vartheta \\)</span> along with the possibilitate <span>\\(\\Diamond \\forall q(Qq\\!\\leftrightarrow \\!(\\vartheta \\!\\leftrightarrow \\! q))\\)</span>. The attempted <i>reductio</i> of this premise-pair, which is constructive, cannot be brought into normal form. The criterion says we have not straightforward inconsistency, but rather genuine paradoxicality. §3 turns to problems engendered by the proposition <span>\\(\\exists p(Qp\\wedge \\lnot p)\\)</span> (call it <span>\\(\\eta \\)</span>) for the similar possibilitate <span>\\(\\Diamond \\forall q(Qq\\!\\leftrightarrow \\!(\\eta \\!\\leftrightarrow \\! q))\\)</span>. The attempted disproof of this premise-pair—again, a constructive one—cannot succeed. It cannot be brought into normal form. The criterion says the premise-pair is a genuine paradox. In §4 we show how Russell’s Paradox of Propositions, like the Priorean intensional paradoxes, is to be classified as a genuine paradox by the proof-theoretic criterion of paradoxicality.</p>","PeriodicalId":51526,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC","volume":"36 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2024-06-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Which ‘Intensional Paradoxes’ are Paradoxes?\",\"authors\":\"Neil Tennant\",\"doi\":\"10.1007/s10992-024-09761-8\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>We begin with a brief explanation of our proof-theoretic criterion of paradoxicality—its motivation, its methods, and its results so far. It is a proof-theoretic account of paradoxicality that can be given in addition to, or alongside, the more familiar semantic account of Kripke. It is a question for further research whether the two accounts agree in general on what is to count as a paradox. It is also a question for further research whether and, if so, how the so-called Ekman problem bears on the investigations here of the intensional paradoxes. Possible exceptions to the proof-theoretic criterion are Prior’s Theorem and Russell’s Paradox of Propositions—the two best-known ‘intensional’ paradoxes. We have not yet addressed them. We do so here. The results are encouraging. §1 studies Prior’s Theorem. In the literature on the paradoxes of intensionality, it does not enjoy rigorous formal proof of a <i>Gentzenian</i> kind—the kind that lends itself to proof-theoretic analysis of recondite features that might escape the attention of logicians using non-Gentzenian systems of logic. We make good that lack, both to render the criterion applicable to the formal proof, and to see whether the criterion gets it right. Prior’s Theorem is a theorem in an <i>unfree</i>, classical, quantified propositional logic. But if one were to insist that the logic employed be <i>free</i>, then Prior’s Theorem would not be a <i>theorem</i> at all. Its proof would have an <i>undischarged assumption</i>—the ‘existential presupposition’ that the proposition <span>\\\\(\\\\forall p(Qp\\\\!\\\\rightarrow \\\\!\\\\lnot p)\\\\)</span> exists. Call this proposition <span>\\\\(\\\\vartheta \\\\)</span>. §2 focuses on <span>\\\\(\\\\vartheta \\\\)</span>. We analyse a Priorean <i>reductio</i> of <span>\\\\(\\\\vartheta \\\\)</span> along with the possibilitate <span>\\\\(\\\\Diamond \\\\forall q(Qq\\\\!\\\\leftrightarrow \\\\!(\\\\vartheta \\\\!\\\\leftrightarrow \\\\! q))\\\\)</span>. The attempted <i>reductio</i> of this premise-pair, which is constructive, cannot be brought into normal form. The criterion says we have not straightforward inconsistency, but rather genuine paradoxicality. §3 turns to problems engendered by the proposition <span>\\\\(\\\\exists p(Qp\\\\wedge \\\\lnot p)\\\\)</span> (call it <span>\\\\(\\\\eta \\\\)</span>) for the similar possibilitate <span>\\\\(\\\\Diamond \\\\forall q(Qq\\\\!\\\\leftrightarrow \\\\!(\\\\eta \\\\!\\\\leftrightarrow \\\\! q))\\\\)</span>. The attempted disproof of this premise-pair—again, a constructive one—cannot succeed. It cannot be brought into normal form. The criterion says the premise-pair is a genuine paradox. In §4 we show how Russell’s Paradox of Propositions, like the Priorean intensional paradoxes, is to be classified as a genuine paradox by the proof-theoretic criterion of paradoxicality.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51526,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC\",\"volume\":\"36 1\",\"pages\":\"\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-06-19\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-024-09761-8\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-024-09761-8","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
We begin with a brief explanation of our proof-theoretic criterion of paradoxicality—its motivation, its methods, and its results so far. It is a proof-theoretic account of paradoxicality that can be given in addition to, or alongside, the more familiar semantic account of Kripke. It is a question for further research whether the two accounts agree in general on what is to count as a paradox. It is also a question for further research whether and, if so, how the so-called Ekman problem bears on the investigations here of the intensional paradoxes. Possible exceptions to the proof-theoretic criterion are Prior’s Theorem and Russell’s Paradox of Propositions—the two best-known ‘intensional’ paradoxes. We have not yet addressed them. We do so here. The results are encouraging. §1 studies Prior’s Theorem. In the literature on the paradoxes of intensionality, it does not enjoy rigorous formal proof of a Gentzenian kind—the kind that lends itself to proof-theoretic analysis of recondite features that might escape the attention of logicians using non-Gentzenian systems of logic. We make good that lack, both to render the criterion applicable to the formal proof, and to see whether the criterion gets it right. Prior’s Theorem is a theorem in an unfree, classical, quantified propositional logic. But if one were to insist that the logic employed be free, then Prior’s Theorem would not be a theorem at all. Its proof would have an undischarged assumption—the ‘existential presupposition’ that the proposition \(\forall p(Qp\!\rightarrow \!\lnot p)\) exists. Call this proposition \(\vartheta \). §2 focuses on \(\vartheta \). We analyse a Priorean reductio of \(\vartheta \) along with the possibilitate \(\Diamond \forall q(Qq\!\leftrightarrow \!(\vartheta \!\leftrightarrow \! q))\). The attempted reductio of this premise-pair, which is constructive, cannot be brought into normal form. The criterion says we have not straightforward inconsistency, but rather genuine paradoxicality. §3 turns to problems engendered by the proposition \(\exists p(Qp\wedge \lnot p)\) (call it \(\eta \)) for the similar possibilitate \(\Diamond \forall q(Qq\!\leftrightarrow \!(\eta \!\leftrightarrow \! q))\). The attempted disproof of this premise-pair—again, a constructive one—cannot succeed. It cannot be brought into normal form. The criterion says the premise-pair is a genuine paradox. In §4 we show how Russell’s Paradox of Propositions, like the Priorean intensional paradoxes, is to be classified as a genuine paradox by the proof-theoretic criterion of paradoxicality.
期刊介绍:
The Journal of Philosophical Logic aims to provide a forum for work at the crossroads of philosophy and logic, old and new, with contributions ranging from conceptual to technical. Accordingly, the Journal invites papers in all of the traditional areas of philosophical logic, including but not limited to: various versions of modal, temporal, epistemic, and deontic logic; constructive logics; relevance and other sub-classical logics; many-valued logics; logics of conditionals; quantum logic; decision theory, inductive logic, logics of belief change, and formal epistemology; defeasible and nonmonotonic logics; formal philosophy of language; vagueness; and theories of truth and validity. In addition to publishing papers on philosophical logic in this familiar sense of the term, the Journal also invites papers on extensions of logic to new areas of application, and on the philosophical issues to which these give rise. The Journal places a special emphasis on the applications of philosophical logic in other disciplines, not only in mathematics and the natural sciences but also, for example, in computer science, artificial intelligence, cognitive science, linguistics, jurisprudence, and the social sciences, such as economics, sociology, and political science.