不服从与公共理性的要求

IF 2.9 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS
Sameer Bajaj
{"title":"不服从与公共理性的要求","authors":"Sameer Bajaj","doi":"10.1111/jopp.12309","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Political liberals argue that democratic citizens have a duty of public reason to ensure that important laws are justified by reasons fellow citizens can accept given their own moral and philosophical beliefs.1 In any real-world democracy, many will fail to comply with this duty. Most people have never heard of public reason, and many who have heard of it reject it. This raises an important question about the demands of public reason: is there ever a duty to ensure that laws are justifiable to those who are not willing to reciprocate? Most political liberals answer “no”—the duty of public reason is owed only to those who are themselves willing to comply.2 This reflects a more general view that has wide currency in democratic thought: individuals ought to moderate their political activity to accommodate disagreement with others, but only when others are willing to reciprocate. Many think, for example, that individuals ought to seek middle-ground policy compromises, but only with those who are willing to compromise. The prevailing view among political liberals is that the duty of public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance in this way. As Andrew Lister asks, “How could it be reasonable to ask me not to count a reason I think true and relevant on the basis that you reject it, if you are not likewise willing to exercise restraint with respect to reasons that you think true but which I reject?”.3 My aim in this article is to answer this question and, in doing so, to rethink the demands of public reason in the face of noncompliance. I argue that there is a wide range of political contexts in which citizens have duties to comply with public reason for the sake of others regardless of whether they reciprocate. This helps lay foundations for a non-ideal theory of political liberalism that gives public reason a more inclusive and morally significant role in the practice of democratic politics. In Section I, I examine what I take to be the strongest argument for the prevailing view that public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance. The civic friendship argument grounds the duty of public reason in the valuable communal relation that citizens realize when they reciprocally comply for the sake of one another. Because unreciprocated compliance with public reason lacks mutuality, it undermines rather than promotes relational equality. When individuals bear the “moral cost” of excluding what they take to be true reasons without demanding reciprocation from others, they allow themselves to be treated as subordinates.4 In Section II, I argue that the civic friendship argument misses an important truth about relational inequality—that whether unreciprocated sacrifice generates subordination depends on background features of the relationship in question, including the motivations of the parties and the history of their relationship. I identify two general political contexts—one with background equality and the other with inequality—in which unreciprocated compliance with public reason promotes rather than undermines egalitarian relationships. When citizens are committed to maintaining a fair overall balance of cooperative sacrifice, unreciprocated compliance with public reason can display a valuable form of respect without subordinating compliers. And in contexts with background oppression, complying with public reason without demanding reciprocation can help repair political relationships to a footing of equality and restore bonds of trust. I illustrate the reparative value of public reason by examining the case of caste-based injustice in India. In ordinary political contexts, then, citizens can have duties to comply with public reason without demanding reciprocation. Acknowledging such duties, I argue in Sections III and IV, helps reconceptualize the role of public reason in non-ideal contexts. If the duty of public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance, it will have only a marginal political role in democracies characterized by substantial noncompliance and injustice. The view I defend gives public reason a broader and more inclusive role in promoting the ideal of an egalitarian community. This does not mean that political liberals must abandon the idea that civic friendship has special value. Rather, civic friendship is best understood as a relational ideal that citizens of pluralistic democracies should strive to realize in the long-run. Liberals have traditionally sought to justify liberal rights and institutions by appeal to a wider view of comprehensive moral or philosophical truth. Mill, for example, defends equal liberties by appeal to a theory of human flourishing that rests on an individualistic understanding of human nature.5 Political liberals believe that comprehensive views of human nature and the good of the sort to which Mill appeals cannot serve as a proper basis for the public justification of a liberal regime. This is because individuals reasoning freely and in good faith will inevitably disagree about such matters. This “fact of reasonable pluralism” ensures that no comprehensive doctrine can provide a mutually acceptable justification for liberal institutions.6 Why does it matter that citizens can accept the public justification of their political regime? Political liberals answer that the principle of public reason requires important laws7 to be justified by reasons that all reasonable citizens can accept given their own moral perspectives. Rawlsians identify the set of mutually acceptable public reasons in terms of a “family” of “political” conceptions of justice that affirm and give priority to basic liberal rights, opportunities, and distributive entitlements.8 Political conceptions are “freestanding” of comprehensive doctrines—they are built up from liberal values implicit in the political cultures of democracies without relying on comprehensive religious, ethical, or philosophical claims.9 The principle of public reason implies an individual moral duty of public reason, which requires citizens and officials to be willing to justify their political activity by appeal to a political conception of justice.10 The prevailing view among political liberals is that citizens must comply with public reason only for the sake of those who are willing to reciprocally comply.11 This implies that only citizens willing to comply properly belong to the justificatory constituency of “reasonable” citizens to whom the duty of public reason is owed.12 It is not immediately obvious why this view is correct. Not all moral duties are conditional on reciprocal compliance in this way. Consider duties of beneficence to help prevent harm to third parties in dire need. If I am walking by a pond with a drowning person whom I can save at reasonable cost, I plausibly have a duty to do so regardless of whether they would be willing to save me. Why not think that we can owe duties of public reason to those who aren't willing to reciprocate? Political liberals have done surprisingly little to answer this question. The view that public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance is often assumed without argument. However, advocates of the civic friendship account of public reason have developed what I think is the most promising argument for the view in the literature. The civic friendship argument grounds the duty of public reason in the communal relation of mutual respect that citizens realize when they reciprocally comply for the sake of one another.13 Andrew Lister understands the relevant form of respect in terms of “non-alienation”—unless laws are mutually justifiable, some will see their terms of political association “as being animated by purposes they find fundamentally alien.”14 R. J. Leland appeals to the value of mutual “non-imposition”. Imposition occurs when we seek to advance others' interests in ways that “substitut[e] [our] own judgments about what's good for recipients' judgments\". This disrespects those we intend to help.15 Civic friends avoid the alienating imposition of cooperative terms by ensuring that each can accept the justification of democratic decisions from their own moral perspectives.16 Lister and Leland disagree about the level of societal compliance required for the duty of public reason to become binding. Lister defends a bilateral account—we always have a duty to justify decisions to every person who is willing to justify decisions to us.17 Leland defends a multilateral account—the duty of public reason is binding only if a significant proportion of citizens comply.18 This debate concerns the background conditions required for the duty of public reason to arise. I am addressing a different question: to whom is the duty of public reason owed when it does arise? In particular, why accept the prevailing view that the duty is owed only to those who are willing to comply with the duty? The civic friendship argument supports two answers. First, because unreciprocated compliance with public reason cannot realize civic friendship; it is morally pointless and cannot be justified. From the standpoint of one's comprehensive doctrine, Lister argues, compliance with public reason comes at a “moral cost”—it requires forgoing the pursuit of what one takes to be true justice for the sake of ensuring a mutually justifiable political order.19 This cost could be justified only if compliance produces a significant moral benefit. But unreciprocated compliance produces no such benefit, the argument goes, since only reciprocal compliance with public reason realizes the value of civic friendship. Lister suggests a different rationale for the view that public reason is conditional on reciprocal compliance when he argues that “[r]efusing to comply with a duty to someone who I know would not reciprocate involves affirming my own dignity”.20 The point can be understood in terms of the ideal of relational equality. Social inequality often arises in relationships when one party allows their willingness to sacrifice their interests to be exploited by others to advance theirs. It is sometimes argued that individuals have an interest in being able to appeal to the full range of their moral convictions when deliberating about matters of great political importance. Public reason requires citizens to bracket their fundamental convictions for the sake of ensuring a mutually justifiable political order.21 When X bears this cost for Y but Y is not willing to reciprocate, Y displays a “failure of recognition” towards X.22 And by allowing themselves to unilaterally bear this cost, X displays a failure of recognition towards themselves. In what follows, I respond to both of these arguments by identifying two ordinary political contexts—one with background equality and the other with background inequality—in which unreciprocated compliance with public reason serves important values while maintaining and promoting egalitarian democratic relationships. As an initial point, it is important to observe that particular instances of unreciprocated cooperative sacrifice do not always generate subordination. Whether they do so depends on contingent features of the relationship in question, including the attitudes of the parties and the history of their relationship. When parties commit to a fair overall balance of sacrifice, they need not engage in in-kind reciprocation of every sacrifice to maintain equality in their relationship. If two friends settle on a routine whereby one always shops for groceries, this need not create any relational subordination if the other friend makes sufficiently many other sorts of sacrifices. Moreover, when the balance of cooperative burdens in a relationship is unfair, beneficiaries can help restore relational equality by sacrificing without demanding reciprocation. If partner B consistently sacrifices their projects for the sake of partner A, A need not problematically subordinate themselves by now making sacrifices without demanding reciprocation. Rather, they can help restore relational equality by repaying their debt of sacrifice and recognizing the equal importance of B's interests. As we've seen, subordination can arise in relationships when individuals allow their willingness to sacrifice their interests to be exploited by others. But noncompliance with public reason is not always or even generally exploitative in this way. Some might fail to comply because they have never heard of political liberalism or the duty of public reason. Some might sincerely reject political liberalism in good faith. Perhaps they would willingly comply if they believed that the duty of public reason existed, but they sincerely believe it doesn't exist. Given the burdens of judgement, we should expect that many people will find the best arguments for political liberalism unpersuasive.23 Those who don't comply with public reason might still give equal weight to the interests of those who comply. They might affirm a comprehensive conception of justice that distributes the benefits and burdens of social cooperation in a fair and impartial way. And they may also be willing to comply with egalitarian laws that others advance through fair democratic procedures, and to cooperate on respectful terms in the democratic process. In such contexts, unreciprocated compliance with public reason need not subordinate compliers. Perhaps they make a particular sort of unreciprocated sacrifice, but noncompliers display a more general willingness to do their fair shares of the overall sacrifice required to relate as equals. To help illustrate the point, consider an idealized democratic society with a high degree of background equality and respectful cooperation: Jordania. Jordania is a democratic community with two large political parties, the Lakers and the Heat. The Lakers accept the duty of public reason. They believe that non-alienation is valuable in both its unreciprocated and reciprocated forms. They include all citizens of Jordania—including the Heat—in the justificatory constituency. The Heat do not comply with public reason. This is not because they want the benefits of being included in the justificatory constituency by the Lakers without bearing the costs of compliance. They simply do not find the best arguments for Rawlsian political liberalism persuasive after careful consideration. They instead appeal to their diverse comprehensive doctrines to justify a political platform that guarantees for all citizens a robust and fair set of primary goods. Jordania has fair and free elections. The Lakers more frequently hold a parliamentary majority because they have broader support among the citizenry. As a consequence, the laws more closely reflect the Lakers' platform than the Heat's platform. The Heat willingly do their fair shares of the sacrifices required by these laws and respectfully cooperate with the Lakers to solve collective problems. There is no pattern of oppression or injustice between the Lakers and Heat; one-off injustices are minor and swiftly remedied. An advocate of the civic friendship argument might concede that unreciprocated compliance with public reason does not create relational inequality in this case, but argue that it is nonetheless morally pointless because unreciprocated compliance cannot realize civic friendship. However, I think the best version of political liberalism acknowledges that individuals have an interest in non-alienation that stands alongside their interest in standing in relations of reciprocal non-alienation. Suppose we ask: why does mutual respect in politics require that we reciprocally justify political decisions to one another? There is generally no problematic lack of respect when individuals do not justify their choice of profession or life partner in terms of reasons others can accept. Why is democratic decision-making different? The most plausible sort of answer appeals to some general feature of democratic politics—for example, that it is coercive,24 that it involves public claims to authority,25 or that democratic power is the collective power of free and equal citizens26—in virtue of which mutual respect demands mutual non-alienation. And this feature of democratic politics will imply that citizens have an independent interest in non-alienation whether or not they comply with public reason. Individuals are subject to the state's use of coercive power and claims to authority even if they don't accept public reason. In this sense, I agree with David Enoch that considerations of reciprocity cannot lie at the “most fundamental moral level” of public reason.27 We can add some clarity by drawing two distinctions concerning cooperative reciprocity. The first distinction is between reciprocity of compliance and reciprocity of benefits. Reciprocity of compliance exists when individuals comply with norms out of a motivation to comply provided others do the same. Reciprocity of benefits exists when norms ensure, as Rawls puts it, that “all who are engaged in cooperation and who do their part as the rules and procedure require, are to benefit in an appropriate way as assessed by a suitable benchmark of comparison.”28 Reciprocity of compliance and reciprocity of benefits can come apart—there can be reciprocal compliance with norms that do not ensure fair mutual benefit and unreciprocated compliance with norms that do ensure fair mutual benefit. The second distinction is between local reciprocity and global reciprocity. Local reciprocity exists when there is reciprocity (of compliance or benefits) with respect to a particular norm. Global reciprocity exists when there is reciprocity (of compliance or benefits) with all norms of a given system. Reciprocity can be more or less global; individuals can reciprocally comply with greater or fewer norms and norms can do a better or worse job of ensuring fair mutual benefit. In Jordania, the Heat are not committed to local reciprocal compliance with the duty of public reason—the Lakers comply while the Heat do not. But the Heat display an effective commitment to global reciprocity of compliance and benefits. In such contexts, unreciprocated compliance with public reason need not subordinate compliers. Of course, real-world democracies have enduring legacies of injustice and oppression. Tommie Shelby argues that victims of systemic injustice are not bound by civic obligations, such as the duty to obey the law. Civic obligations are conditional on global reciprocity of benefits; when a cooperative scheme fails to distribute benefits and burdens in a reasonably just way, victims do not have a civic duty to obey the rules of the scheme. Drawing on Shelby, R. J. Leland argues that victims of injustice are not bound by the demands of civic friendship, including the duty of public reason.29 This is because they can reasonably conclude that fellow citizens do not take their civic interests seriously. And we cannot relate as civic friends with those who don't take our civic interests seriously. Notice what follows if we combine this conclusion with the view that public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance. Victims of injustice are not bound by the duty of public reason because fellow citizens don't treat them as equal partners in a fair cooperative scheme. So, victims must go above and beyond the call of duty to be included in the justificatory constituency and secure the good of non-alienation. By contrast, fellow citizens are properly included in the justificatory constituency simply by doing their duty. This seems unfair to victims of injustice. Leland suggests a response to this worry in passing, though he does not develop it at any length. Although unreciprocated compliance with public reason cannot constitute civic friendship, the response goes, it can promote civic friendship in the future. Extending fair cooperative terms that victims of injustice can accept from their own perspectives facilitate a kind of “reconciliation”. After reconciliation has been achieved through “an extended demonstration of concern over time”, victims of injustice will be bound by the full range of their civic obligations, including the duty of public reason.30 This is valuable because it is necessary for realizing civic friendship. Leland never clarifies in his brief remarks what he means by “reconciliation” or how public reason helps to promote it. One interpretation is that public reason can help repair political relationships damaged by injustice and oppression.31 I think that there is something right about this idea, and I develop a version of it below. However, any attempt to develop the idea within a civic friendship framework faces two problems. First, the civic friendship account seems unable to explain why unreciprocated compliance with public reason can help repair democratic relationships. The most natural explanation is that justifying laws in terms that victims of injustice can accept displays a valuable form of respect. However, the asymmetrical form of respect involved in complying with public reason without demanding reciprocation cannot be explained in terms of civic friendship, which is constituted by the symmetrical respect of reciprocal compliance. A second problem with Leland's account is that it grounds the reparative value of public reason in the value of realizing civic friendship in the future. But the eventual realization of civic friendship seems at most an ancillary reason to care about repairing relationships damaged by serious injustice. The more important reason is that we owe it as a matter of basic respect to affirm the equal standing of those who have been oppressed. Suppose that majorities can reliably predict that victims will not eventually accept the hand of civic friendship and comply with public reason in the future. They still have an urgent duty to repair their political relationship to a footing of equality and trust. If the use of public reason can help do so, this can ground a reparative duty of public reason. If public reason is grounded in its reparative value, its demands are not properly thought to be conditional on reciprocal compliance. Reparative duties are unidirectional and, plausibly, unilaterally binding. They are unidirectional in the sense that if X wrongs Y, X must perform reparative actions for Y (for example, apologize) that Y need not perform for X. Moreover, they are unilaterally binding in the sense that X must perform reparative actions regardless of whether they have assurance that Y would do the same if their positions were reversed. We must take responsibility for remedying the wrongs we have committed, even if we do not have assurance that those we have wronged would do the same for us in the (possibly hypothetical) world in which they wrong us. This can ground a duty to comply with public reason without demanding reciprocation. I have argued that the civic friendship account has difficulty answering two questions about the reparative value of public reason. First, why think that public reason can be used to repair relationships damaged by injustice? In the next subsection, I argue that the use of public reason facilitates a higher-order recognition of the equal standing of victims of injustice. Second, why is repairing relationships through public reason valuable? Leland answers that it helps promote civic friendship through reciprocal compliance in the future. I argue that moral repair through public reason is intrinsically valuable regardless of whether it eventually leads to reciprocal compliance or not. Democratic citizens stand in a distinctive relationship as co-sovereigns and co-subjects of their laws. They are co-sovereigns at least in the minimal sense that they have equal shares of political power—equal voting and other democratic rights—to determine which laws are made and implemented (or which representatives make and implement them). Like Rawls and many others, I assume that citizens have a duty to use their share of political power to promote just institutions and oppose unjust institutions.32 Citizens' duties of justice as co-sovereigns correspond to their vulnerability as co-subjects.33 In a democracy, we depend on others to ensure that laws and institutions treat us as free and equal members of a fair cooperative scheme. Unless enough fellow citizens vote and advocate for just laws and representatives, we may be subject to a basic structure that fails to give us the rights, entitlements, and opportunities we are owed as free and equal. This vulnerability is heightened by the fact that closed borders, limited economic opportunities, and language barriers make it excessively costly for most individuals to exit their states. Most people cannot easily escape the confines of an unjust basic structure. Political majorities commit a serious wrong when they use democratic power to exploit the vulnerability of minorities to advance their own interests. A paradigm example is persistent majority tyranny. This occurs when majorities use democratic institutions to persistently impose unjust cooperative terms on political minorities, often based on race, gender, class, sexual orientation, caste, or creed. I examine the case of caste-based tyranny below. Majority tyranny is wrong for many reasons. It is wrong in part because it results in substantively unjust institutions. But it is also an intrinsically problematic form of relational subordination—members of majorities and minorities do not relate as equal co-sovereigns and co-subjects, but as rulers and ruled-over. Consciousness of this subordination is likely to be experienced as oppressive by victims and to damage self-respect and bonds of trust. Individuals are active participants in majority tyranny when they vote and advocate for unjust laws, and they are mere beneficiaries when they do not vote for such laws but benefit from them. I will use the more general term “beneficiaries” to refer to both groups, and the term “victims” to refer to those who are subject to majority tyranny. Beneficiaries have a duty to oppose the effects of majority tyranny in a way that repairs their democratic relationships with victims. Importantly, the task of repairing a relationship introduces a set of demands oriented towards recognizing the equal standing of those who have suffered wrongdoing. Public reason can play an important role in this reparative task. It does not replace the need for corrective measures that guarantee victims a fair share of rights, opportunities, and resources, or for appropriate restorative procedures such as trials or commissions that hold wrongdoers to account. The use of public reason helps repair relationships through the public justification of such measures. It does so by facilitating a higher-order recognition of the equal standing of victims of injustice. Higher-order recognition is X's recognition that Y recognizes X's equal standing in their relationship.34 Establishing higher-order recognition is often an important element repairing relationships after wrongdoing. Persistent mistreatment generates a justified perception on the part of victims that they have, and are viewed as having, a subordinate moral status. After this damaging failure of recognition, establishing relational equality requires that victims can agree from their own perspectives that wrongdoers recognize their equal standing.35 This partly explains why reparative gestures such as apologies must be sincerely and freely accepted to have their full reparative effect.36 Higher-order recognition can be contrasted with the mere lower-order recognition that occurs when Y recognizes X's equal standing according to Y's moral standards but not X's standards. Wrongdoers might believe that they treat victims as equals, but if their moral beliefs are fundamentally alien or at odds with victims' beliefs about moral equality, victims might be unable to agree that they are respected as equals. Moral repair remains incomplete in an important sense. The use of public reason recognizes victims' equal standing, and promotes victims' recognition that they are so recognized, in two ways. First, it opposes the continued political alienation of victims. Part of what makes majority tyranny wrong is that it imposes institutions that political minorities cannot see as congruent with their own values and self-respect. Majorities have a strong reason to establish relational equality by combating the political alienation they have created and benefited from. The use of public reason does so by ensuring that important decisions are justified in terms of liberal values and principles victims can accept from their own moral perspectives. Second, the use of public reason promotes higher-order recognition of the equal weight of victims' interests in the distribution of primary goods. Majority tyranny entrenches an unfair and exploitative basic structure. Ensuring that the distribution of cooperative benefits and burdens is justifiable in terms of public reasons victims can accept promotes their recognition that majorities recognize their equality. If there is a mere modus vivendi on cooperative terms based on the balance of political power, there is no adequate assurance that majorities won't engage in further tyranny once their political position is more favourable. Moral repair is best promoted when victims can accept the entire public justification for democratic decisions, including the underlying values, principles, and intuitions that justify the decisions. This provides a reason to include victims of injustice in the justificatory constituency of public reason. Justice as fairness, understood as a political conception of justice, provides an argument from moral equality—the original position argument—that individuals with different comprehensive doctrines can accept. Given these considerations, I think the reparative value of public reason","PeriodicalId":47624,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Political Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Noncompliance and the Demands of Public Reason\",\"authors\":\"Sameer Bajaj\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/jopp.12309\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Political liberals argue that democratic citizens have a duty of public reason to ensure that important laws are justified by reasons fellow citizens can accept given their own moral and philosophical beliefs.1 In any real-world democracy, many will fail to comply with this duty. Most people have never heard of public reason, and many who have heard of it reject it. This raises an important question about the demands of public reason: is there ever a duty to ensure that laws are justifiable to those who are not willing to reciprocate? Most political liberals answer “no”—the duty of public reason is owed only to those who are themselves willing to comply.2 This reflects a more general view that has wide currency in democratic thought: individuals ought to moderate their political activity to accommodate disagreement with others, but only when others are willing to reciprocate. Many think, for example, that individuals ought to seek middle-ground policy compromises, but only with those who are willing to compromise. The prevailing view among political liberals is that the duty of public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance in this way. As Andrew Lister asks, “How could it be reasonable to ask me not to count a reason I think true and relevant on the basis that you reject it, if you are not likewise willing to exercise restraint with respect to reasons that you think true but which I reject?”.3 My aim in this article is to answer this question and, in doing so, to rethink the demands of public reason in the face of noncompliance. I argue that there is a wide range of political contexts in which citizens have duties to comply with public reason for the sake of others regardless of whether they reciprocate. This helps lay foundations for a non-ideal theory of political liberalism that gives public reason a more inclusive and morally significant role in the practice of democratic politics. In Section I, I examine what I take to be the strongest argument for the prevailing view that public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance. The civic friendship argument grounds the duty of public reason in the valuable communal relation that citizens realize when they reciprocally comply for the sake of one another. Because unreciprocated compliance with public reason lacks mutuality, it undermines rather than promotes relational equality. When individuals bear the “moral cost” of excluding what they take to be true reasons without demanding reciprocation from others, they allow themselves to be treated as subordinates.4 In Section II, I argue that the civic friendship argument misses an important truth about relational inequality—that whether unreciprocated sacrifice generates subordination depends on background features of the relationship in question, including the motivations of the parties and the history of their relationship. I identify two general political contexts—one with background equality and the other with inequality—in which unreciprocated compliance with public reason promotes rather than undermines egalitarian relationships. When citizens are committed to maintaining a fair overall balance of cooperative sacrifice, unreciprocated compliance with public reason can display a valuable form of respect without subordinating compliers. And in contexts with background oppression, complying with public reason without demanding reciprocation can help repair political relationships to a footing of equality and restore bonds of trust. I illustrate the reparative value of public reason by examining the case of caste-based injustice in India. In ordinary political contexts, then, citizens can have duties to comply with public reason without demanding reciprocation. Acknowledging such duties, I argue in Sections III and IV, helps reconceptualize the role of public reason in non-ideal contexts. If the duty of public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance, it will have only a marginal political role in democracies characterized by substantial noncompliance and injustice. The view I defend gives public reason a broader and more inclusive role in promoting the ideal of an egalitarian community. This does not mean that political liberals must abandon the idea that civic friendship has special value. Rather, civic friendship is best understood as a relational ideal that citizens of pluralistic democracies should strive to realize in the long-run. Liberals have traditionally sought to justify liberal rights and institutions by appeal to a wider view of comprehensive moral or philosophical truth. Mill, for example, defends equal liberties by appeal to a theory of human flourishing that rests on an individualistic understanding of human nature.5 Political liberals believe that comprehensive views of human nature and the good of the sort to which Mill appeals cannot serve as a proper basis for the public justification of a liberal regime. This is because individuals reasoning freely and in good faith will inevitably disagree about such matters. This “fact of reasonable pluralism” ensures that no comprehensive doctrine can provide a mutually acceptable justification for liberal institutions.6 Why does it matter that citizens can accept the public justification of their political regime? Political liberals answer that the principle of public reason requires important laws7 to be justified by reasons that all reasonable citizens can accept given their own moral perspectives. Rawlsians identify the set of mutually acceptable public reasons in terms of a “family” of “political” conceptions of justice that affirm and give priority to basic liberal rights, opportunities, and distributive entitlements.8 Political conceptions are “freestanding” of comprehensive doctrines—they are built up from liberal values implicit in the political cultures of democracies without relying on comprehensive religious, ethical, or philosophical claims.9 The principle of public reason implies an individual moral duty of public reason, which requires citizens and officials to be willing to justify their political activity by appeal to a political conception of justice.10 The prevailing view among political liberals is that citizens must comply with public reason only for the sake of those who are willing to reciprocally comply.11 This implies that only citizens willing to comply properly belong to the justificatory constituency of “reasonable” citizens to whom the duty of public reason is owed.12 It is not immediately obvious why this view is correct. Not all moral duties are conditional on reciprocal compliance in this way. Consider duties of beneficence to help prevent harm to third parties in dire need. If I am walking by a pond with a drowning person whom I can save at reasonable cost, I plausibly have a duty to do so regardless of whether they would be willing to save me. Why not think that we can owe duties of public reason to those who aren't willing to reciprocate? Political liberals have done surprisingly little to answer this question. The view that public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance is often assumed without argument. However, advocates of the civic friendship account of public reason have developed what I think is the most promising argument for the view in the literature. The civic friendship argument grounds the duty of public reason in the communal relation of mutual respect that citizens realize when they reciprocally comply for the sake of one another.13 Andrew Lister understands the relevant form of respect in terms of “non-alienation”—unless laws are mutually justifiable, some will see their terms of political association “as being animated by purposes they find fundamentally alien.”14 R. J. Leland appeals to the value of mutual “non-imposition”. Imposition occurs when we seek to advance others' interests in ways that “substitut[e] [our] own judgments about what's good for recipients' judgments\\\". This disrespects those we intend to help.15 Civic friends avoid the alienating imposition of cooperative terms by ensuring that each can accept the justification of democratic decisions from their own moral perspectives.16 Lister and Leland disagree about the level of societal compliance required for the duty of public reason to become binding. Lister defends a bilateral account—we always have a duty to justify decisions to every person who is willing to justify decisions to us.17 Leland defends a multilateral account—the duty of public reason is binding only if a significant proportion of citizens comply.18 This debate concerns the background conditions required for the duty of public reason to arise. I am addressing a different question: to whom is the duty of public reason owed when it does arise? In particular, why accept the prevailing view that the duty is owed only to those who are willing to comply with the duty? The civic friendship argument supports two answers. First, because unreciprocated compliance with public reason cannot realize civic friendship; it is morally pointless and cannot be justified. From the standpoint of one's comprehensive doctrine, Lister argues, compliance with public reason comes at a “moral cost”—it requires forgoing the pursuit of what one takes to be true justice for the sake of ensuring a mutually justifiable political order.19 This cost could be justified only if compliance produces a significant moral benefit. But unreciprocated compliance produces no such benefit, the argument goes, since only reciprocal compliance with public reason realizes the value of civic friendship. Lister suggests a different rationale for the view that public reason is conditional on reciprocal compliance when he argues that “[r]efusing to comply with a duty to someone who I know would not reciprocate involves affirming my own dignity”.20 The point can be understood in terms of the ideal of relational equality. Social inequality often arises in relationships when one party allows their willingness to sacrifice their interests to be exploited by others to advance theirs. It is sometimes argued that individuals have an interest in being able to appeal to the full range of their moral convictions when deliberating about matters of great political importance. Public reason requires citizens to bracket their fundamental convictions for the sake of ensuring a mutually justifiable political order.21 When X bears this cost for Y but Y is not willing to reciprocate, Y displays a “failure of recognition” towards X.22 And by allowing themselves to unilaterally bear this cost, X displays a failure of recognition towards themselves. In what follows, I respond to both of these arguments by identifying two ordinary political contexts—one with background equality and the other with background inequality—in which unreciprocated compliance with public reason serves important values while maintaining and promoting egalitarian democratic relationships. As an initial point, it is important to observe that particular instances of unreciprocated cooperative sacrifice do not always generate subordination. Whether they do so depends on contingent features of the relationship in question, including the attitudes of the parties and the history of their relationship. When parties commit to a fair overall balance of sacrifice, they need not engage in in-kind reciprocation of every sacrifice to maintain equality in their relationship. If two friends settle on a routine whereby one always shops for groceries, this need not create any relational subordination if the other friend makes sufficiently many other sorts of sacrifices. Moreover, when the balance of cooperative burdens in a relationship is unfair, beneficiaries can help restore relational equality by sacrificing without demanding reciprocation. If partner B consistently sacrifices their projects for the sake of partner A, A need not problematically subordinate themselves by now making sacrifices without demanding reciprocation. Rather, they can help restore relational equality by repaying their debt of sacrifice and recognizing the equal importance of B's interests. As we've seen, subordination can arise in relationships when individuals allow their willingness to sacrifice their interests to be exploited by others. But noncompliance with public reason is not always or even generally exploitative in this way. Some might fail to comply because they have never heard of political liberalism or the duty of public reason. Some might sincerely reject political liberalism in good faith. Perhaps they would willingly comply if they believed that the duty of public reason existed, but they sincerely believe it doesn't exist. Given the burdens of judgement, we should expect that many people will find the best arguments for political liberalism unpersuasive.23 Those who don't comply with public reason might still give equal weight to the interests of those who comply. They might affirm a comprehensive conception of justice that distributes the benefits and burdens of social cooperation in a fair and impartial way. And they may also be willing to comply with egalitarian laws that others advance through fair democratic procedures, and to cooperate on respectful terms in the democratic process. In such contexts, unreciprocated compliance with public reason need not subordinate compliers. Perhaps they make a particular sort of unreciprocated sacrifice, but noncompliers display a more general willingness to do their fair shares of the overall sacrifice required to relate as equals. To help illustrate the point, consider an idealized democratic society with a high degree of background equality and respectful cooperation: Jordania. Jordania is a democratic community with two large political parties, the Lakers and the Heat. The Lakers accept the duty of public reason. They believe that non-alienation is valuable in both its unreciprocated and reciprocated forms. They include all citizens of Jordania—including the Heat—in the justificatory constituency. The Heat do not comply with public reason. This is not because they want the benefits of being included in the justificatory constituency by the Lakers without bearing the costs of compliance. They simply do not find the best arguments for Rawlsian political liberalism persuasive after careful consideration. They instead appeal to their diverse comprehensive doctrines to justify a political platform that guarantees for all citizens a robust and fair set of primary goods. Jordania has fair and free elections. The Lakers more frequently hold a parliamentary majority because they have broader support among the citizenry. As a consequence, the laws more closely reflect the Lakers' platform than the Heat's platform. The Heat willingly do their fair shares of the sacrifices required by these laws and respectfully cooperate with the Lakers to solve collective problems. There is no pattern of oppression or injustice between the Lakers and Heat; one-off injustices are minor and swiftly remedied. An advocate of the civic friendship argument might concede that unreciprocated compliance with public reason does not create relational inequality in this case, but argue that it is nonetheless morally pointless because unreciprocated compliance cannot realize civic friendship. However, I think the best version of political liberalism acknowledges that individuals have an interest in non-alienation that stands alongside their interest in standing in relations of reciprocal non-alienation. Suppose we ask: why does mutual respect in politics require that we reciprocally justify political decisions to one another? There is generally no problematic lack of respect when individuals do not justify their choice of profession or life partner in terms of reasons others can accept. Why is democratic decision-making different? The most plausible sort of answer appeals to some general feature of democratic politics—for example, that it is coercive,24 that it involves public claims to authority,25 or that democratic power is the collective power of free and equal citizens26—in virtue of which mutual respect demands mutual non-alienation. And this feature of democratic politics will imply that citizens have an independent interest in non-alienation whether or not they comply with public reason. Individuals are subject to the state's use of coercive power and claims to authority even if they don't accept public reason. In this sense, I agree with David Enoch that considerations of reciprocity cannot lie at the “most fundamental moral level” of public reason.27 We can add some clarity by drawing two distinctions concerning cooperative reciprocity. The first distinction is between reciprocity of compliance and reciprocity of benefits. Reciprocity of compliance exists when individuals comply with norms out of a motivation to comply provided others do the same. Reciprocity of benefits exists when norms ensure, as Rawls puts it, that “all who are engaged in cooperation and who do their part as the rules and procedure require, are to benefit in an appropriate way as assessed by a suitable benchmark of comparison.”28 Reciprocity of compliance and reciprocity of benefits can come apart—there can be reciprocal compliance with norms that do not ensure fair mutual benefit and unreciprocated compliance with norms that do ensure fair mutual benefit. The second distinction is between local reciprocity and global reciprocity. Local reciprocity exists when there is reciprocity (of compliance or benefits) with respect to a particular norm. Global reciprocity exists when there is reciprocity (of compliance or benefits) with all norms of a given system. Reciprocity can be more or less global; individuals can reciprocally comply with greater or fewer norms and norms can do a better or worse job of ensuring fair mutual benefit. In Jordania, the Heat are not committed to local reciprocal compliance with the duty of public reason—the Lakers comply while the Heat do not. But the Heat display an effective commitment to global reciprocity of compliance and benefits. In such contexts, unreciprocated compliance with public reason need not subordinate compliers. Of course, real-world democracies have enduring legacies of injustice and oppression. Tommie Shelby argues that victims of systemic injustice are not bound by civic obligations, such as the duty to obey the law. Civic obligations are conditional on global reciprocity of benefits; when a cooperative scheme fails to distribute benefits and burdens in a reasonably just way, victims do not have a civic duty to obey the rules of the scheme. Drawing on Shelby, R. J. Leland argues that victims of injustice are not bound by the demands of civic friendship, including the duty of public reason.29 This is because they can reasonably conclude that fellow citizens do not take their civic interests seriously. And we cannot relate as civic friends with those who don't take our civic interests seriously. Notice what follows if we combine this conclusion with the view that public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance. Victims of injustice are not bound by the duty of public reason because fellow citizens don't treat them as equal partners in a fair cooperative scheme. So, victims must go above and beyond the call of duty to be included in the justificatory constituency and secure the good of non-alienation. By contrast, fellow citizens are properly included in the justificatory constituency simply by doing their duty. This seems unfair to victims of injustice. Leland suggests a response to this worry in passing, though he does not develop it at any length. Although unreciprocated compliance with public reason cannot constitute civic friendship, the response goes, it can promote civic friendship in the future. Extending fair cooperative terms that victims of injustice can accept from their own perspectives facilitate a kind of “reconciliation”. After reconciliation has been achieved through “an extended demonstration of concern over time”, victims of injustice will be bound by the full range of their civic obligations, including the duty of public reason.30 This is valuable because it is necessary for realizing civic friendship. Leland never clarifies in his brief remarks what he means by “reconciliation” or how public reason helps to promote it. One interpretation is that public reason can help repair political relationships damaged by injustice and oppression.31 I think that there is something right about this idea, and I develop a version of it below. However, any attempt to develop the idea within a civic friendship framework faces two problems. First, the civic friendship account seems unable to explain why unreciprocated compliance with public reason can help repair democratic relationships. The most natural explanation is that justifying laws in terms that victims of injustice can accept displays a valuable form of respect. However, the asymmetrical form of respect involved in complying with public reason without demanding reciprocation cannot be explained in terms of civic friendship, which is constituted by the symmetrical respect of reciprocal compliance. A second problem with Leland's account is that it grounds the reparative value of public reason in the value of realizing civic friendship in the future. But the eventual realization of civic friendship seems at most an ancillary reason to care about repairing relationships damaged by serious injustice. The more important reason is that we owe it as a matter of basic respect to affirm the equal standing of those who have been oppressed. Suppose that majorities can reliably predict that victims will not eventually accept the hand of civic friendship and comply with public reason in the future. They still have an urgent duty to repair their political relationship to a footing of equality and trust. If the use of public reason can help do so, this can ground a reparative duty of public reason. If public reason is grounded in its reparative value, its demands are not properly thought to be conditional on reciprocal compliance. Reparative duties are unidirectional and, plausibly, unilaterally binding. They are unidirectional in the sense that if X wrongs Y, X must perform reparative actions for Y (for example, apologize) that Y need not perform for X. Moreover, they are unilaterally binding in the sense that X must perform reparative actions regardless of whether they have assurance that Y would do the same if their positions were reversed. We must take responsibility for remedying the wrongs we have committed, even if we do not have assurance that those we have wronged would do the same for us in the (possibly hypothetical) world in which they wrong us. This can ground a duty to comply with public reason without demanding reciprocation. I have argued that the civic friendship account has difficulty answering two questions about the reparative value of public reason. First, why think that public reason can be used to repair relationships damaged by injustice? In the next subsection, I argue that the use of public reason facilitates a higher-order recognition of the equal standing of victims of injustice. Second, why is repairing relationships through public reason valuable? Leland answers that it helps promote civic friendship through reciprocal compliance in the future. I argue that moral repair through public reason is intrinsically valuable regardless of whether it eventually leads to reciprocal compliance or not. Democratic citizens stand in a distinctive relationship as co-sovereigns and co-subjects of their laws. They are co-sovereigns at least in the minimal sense that they have equal shares of political power—equal voting and other democratic rights—to determine which laws are made and implemented (or which representatives make and implement them). Like Rawls and many others, I assume that citizens have a duty to use their share of political power to promote just institutions and oppose unjust institutions.32 Citizens' duties of justice as co-sovereigns correspond to their vulnerability as co-subjects.33 In a democracy, we depend on others to ensure that laws and institutions treat us as free and equal members of a fair cooperative scheme. Unless enough fellow citizens vote and advocate for just laws and representatives, we may be subject to a basic structure that fails to give us the rights, entitlements, and opportunities we are owed as free and equal. This vulnerability is heightened by the fact that closed borders, limited economic opportunities, and language barriers make it excessively costly for most individuals to exit their states. Most people cannot easily escape the confines of an unjust basic structure. Political majorities commit a serious wrong when they use democratic power to exploit the vulnerability of minorities to advance their own interests. A paradigm example is persistent majority tyranny. This occurs when majorities use democratic institutions to persistently impose unjust cooperative terms on political minorities, often based on race, gender, class, sexual orientation, caste, or creed. I examine the case of caste-based tyranny below. Majority tyranny is wrong for many reasons. It is wrong in part because it results in substantively unjust institutions. But it is also an intrinsically problematic form of relational subordination—members of majorities and minorities do not relate as equal co-sovereigns and co-subjects, but as rulers and ruled-over. Consciousness of this subordination is likely to be experienced as oppressive by victims and to damage self-respect and bonds of trust. Individuals are active participants in majority tyranny when they vote and advocate for unjust laws, and they are mere beneficiaries when they do not vote for such laws but benefit from them. I will use the more general term “beneficiaries” to refer to both groups, and the term “victims” to refer to those who are subject to majority tyranny. Beneficiaries have a duty to oppose the effects of majority tyranny in a way that repairs their democratic relationships with victims. Importantly, the task of repairing a relationship introduces a set of demands oriented towards recognizing the equal standing of those who have suffered wrongdoing. Public reason can play an important role in this reparative task. It does not replace the need for corrective measures that guarantee victims a fair share of rights, opportunities, and resources, or for appropriate restorative procedures such as trials or commissions that hold wrongdoers to account. The use of public reason helps repair relationships through the public justification of such measures. It does so by facilitating a higher-order recognition of the equal standing of victims of injustice. Higher-order recognition is X's recognition that Y recognizes X's equal standing in their relationship.34 Establishing higher-order recognition is often an important element repairing relationships after wrongdoing. Persistent mistreatment generates a justified perception on the part of victims that they have, and are viewed as having, a subordinate moral status. After this damaging failure of recognition, establishing relational equality requires that victims can agree from their own perspectives that wrongdoers recognize their equal standing.35 This partly explains why reparative gestures such as apologies must be sincerely and freely accepted to have their full reparative effect.36 Higher-order recognition can be contrasted with the mere lower-order recognition that occurs when Y recognizes X's equal standing according to Y's moral standards but not X's standards. Wrongdoers might believe that they treat victims as equals, but if their moral beliefs are fundamentally alien or at odds with victims' beliefs about moral equality, victims might be unable to agree that they are respected as equals. Moral repair remains incomplete in an important sense. The use of public reason recognizes victims' equal standing, and promotes victims' recognition that they are so recognized, in two ways. First, it opposes the continued political alienation of victims. Part of what makes majority tyranny wrong is that it imposes institutions that political minorities cannot see as congruent with their own values and self-respect. Majorities have a strong reason to establish relational equality by combating the political alienation they have created and benefited from. The use of public reason does so by ensuring that important decisions are justified in terms of liberal values and principles victims can accept from their own moral perspectives. Second, the use of public reason promotes higher-order recognition of the equal weight of victims' interests in the distribution of primary goods. Majority tyranny entrenches an unfair and exploitative basic structure. Ensuring that the distribution of cooperative benefits and burdens is justifiable in terms of public reasons victims can accept promotes their recognition that majorities recognize their equality. If there is a mere modus vivendi on cooperative terms based on the balance of political power, there is no adequate assurance that majorities won't engage in further tyranny once their political position is more favourable. Moral repair is best promoted when victims can accept the entire public justification for democratic decisions, including the underlying values, principles, and intuitions that justify the decisions. This provides a reason to include victims of injustice in the justificatory constituency of public reason. Justice as fairness, understood as a political conception of justice, provides an argument from moral equality—the original position argument—that individuals with different comprehensive doctrines can accept. Given these considerations, I think the reparative value of public reason\",\"PeriodicalId\":47624,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Political Philosophy\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.9000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-10-11\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Political Philosophy\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1111/jopp.12309\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"ETHICS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Political Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1111/jopp.12309","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

政治自由主义者认为,民主国家的公民有公共理性的义务,以确保其他公民在他们自己的道德和哲学信仰下能够接受的理由来证明重要法律的正当性在任何现实世界的民主国家,许多人都无法履行这一义务。大多数人从未听说过公共理性,而许多听说过它的人也拒绝接受它。这就提出了一个关于公共理性要求的重要问题:对于那些不愿回报法律的人来说,是否有义务确保法律是合理的?大多数政治自由主义者的回答是“不”——公共理性的责任只属于那些自己愿意服从的人这反映了在民主思想中广泛流行的一种更普遍的观点:个人应该缓和自己的政治活动,以容纳与他人的分歧,但前提是其他人愿意回报。例如,许多人认为,个人应该寻求中间立场的政策妥协,但只与那些愿意妥协的人。政治自由主义者的主流观点是,公共理性的义务总是以这种方式的相互遵从为条件。正如安德鲁·李斯特(Andrew Lister)所问的那样,“如果你不愿意同样地对你认为正确但我拒绝的理由进行克制,那么要求我不考虑我认为正确和相关的理由,这怎么可能是合理的呢?我在这篇文章中的目的是回答这个问题,并在这样做的过程中,重新思考公共理性在面对违规行为时的需求。我认为,在广泛的政治背景下,公民有义务为了他人的利益而服从公共理由,而不管他们是否回报。这有助于为政治自由主义的非理想理论奠定基础,使公共理性在民主政治实践中发挥更具包容性和道德意义的作用。在第一节中,我考察了我认为最有力的论据,以支持公共理性总是以相互遵守为条件的主流观点。公民友谊论把公共理性的义务建立在有价值的社区关系之上,这种关系是公民为了彼此的利益而相互遵守时所认识到的。由于对公共理性的无条件服从缺乏相互性,它破坏而不是促进关系平等。当个人承担排除他们认为是真实原因的“道德成本”而不要求他人回报时,他们就允许自己被视为下属在第二节中,我认为,公民友谊的论点错过了一个关于关系不平等的重要事实——是否没有回报的牺牲会产生从属关系取决于所讨论的关系的背景特征,包括各方的动机和他们关系的历史。我确定了两种普遍的政治背景——一种是背景平等,另一种是背景不平等——在这种背景下,对公共理性的无条件服从促进了而不是破坏了平等主义关系。当公民致力于维持合作牺牲的公平整体平衡时,对公共理性的无条件服从可以在不使服从者服从的情况下显示出一种宝贵的尊重形式。在有背景压迫的情况下,遵从公共理性而不要求回报,有助于将政治关系修复到平等的基础上,并恢复信任纽带。我通过研究印度基于种姓的不公正现象来说明公共理性的修复价值。因此,在普通的政治环境中,公民可以有义务遵从公共理性,而不要求回报。我在第三节和第四节中认为,承认这些责任有助于重新定义公共理性在非理想环境中的作用。如果公共理性的义务总是以相互服从为条件,那么在以大量不服从和不公正为特征的民主国家,它的政治作用就会微乎其微。我所捍卫的观点赋予了公共理性一个更广泛、更具包容性的角色,以促进平等主义社会的理想。这并不意味着政治自由主义者必须放弃公民友谊具有特殊价值的观点。相反,公民友谊最好被理解为一种关系理想,多元民主国家的公民应该努力实现这种理想。传统上,自由主义者试图通过呼吁更广泛的道德或哲学真理来证明自由权利和制度的合理性。例如,密尔通过诉诸一种基于对人性的个人主义理解的人类繁荣理论来捍卫平等的自由政治自由主义者认为,对人性和密尔所呼吁的那种善的综合观点不能作为自由主义制度的公共辩护的适当基础。 这是因为个人自由地、真诚地进行推理,不可避免地会在这些问题上产生分歧。这种“合理多元主义的事实”确保了没有任何一种全面的学说能够为自由主义制度提供一个双方都能接受的理由为什么公民能够接受其政治制度的公开辩护很重要?政治自由主义者回答说,公共理性原则要求重要的法律必须以所有理性的公民都能接受的理由为依据。罗尔斯主义者根据“政治”正义概念的“家族”确定了一套相互接受的公共理由,这些正义概念肯定并优先考虑基本的自由权利、机会和分配权利政治观念是“独立的”综合教义——它们是建立在民主政治文化中隐含的自由主义价值观之上的,而不依赖于全面的宗教、伦理或哲学主张公共理性原则意味着公共理性的个人道德义务,这要求公民和官员愿意通过诉诸政治正义概念来为他们的政治活动辩护在政治自由主义者中流行的观点是,公民必须服从公共理性,只是为了那些愿意相互服从的人这意味着,只有愿意适当遵守的公民才属于“合理”公民的正当选民,他们负有公共理性的义务目前还不清楚为什么这种观点是正确的。并不是所有的道德义务都以这种方式的相互遵守为条件。考虑慈善义务,以帮助防止对急需的第三方造成伤害。如果我和一个溺水的人一起走在池塘边,我可以以合理的代价救他,我似乎有义务这样做,不管他们是否愿意救我。为什么不认为我们可以对那些不愿意回报的人承担公共理性的责任呢?令人惊讶的是,政治自由主义者几乎没有回答这个问题。公共理性总是以相互服从为条件,这一观点往往是毫无争议的。然而,倡导公共理性的公民友谊的人已经发展出了我认为在文献中最有希望的观点。公民友谊论把公共理性的义务建立在相互尊重的社会关系之上,这种关系是公民为了彼此的利益而相互遵守时所认识到的安德鲁·李斯特(Andrew Lister)从“非异化”的角度理解了尊重的相关形式——除非法律是相互合理的,否则一些人会认为他们的政治联合条款“被他们认为根本陌生的目的所激发”。R. J.利兰呼吁相互“不强加”的价值。当我们试图推进他人的利益时,就会出现强加的情况,这种方式“取代了[e][我们]自己的判断,认为什么对接受者的判断是好的”。这是对我们打算帮助的人的不尊重公民之友通过确保每个人都能从自己的道德角度接受民主决定的正当性,避免了合作条件的疏远强加李斯特和利兰在公共理性义务具有约束力所需的社会遵从程度上存在分歧。李斯特为一种双边解释辩护——我们总是有责任向每一个愿意为我们的决定辩护的人证明我们的决定是正确的利兰为多边解释辩护——公共理性的义务只有在相当比例的公民遵守的情况下才具有约束力这场辩论涉及公共理性义务产生所需的背景条件。我在回答一个不同的问题:当公共理性的义务出现时,它应该对谁负责?特别是,为什么要接受这种普遍的观点,即只有那些愿意履行义务的人才有义务?公民友谊的论点支持两个答案。第一,因为对公共理性的无条件服从无法实现公民友谊;这在道德上是毫无意义的,不能被证明是正当的。李斯特认为,从一个人的综合主义的立场来看,遵从公共理性需要付出“道德代价”——它需要放弃追求人们所认为的真正正义,以确保一种相互合理的政治秩序只有当遵守规定能产生重大的道德利益时,这种成本才有可能是合理的。但这种观点认为,没有回报的服从不会产生这样的好处,因为只有对公共理性的互惠服从才能实现公民友谊的价值。李斯特提出了一种不同的观点,即公共理性是以互惠性为条件的,他认为“拒绝履行对我知道不会回报的人的义务涉及到肯定我自己的尊严”这一点可以从关系平等的理想角度来理解。 当一方允许他人利用自己牺牲利益的意愿来推进自己的利益时,社会不平等就会出现在关系中。有时有人认为,在考虑重大政治问题时,个人有兴趣能够诉诸于他们全部的道德信念。公共理性要求公民维护他们的基本信念,以确保一个相互公正的政治秩序当X为Y承担这个成本,但Y不愿意回报时,Y对X表现出“认可失败”。22而允许自己单方面承担这个成本,X对自己表现出认可失败。在接下来的文章中,我通过识别两种普通的政治背景来回应这两个论点——一种是背景平等,另一种是背景不平等——在这种政治背景下,对公共理性的无条件服从在维护和促进平等民主关系的同时服务于重要的价值观。首先,重要的是要注意,特定情况下,无偿的合作牺牲并不总是产生从属关系。他们是否这样做取决于有关关系的偶然特征,包括各方的态度和他们关系的历史。当双方承诺做出公平的整体牺牲时,他们不需要对每一个牺牲都进行实物回报,以保持他们关系中的平等。如果两个朋友确定了一个总是去买杂货的习惯,如果另一个朋友在其他方面做出了足够多的牺牲,这就不必产生任何关系上的从属关系。此外,当一段关系中合作负担的平衡不公平时,受益者可以通过牺牲而不要求回报来帮助恢复关系的平等。如果合作伙伴B一直为了合作伙伴A而牺牲自己的项目,那么A现在不必在不要求回报的情况下做出牺牲,从而使自己处于从属地位。相反,他们可以通过偿还自己的牺牲债务和承认B的利益同样重要来帮助恢复关系平等。正如我们所看到的,当个人愿意牺牲自己的利益而被他人利用时,关系中就会出现从属关系。但是,不服从公共理性并不总是或甚至一般都是以这种方式剥削的。有些人可能不遵守,因为他们从未听说过政治自由主义或公共理性的责任。有些人可能真诚地拒绝政治自由主义。如果他们相信公共理性的义务存在,也许他们会心甘情愿地服从,但他们真诚地认为它不存在。考虑到判断的负担,我们应该预料到许多人会发现政治自由主义的最佳论据是没有说服力的那些不服从公共理性的人可能仍然会同等重视服从者的利益。它们可能肯定一种全面的正义概念,以公平和不偏不倚的方式分配社会合作的利益和负担。他们也可能愿意遵守其他国家通过公平民主程序制定的平等主义法律,并在民主进程中以相互尊重的方式进行合作。在这种情况下,对公共理性的无条件服从不需要下级的服从者。也许他们做出了某种特殊的不求回报的牺牲,但不服从者表现出更普遍的意愿,愿意在平等关系所需的整体牺牲中做出自己的公平份额。为了帮助说明这一点,考虑一个具有高度背景平等和尊重合作的理想化民主社会:约旦。约旦是一个民主国家,有两大政党:湖人队和热火队。湖人队接受公众理性的责任。他们认为,非异化在非互惠和互惠两种形式下都是有价值的。他们包括所有约旦公民- - -包括热- - -在正义的选区。热火不遵守公开的理由。这并不是因为他们想要在不承担合规成本的情况下被湖人纳入正当选区的好处。在仔细考虑之后,他们根本找不到罗尔斯政治自由主义的最佳论据。相反,他们诉诸于他们多样化的综合理论,以证明一个保证所有公民都能获得一套健全和公平的初级商品的政治平台是合理的。约旦有公平和自由的选举。湖人队更频繁地拥有议会多数席位,因为他们在公民中有更广泛的支持。因此,这些规则更能反映湖人的平台,而不是热火的平台。 热火愿意在这些法律要求下做出公平的牺牲,并恭敬地与湖人合作解决集体问题。湖人和热火之间没有压迫或不公平的模式;一次性的不公正是微不足道的,可以迅速得到纠正。公民友谊论点的倡导者可能会承认,在这种情况下,对公共理性的无条件服从不会造成关系不平等,但他们认为,这在道德上是毫无意义的,因为无条件的服从不能实现公民友谊。然而,我认为政治自由主义最好的版本承认,个人对非异化的兴趣与他们对相互非异化关系的兴趣并存。假设我们问:为什么政治上的相互尊重要求我们相互为政治决策辩护?当个人不以他人可以接受的理由为他们选择的职业或生活伴侣辩护时,通常不会出现缺乏尊重的问题。为什么民主决策不同?最合理的回答诉诸于民主政治的一些一般特征——例如,它是强制性的(24),它涉及公众对权威的要求(25),或者民主权力是自由平等的公民的集体权力(26)——因此,相互尊重要求相互不异化。民主政治的这一特征意味着公民无论是否遵从公共理性,在非异化方面都具有独立的利益。个人即使不接受公共理性,也受制于国家使用的强制性权力和对权威的要求。在这个意义上,我同意大卫·伊诺克的观点,即互惠的考虑不可能存在于公共理性的“最基本的道德层面”我们可以通过画出关于合作互惠的两个区别来增加一些清晰度。第一个区别是服从互惠和利益互惠。当个人出于遵守规范的动机而遵守规范时,如果其他人也这样做,则存在遵守的互惠性。正如罗尔斯所说,当规范确保“所有参与合作并按规则和程序要求履行职责的人,都能以适当的方式受益,并通过适当的比较基准进行评估”时,利益互惠就存在了。“遵守的互惠和利益的互惠可以分开——可以互惠地遵守不能确保公平互惠的规范,也可以不互惠地遵守确保公平互惠的规范。第二个区别是局部互惠和全局互惠。当对特定规范存在互惠(遵守或利益)时,就存在本地互惠。当与给定系统的所有规范存在互惠(遵守或利益)时,就存在全局互惠。互惠或多或少是全球性的;个人可以相互遵守或多或少的规范,规范可以在确保公平互利方面做得更好或更差。在约旦,热火并没有承诺在当地遵守公共理由的义务——湖人遵守了,而热火没有。但是,热显示了一个有效的承诺,对全球互惠的遵守和利益。在这种情况下,对公共理性的无条件服从不需要下级的服从者。当然,现实世界的民主制度有不公正和压迫的持久遗产。汤米·谢尔比(Tommie Shelby)认为,系统性不公的受害者不受公民义务的约束,比如遵守法律的义务。公民义务以全球利益互惠为条件;当一个合作方案不能合理公正地分配利益和负担时,受害者就没有遵守该方案规则的公民义务。参考Shelby, R. J. Leland认为,不公正的受害者不受公民友谊要求的约束,包括公共理性的义务这是因为他们可以合理地得出结论:同胞们没有认真对待他们的公民利益。作为公民朋友,我们不能与那些不重视我们公民利益的人交往。请注意,如果我们把这个结论与公共理性总是以相互服从为条件的观点结合起来,会发生什么。不公正的受害者不受公共理性义务的约束,因为同胞们没有在公平的合作计划中把他们视为平等的伙伴。因此,受害者必须超越义务的要求,将其纳入正当选区,并确保非异化的利益。相比之下,同胞们仅仅通过履行自己的职责就被恰当地纳入了正当的选区。这对不公正的受害者来说似乎不公平。利兰顺便提出了对这种担忧的回应,尽管他没有详细阐述。 尽管对公共理性的无条件服从不能构成公民友谊,但回应认为,它可以促进未来的公民友谊。扩大公平的合作条件,使不公正的受害者能够从自己的角度接受,这有助于一种“和解”。在通过“长时间的长期关注”实现和解之后,不公正的受害者将受到其全部公民义务的约束,包括公共理性的义务这是有价值的,因为它是实现公民友谊的必要条件。利兰从来没有在他简短的评论中澄清他所说的“和解”是什么意思,也没有说明公共理性如何帮助促进和解。一种解释是,公众理性可以帮助修复因不公正和压迫而受损的政治关系我认为这个想法是对的,我在下面开发了一个版本。然而,任何在公民友谊框架内发展这一想法的尝试都面临两个问题。首先,公民友谊的说法似乎无法解释为什么对公共理性的无条件服从可以帮助修复民主关系。最自然的解释是,以不公正的受害者可以接受的方式为法律辩护,显示了一种有价值的尊重。然而,不要求回报而服从公共理性所涉及的不对称形式的尊重不能用公民友谊来解释,公民友谊是由互惠服从的对称尊重构成的。利兰论述的第二个问题是,它将公共理性的修复价值建立在未来实现公民友谊的价值之上。但是,公民友谊的最终实现似乎最多只是关心修复被严重不公正损害的关系的辅助理由。更重要的原因是,作为一种基本的尊重,我们有责任确认那些受压迫者的平等地位。假设多数人能够可靠地预测,受害者最终不会接受公民友谊之手,也不会遵守公共理性。他们仍然有紧迫的责任将他们的政治关系修复到平等和信任的基础上。如果运用公共理性可以帮助做到这一点,这就可以奠定公共理性的补救义务。如果公共理性是建立在其修复价值的基础上的,那么它的要求就不能被恰当地认为是以相互遵守为条件的。赔偿义务是单向的,而且似乎具有单方面的约束力。它们是单向的,即如果X错了Y, X必须为Y执行Y不需要为X执行的补救措施(例如,道歉)。此外,它们是单边约束,即X必须执行补救措施,而不管他们是否确信如果他们的位置相反,Y会做同样的事情。我们必须承担起纠正我们所犯错误的责任,即使我们不能保证那些被我们冤枉的人会在他们冤枉我们的(可能是假设的)世界里为我们做同样的事情。这可以使一种义务在不要求回报的情况下服从公共理性。我认为,公民友谊理论难以回答关于公共理性的修复价值的两个问题。首先,为什么认为公共理性可以用来修复因不公正而受损的关系?在下一小节中,我将论证公共理性的运用有助于在更高层次上承认不公正受害者的平等地位。第二,为什么通过公共理性修复关系是有价值的?利兰回答说,这有助于通过未来的相互遵守来促进公民友谊。我认为,通过公共理性进行的道德修复具有内在价值,无论它最终是否会导致相互遵守。民主国家的公民作为共同的主权者和共同的法律主体,处于一种独特的关系中。他们是共同主权国家,至少在最小的意义上,他们拥有平等的政治权力——平等的投票权和其他民主权利——来决定哪些法律被制定和实施(或者由哪些代表制定和实施)。像罗尔斯和其他许多人一样,我认为公民有责任利用他们的政治权力来促进公正的制度,反对不公正的制度公民作为共同主权者的正义义务与他们作为共同主体的脆弱性相对应在一个民主国家,我们依靠他人来确保法律和制度将我们视为公平合作计划的自由和平等成员。除非有足够多的同胞投票支持公正的法律和代表,否则我们可能受制于一种基本结构,这种结构无法赋予我们自由和平等的权利、权利和机会。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Noncompliance and the Demands of Public Reason
Political liberals argue that democratic citizens have a duty of public reason to ensure that important laws are justified by reasons fellow citizens can accept given their own moral and philosophical beliefs.1 In any real-world democracy, many will fail to comply with this duty. Most people have never heard of public reason, and many who have heard of it reject it. This raises an important question about the demands of public reason: is there ever a duty to ensure that laws are justifiable to those who are not willing to reciprocate? Most political liberals answer “no”—the duty of public reason is owed only to those who are themselves willing to comply.2 This reflects a more general view that has wide currency in democratic thought: individuals ought to moderate their political activity to accommodate disagreement with others, but only when others are willing to reciprocate. Many think, for example, that individuals ought to seek middle-ground policy compromises, but only with those who are willing to compromise. The prevailing view among political liberals is that the duty of public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance in this way. As Andrew Lister asks, “How could it be reasonable to ask me not to count a reason I think true and relevant on the basis that you reject it, if you are not likewise willing to exercise restraint with respect to reasons that you think true but which I reject?”.3 My aim in this article is to answer this question and, in doing so, to rethink the demands of public reason in the face of noncompliance. I argue that there is a wide range of political contexts in which citizens have duties to comply with public reason for the sake of others regardless of whether they reciprocate. This helps lay foundations for a non-ideal theory of political liberalism that gives public reason a more inclusive and morally significant role in the practice of democratic politics. In Section I, I examine what I take to be the strongest argument for the prevailing view that public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance. The civic friendship argument grounds the duty of public reason in the valuable communal relation that citizens realize when they reciprocally comply for the sake of one another. Because unreciprocated compliance with public reason lacks mutuality, it undermines rather than promotes relational equality. When individuals bear the “moral cost” of excluding what they take to be true reasons without demanding reciprocation from others, they allow themselves to be treated as subordinates.4 In Section II, I argue that the civic friendship argument misses an important truth about relational inequality—that whether unreciprocated sacrifice generates subordination depends on background features of the relationship in question, including the motivations of the parties and the history of their relationship. I identify two general political contexts—one with background equality and the other with inequality—in which unreciprocated compliance with public reason promotes rather than undermines egalitarian relationships. When citizens are committed to maintaining a fair overall balance of cooperative sacrifice, unreciprocated compliance with public reason can display a valuable form of respect without subordinating compliers. And in contexts with background oppression, complying with public reason without demanding reciprocation can help repair political relationships to a footing of equality and restore bonds of trust. I illustrate the reparative value of public reason by examining the case of caste-based injustice in India. In ordinary political contexts, then, citizens can have duties to comply with public reason without demanding reciprocation. Acknowledging such duties, I argue in Sections III and IV, helps reconceptualize the role of public reason in non-ideal contexts. If the duty of public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance, it will have only a marginal political role in democracies characterized by substantial noncompliance and injustice. The view I defend gives public reason a broader and more inclusive role in promoting the ideal of an egalitarian community. This does not mean that political liberals must abandon the idea that civic friendship has special value. Rather, civic friendship is best understood as a relational ideal that citizens of pluralistic democracies should strive to realize in the long-run. Liberals have traditionally sought to justify liberal rights and institutions by appeal to a wider view of comprehensive moral or philosophical truth. Mill, for example, defends equal liberties by appeal to a theory of human flourishing that rests on an individualistic understanding of human nature.5 Political liberals believe that comprehensive views of human nature and the good of the sort to which Mill appeals cannot serve as a proper basis for the public justification of a liberal regime. This is because individuals reasoning freely and in good faith will inevitably disagree about such matters. This “fact of reasonable pluralism” ensures that no comprehensive doctrine can provide a mutually acceptable justification for liberal institutions.6 Why does it matter that citizens can accept the public justification of their political regime? Political liberals answer that the principle of public reason requires important laws7 to be justified by reasons that all reasonable citizens can accept given their own moral perspectives. Rawlsians identify the set of mutually acceptable public reasons in terms of a “family” of “political” conceptions of justice that affirm and give priority to basic liberal rights, opportunities, and distributive entitlements.8 Political conceptions are “freestanding” of comprehensive doctrines—they are built up from liberal values implicit in the political cultures of democracies without relying on comprehensive religious, ethical, or philosophical claims.9 The principle of public reason implies an individual moral duty of public reason, which requires citizens and officials to be willing to justify their political activity by appeal to a political conception of justice.10 The prevailing view among political liberals is that citizens must comply with public reason only for the sake of those who are willing to reciprocally comply.11 This implies that only citizens willing to comply properly belong to the justificatory constituency of “reasonable” citizens to whom the duty of public reason is owed.12 It is not immediately obvious why this view is correct. Not all moral duties are conditional on reciprocal compliance in this way. Consider duties of beneficence to help prevent harm to third parties in dire need. If I am walking by a pond with a drowning person whom I can save at reasonable cost, I plausibly have a duty to do so regardless of whether they would be willing to save me. Why not think that we can owe duties of public reason to those who aren't willing to reciprocate? Political liberals have done surprisingly little to answer this question. The view that public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance is often assumed without argument. However, advocates of the civic friendship account of public reason have developed what I think is the most promising argument for the view in the literature. The civic friendship argument grounds the duty of public reason in the communal relation of mutual respect that citizens realize when they reciprocally comply for the sake of one another.13 Andrew Lister understands the relevant form of respect in terms of “non-alienation”—unless laws are mutually justifiable, some will see their terms of political association “as being animated by purposes they find fundamentally alien.”14 R. J. Leland appeals to the value of mutual “non-imposition”. Imposition occurs when we seek to advance others' interests in ways that “substitut[e] [our] own judgments about what's good for recipients' judgments". This disrespects those we intend to help.15 Civic friends avoid the alienating imposition of cooperative terms by ensuring that each can accept the justification of democratic decisions from their own moral perspectives.16 Lister and Leland disagree about the level of societal compliance required for the duty of public reason to become binding. Lister defends a bilateral account—we always have a duty to justify decisions to every person who is willing to justify decisions to us.17 Leland defends a multilateral account—the duty of public reason is binding only if a significant proportion of citizens comply.18 This debate concerns the background conditions required for the duty of public reason to arise. I am addressing a different question: to whom is the duty of public reason owed when it does arise? In particular, why accept the prevailing view that the duty is owed only to those who are willing to comply with the duty? The civic friendship argument supports two answers. First, because unreciprocated compliance with public reason cannot realize civic friendship; it is morally pointless and cannot be justified. From the standpoint of one's comprehensive doctrine, Lister argues, compliance with public reason comes at a “moral cost”—it requires forgoing the pursuit of what one takes to be true justice for the sake of ensuring a mutually justifiable political order.19 This cost could be justified only if compliance produces a significant moral benefit. But unreciprocated compliance produces no such benefit, the argument goes, since only reciprocal compliance with public reason realizes the value of civic friendship. Lister suggests a different rationale for the view that public reason is conditional on reciprocal compliance when he argues that “[r]efusing to comply with a duty to someone who I know would not reciprocate involves affirming my own dignity”.20 The point can be understood in terms of the ideal of relational equality. Social inequality often arises in relationships when one party allows their willingness to sacrifice their interests to be exploited by others to advance theirs. It is sometimes argued that individuals have an interest in being able to appeal to the full range of their moral convictions when deliberating about matters of great political importance. Public reason requires citizens to bracket their fundamental convictions for the sake of ensuring a mutually justifiable political order.21 When X bears this cost for Y but Y is not willing to reciprocate, Y displays a “failure of recognition” towards X.22 And by allowing themselves to unilaterally bear this cost, X displays a failure of recognition towards themselves. In what follows, I respond to both of these arguments by identifying two ordinary political contexts—one with background equality and the other with background inequality—in which unreciprocated compliance with public reason serves important values while maintaining and promoting egalitarian democratic relationships. As an initial point, it is important to observe that particular instances of unreciprocated cooperative sacrifice do not always generate subordination. Whether they do so depends on contingent features of the relationship in question, including the attitudes of the parties and the history of their relationship. When parties commit to a fair overall balance of sacrifice, they need not engage in in-kind reciprocation of every sacrifice to maintain equality in their relationship. If two friends settle on a routine whereby one always shops for groceries, this need not create any relational subordination if the other friend makes sufficiently many other sorts of sacrifices. Moreover, when the balance of cooperative burdens in a relationship is unfair, beneficiaries can help restore relational equality by sacrificing without demanding reciprocation. If partner B consistently sacrifices their projects for the sake of partner A, A need not problematically subordinate themselves by now making sacrifices without demanding reciprocation. Rather, they can help restore relational equality by repaying their debt of sacrifice and recognizing the equal importance of B's interests. As we've seen, subordination can arise in relationships when individuals allow their willingness to sacrifice their interests to be exploited by others. But noncompliance with public reason is not always or even generally exploitative in this way. Some might fail to comply because they have never heard of political liberalism or the duty of public reason. Some might sincerely reject political liberalism in good faith. Perhaps they would willingly comply if they believed that the duty of public reason existed, but they sincerely believe it doesn't exist. Given the burdens of judgement, we should expect that many people will find the best arguments for political liberalism unpersuasive.23 Those who don't comply with public reason might still give equal weight to the interests of those who comply. They might affirm a comprehensive conception of justice that distributes the benefits and burdens of social cooperation in a fair and impartial way. And they may also be willing to comply with egalitarian laws that others advance through fair democratic procedures, and to cooperate on respectful terms in the democratic process. In such contexts, unreciprocated compliance with public reason need not subordinate compliers. Perhaps they make a particular sort of unreciprocated sacrifice, but noncompliers display a more general willingness to do their fair shares of the overall sacrifice required to relate as equals. To help illustrate the point, consider an idealized democratic society with a high degree of background equality and respectful cooperation: Jordania. Jordania is a democratic community with two large political parties, the Lakers and the Heat. The Lakers accept the duty of public reason. They believe that non-alienation is valuable in both its unreciprocated and reciprocated forms. They include all citizens of Jordania—including the Heat—in the justificatory constituency. The Heat do not comply with public reason. This is not because they want the benefits of being included in the justificatory constituency by the Lakers without bearing the costs of compliance. They simply do not find the best arguments for Rawlsian political liberalism persuasive after careful consideration. They instead appeal to their diverse comprehensive doctrines to justify a political platform that guarantees for all citizens a robust and fair set of primary goods. Jordania has fair and free elections. The Lakers more frequently hold a parliamentary majority because they have broader support among the citizenry. As a consequence, the laws more closely reflect the Lakers' platform than the Heat's platform. The Heat willingly do their fair shares of the sacrifices required by these laws and respectfully cooperate with the Lakers to solve collective problems. There is no pattern of oppression or injustice between the Lakers and Heat; one-off injustices are minor and swiftly remedied. An advocate of the civic friendship argument might concede that unreciprocated compliance with public reason does not create relational inequality in this case, but argue that it is nonetheless morally pointless because unreciprocated compliance cannot realize civic friendship. However, I think the best version of political liberalism acknowledges that individuals have an interest in non-alienation that stands alongside their interest in standing in relations of reciprocal non-alienation. Suppose we ask: why does mutual respect in politics require that we reciprocally justify political decisions to one another? There is generally no problematic lack of respect when individuals do not justify their choice of profession or life partner in terms of reasons others can accept. Why is democratic decision-making different? The most plausible sort of answer appeals to some general feature of democratic politics—for example, that it is coercive,24 that it involves public claims to authority,25 or that democratic power is the collective power of free and equal citizens26—in virtue of which mutual respect demands mutual non-alienation. And this feature of democratic politics will imply that citizens have an independent interest in non-alienation whether or not they comply with public reason. Individuals are subject to the state's use of coercive power and claims to authority even if they don't accept public reason. In this sense, I agree with David Enoch that considerations of reciprocity cannot lie at the “most fundamental moral level” of public reason.27 We can add some clarity by drawing two distinctions concerning cooperative reciprocity. The first distinction is between reciprocity of compliance and reciprocity of benefits. Reciprocity of compliance exists when individuals comply with norms out of a motivation to comply provided others do the same. Reciprocity of benefits exists when norms ensure, as Rawls puts it, that “all who are engaged in cooperation and who do their part as the rules and procedure require, are to benefit in an appropriate way as assessed by a suitable benchmark of comparison.”28 Reciprocity of compliance and reciprocity of benefits can come apart—there can be reciprocal compliance with norms that do not ensure fair mutual benefit and unreciprocated compliance with norms that do ensure fair mutual benefit. The second distinction is between local reciprocity and global reciprocity. Local reciprocity exists when there is reciprocity (of compliance or benefits) with respect to a particular norm. Global reciprocity exists when there is reciprocity (of compliance or benefits) with all norms of a given system. Reciprocity can be more or less global; individuals can reciprocally comply with greater or fewer norms and norms can do a better or worse job of ensuring fair mutual benefit. In Jordania, the Heat are not committed to local reciprocal compliance with the duty of public reason—the Lakers comply while the Heat do not. But the Heat display an effective commitment to global reciprocity of compliance and benefits. In such contexts, unreciprocated compliance with public reason need not subordinate compliers. Of course, real-world democracies have enduring legacies of injustice and oppression. Tommie Shelby argues that victims of systemic injustice are not bound by civic obligations, such as the duty to obey the law. Civic obligations are conditional on global reciprocity of benefits; when a cooperative scheme fails to distribute benefits and burdens in a reasonably just way, victims do not have a civic duty to obey the rules of the scheme. Drawing on Shelby, R. J. Leland argues that victims of injustice are not bound by the demands of civic friendship, including the duty of public reason.29 This is because they can reasonably conclude that fellow citizens do not take their civic interests seriously. And we cannot relate as civic friends with those who don't take our civic interests seriously. Notice what follows if we combine this conclusion with the view that public reason is always conditional on reciprocal compliance. Victims of injustice are not bound by the duty of public reason because fellow citizens don't treat them as equal partners in a fair cooperative scheme. So, victims must go above and beyond the call of duty to be included in the justificatory constituency and secure the good of non-alienation. By contrast, fellow citizens are properly included in the justificatory constituency simply by doing their duty. This seems unfair to victims of injustice. Leland suggests a response to this worry in passing, though he does not develop it at any length. Although unreciprocated compliance with public reason cannot constitute civic friendship, the response goes, it can promote civic friendship in the future. Extending fair cooperative terms that victims of injustice can accept from their own perspectives facilitate a kind of “reconciliation”. After reconciliation has been achieved through “an extended demonstration of concern over time”, victims of injustice will be bound by the full range of their civic obligations, including the duty of public reason.30 This is valuable because it is necessary for realizing civic friendship. Leland never clarifies in his brief remarks what he means by “reconciliation” or how public reason helps to promote it. One interpretation is that public reason can help repair political relationships damaged by injustice and oppression.31 I think that there is something right about this idea, and I develop a version of it below. However, any attempt to develop the idea within a civic friendship framework faces two problems. First, the civic friendship account seems unable to explain why unreciprocated compliance with public reason can help repair democratic relationships. The most natural explanation is that justifying laws in terms that victims of injustice can accept displays a valuable form of respect. However, the asymmetrical form of respect involved in complying with public reason without demanding reciprocation cannot be explained in terms of civic friendship, which is constituted by the symmetrical respect of reciprocal compliance. A second problem with Leland's account is that it grounds the reparative value of public reason in the value of realizing civic friendship in the future. But the eventual realization of civic friendship seems at most an ancillary reason to care about repairing relationships damaged by serious injustice. The more important reason is that we owe it as a matter of basic respect to affirm the equal standing of those who have been oppressed. Suppose that majorities can reliably predict that victims will not eventually accept the hand of civic friendship and comply with public reason in the future. They still have an urgent duty to repair their political relationship to a footing of equality and trust. If the use of public reason can help do so, this can ground a reparative duty of public reason. If public reason is grounded in its reparative value, its demands are not properly thought to be conditional on reciprocal compliance. Reparative duties are unidirectional and, plausibly, unilaterally binding. They are unidirectional in the sense that if X wrongs Y, X must perform reparative actions for Y (for example, apologize) that Y need not perform for X. Moreover, they are unilaterally binding in the sense that X must perform reparative actions regardless of whether they have assurance that Y would do the same if their positions were reversed. We must take responsibility for remedying the wrongs we have committed, even if we do not have assurance that those we have wronged would do the same for us in the (possibly hypothetical) world in which they wrong us. This can ground a duty to comply with public reason without demanding reciprocation. I have argued that the civic friendship account has difficulty answering two questions about the reparative value of public reason. First, why think that public reason can be used to repair relationships damaged by injustice? In the next subsection, I argue that the use of public reason facilitates a higher-order recognition of the equal standing of victims of injustice. Second, why is repairing relationships through public reason valuable? Leland answers that it helps promote civic friendship through reciprocal compliance in the future. I argue that moral repair through public reason is intrinsically valuable regardless of whether it eventually leads to reciprocal compliance or not. Democratic citizens stand in a distinctive relationship as co-sovereigns and co-subjects of their laws. They are co-sovereigns at least in the minimal sense that they have equal shares of political power—equal voting and other democratic rights—to determine which laws are made and implemented (or which representatives make and implement them). Like Rawls and many others, I assume that citizens have a duty to use their share of political power to promote just institutions and oppose unjust institutions.32 Citizens' duties of justice as co-sovereigns correspond to their vulnerability as co-subjects.33 In a democracy, we depend on others to ensure that laws and institutions treat us as free and equal members of a fair cooperative scheme. Unless enough fellow citizens vote and advocate for just laws and representatives, we may be subject to a basic structure that fails to give us the rights, entitlements, and opportunities we are owed as free and equal. This vulnerability is heightened by the fact that closed borders, limited economic opportunities, and language barriers make it excessively costly for most individuals to exit their states. Most people cannot easily escape the confines of an unjust basic structure. Political majorities commit a serious wrong when they use democratic power to exploit the vulnerability of minorities to advance their own interests. A paradigm example is persistent majority tyranny. This occurs when majorities use democratic institutions to persistently impose unjust cooperative terms on political minorities, often based on race, gender, class, sexual orientation, caste, or creed. I examine the case of caste-based tyranny below. Majority tyranny is wrong for many reasons. It is wrong in part because it results in substantively unjust institutions. But it is also an intrinsically problematic form of relational subordination—members of majorities and minorities do not relate as equal co-sovereigns and co-subjects, but as rulers and ruled-over. Consciousness of this subordination is likely to be experienced as oppressive by victims and to damage self-respect and bonds of trust. Individuals are active participants in majority tyranny when they vote and advocate for unjust laws, and they are mere beneficiaries when they do not vote for such laws but benefit from them. I will use the more general term “beneficiaries” to refer to both groups, and the term “victims” to refer to those who are subject to majority tyranny. Beneficiaries have a duty to oppose the effects of majority tyranny in a way that repairs their democratic relationships with victims. Importantly, the task of repairing a relationship introduces a set of demands oriented towards recognizing the equal standing of those who have suffered wrongdoing. Public reason can play an important role in this reparative task. It does not replace the need for corrective measures that guarantee victims a fair share of rights, opportunities, and resources, or for appropriate restorative procedures such as trials or commissions that hold wrongdoers to account. The use of public reason helps repair relationships through the public justification of such measures. It does so by facilitating a higher-order recognition of the equal standing of victims of injustice. Higher-order recognition is X's recognition that Y recognizes X's equal standing in their relationship.34 Establishing higher-order recognition is often an important element repairing relationships after wrongdoing. Persistent mistreatment generates a justified perception on the part of victims that they have, and are viewed as having, a subordinate moral status. After this damaging failure of recognition, establishing relational equality requires that victims can agree from their own perspectives that wrongdoers recognize their equal standing.35 This partly explains why reparative gestures such as apologies must be sincerely and freely accepted to have their full reparative effect.36 Higher-order recognition can be contrasted with the mere lower-order recognition that occurs when Y recognizes X's equal standing according to Y's moral standards but not X's standards. Wrongdoers might believe that they treat victims as equals, but if their moral beliefs are fundamentally alien or at odds with victims' beliefs about moral equality, victims might be unable to agree that they are respected as equals. Moral repair remains incomplete in an important sense. The use of public reason recognizes victims' equal standing, and promotes victims' recognition that they are so recognized, in two ways. First, it opposes the continued political alienation of victims. Part of what makes majority tyranny wrong is that it imposes institutions that political minorities cannot see as congruent with their own values and self-respect. Majorities have a strong reason to establish relational equality by combating the political alienation they have created and benefited from. The use of public reason does so by ensuring that important decisions are justified in terms of liberal values and principles victims can accept from their own moral perspectives. Second, the use of public reason promotes higher-order recognition of the equal weight of victims' interests in the distribution of primary goods. Majority tyranny entrenches an unfair and exploitative basic structure. Ensuring that the distribution of cooperative benefits and burdens is justifiable in terms of public reasons victims can accept promotes their recognition that majorities recognize their equality. If there is a mere modus vivendi on cooperative terms based on the balance of political power, there is no adequate assurance that majorities won't engage in further tyranny once their political position is more favourable. Moral repair is best promoted when victims can accept the entire public justification for democratic decisions, including the underlying values, principles, and intuitions that justify the decisions. This provides a reason to include victims of injustice in the justificatory constituency of public reason. Justice as fairness, understood as a political conception of justice, provides an argument from moral equality—the original position argument—that individuals with different comprehensive doctrines can accept. Given these considerations, I think the reparative value of public reason
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
4.10
自引率
5.60%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: The Journal of Political Philosophy is an international journal devoted to the study of theoretical issues arising out of moral, legal and political life. It welcomes, and hopes to foster, work cutting across a variety of disciplinary concerns, among them philosophy, sociology, history, economics and political science. The journal encourages new approaches, including (but not limited to): feminism; environmentalism; critical theory, post-modernism and analytical Marxism; social and public choice theory; law and economics, critical legal studies and critical race studies; and game theoretic, socio-biological and anthropological approaches to politics. It also welcomes work in the history of political thought which builds to a larger philosophical point and work in the philosophy of the social sciences and applied ethics with broader political implications. Featuring a distinguished editorial board from major centres of thought from around the globe, the journal draws equally upon the work of non-philosophers and philosophers and provides a forum of debate between disparate factions who usually keep to their own separate journals.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信