社会科学、政策与民主

IF 3.3 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS
Johanna Thoma
{"title":"社会科学、政策与民主","authors":"Johanna Thoma","doi":"10.1111/papa.12250","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Can social science provide policy-guidance without undermining some basic democratic values? It would clearly be devastating if the answer was “no”: Most people are deeply committed both to democracy, as well as to the idea that policy decisions should be informed by the best available science, including the best available social science. Accordingly, the many philosophers who have worried about potential tensions between science and democracy have come out arguing that, if done right, good science and democracy mutually support rather than undermine each other, John Dewey and Philip Kitcher being paradigmatic examples.1 This article argues that there is an under-appreciated democratic challenge for policy-relevant science, which I will articulate specifically in the context of value-laden social scientific indicators. Value-ladenness has long been acknowledged to pose an obstacle for reconciling science and democracy: It creates the potential for the value judgments made by a small subset of the population to have a significant impact on policy decisions, in a way that bypasses normal processes of democratic legitimization. Consequently, solutions to this challenge have either defended the value-free ideal,2 or stressed the need to, in one way or another, democratically align the values entering science, in a way that is parallel to how democratic legitimacy is given to public decision-making more generally. The nature of many social scientific indicators makes the value-free ideal wholly unworkable, lest we give up the entire project of aiming to measure poverty, inequality, or wellbeing. And so only the second common type of response seems to be available in their case. But, I will argue, this response misses a significant part of the challenge value-ladenness poses to democracy. The solution, I will argue, is greater value pluralism rather than democratic alignment. As I write, the United Kingdom, like many countries around the world, is facing a devastating cost of living crisis. The incomes of large numbers of households cannot keep up with the rising prices of the goods and services they consume, pushing increasing numbers into poverty. To tackle this crisis, it is important that policy-makers have a clear picture of inflation—of how much the cost of living has increased, how it is projected to further increase, and how different policy options will affect the rate of change. In the United Kingdom, the Office of National Statistics (ONS) supplies a number of measures of inflation that are treated as key indicators by policy-makers, by the public and media holding them to account, and by social scientists studying the causal relationships between inflation and other social scientific variables or policy interventions. The most widely used and reported indicator is the Consumer Price Index (CPI). But what is the cost of living? The first thing to note is that it is clearly a value-laden concept and treated as such by those using it. Saying that the cost of living has gone up involves making a comparative evaluation of the kinds of goods and lifestyles that can be afforded by households before and after changes in prices. In the most general terms, it is good for people to be able to afford to live well, and measures of changes in the cost of living aim to capture the extent to which households can do that. Clearly, however, there are different ways of making this idea precise. Two salient ways of making it at least somewhat more precise would be to either think of it as the cost of meeting one's basic needs, or to conceive of it as the cost of consuming the kinds of things one is actually consuming—which in many cases will go beyond meeting one's basic needs. In either case, the cost of living in fact differs between different people. Clearly, different people actually consume different things, the prices of which may change to different extents. But even the cost of meeting basic needs may differ between different people; I need corrective lenses to function in daily life, while you may not. A measure of inflation useful for large scale policy needs to capture changes in the aggregate cost of living despite this heterogeneity.3 Both the choice of concept of “cost of living” as well as choices about how to aggregate over a diverse population involve important value judgments, about what makes life good, about who matters how much, about what we are entitled to expect compensation for from each other and the state, and about our policy priorities. Actual measures of inflation embed these value judgments. In practice, the headline CPI published by the ONS aspires to capture changes in the prices of the things households are actually consuming.4 It uses a representative basket of 700 goods, regularly collecting price quotations from different kinds of outlets all over the country. In deciding on the quantities of each good in the basket, the headline CPI defers to the consumption decisions of households. More specifically, it gives weight to different households in proportion to their share of the total expenditure of all households, making the CPI more sensitive to the consumption decisions of richer households. The ONS has been under increased pressure from anti-poverty campaigners in recent years arguing that the headline inflation figures do not capture well the extent of the cost of living crisis experienced by the poorest households.5 The criticism is both that the standard basket used by the ONS does not include enough of the items the poorest households are consuming to meet basic needs, such as supermarket own-brand products, and that, as an effect of aggregation, higher price increases on those products are washed out by lower price increases in the goods disproportionately consumed by richer households. Periodic disaggregation carried out by the ONS can address the second concern to some extent, but not the first. The central controversy here is at heart about values and policy priorities: Relative to the other purposes inflation measures may help to serve, campaigners want greater policy priority given to compensating the worst-off households for increases in the cost of meeting basic needs, or to preventing such increases from happening in the first place. Consequently, they want inflation measures to be designed for serving those purposes to the greatest extent possible, which they traditionally have not. The ONS is currently making some changes to address these challenges better, to which we will return below.6 To get to the heart of my concern in this article, note that there are two levels to this controversy. On the one hand, there is disagreement about the values that, in virtue of being captured by policy-guiding social scientific indicators, will end up shaping public policy. In that respect, the controversy is much like any other disagreement in the political sphere. But on the other hand, there is also the complaint that one side to this debate does not have access to the measurements (and scientific studies employing them) that would help them make their case in public debate, while the other side does. One side can appeal to official statistics capturing what they care about, while the other needs to rely on evidence that remains anecdotal. They are not entering public deliberation as equals. This is a distinct issue from the first, and, I argue, one that is neglected by the literature aiming to reconcile democracy and the value-ladenness of science. It is also an issue that, for reasons explored below, is unlikely to sufficiently self-correct in democratic societies. Measures of inflation are just one type of social scientific indicator that is at once value-laden, and highly relevant for guiding policy. Were it the case that the value judgments in question were made entirely by unelected social scientists, based exclusively on personal values unrepresentative of the population at large, this would be problematic on any plausible normative theory of democracy. To the extent that value judgments have an impact on policy, we may want to ensure that the values embedded in them are picked in a democratically legitimate way, just like we aim to ensure democratic legitimacy for any significant policy decision. But there is another important aspect of the relationship between policy-relevant science and democracy. The outputs of policy-relevant science, such as social scientific indicators, are not only used to inform the choices of policy-makers. They also feed back into public deliberation, and are used to hold policy-makers to account. Focusing only on the democratic selection of the values that enter the research that is then used to guide policy choice ignores this second purpose of policy-relevant science. This is problematic specifically in contexts of significant value disagreement. Modern democracies often find themselves confronted with irresolvable disagreement about the values at stake in a policy decision, including the types of values that are embedded in policy-relevant social scientific indicators. Still, most accounts of democracy allow for such decisions to be made without requiring that consensus is in fact reached. Likewise, we may, in a democratically legitimate way, settle on the values to be embedded in the social scientific indicators that are then used to guide specific types of policy, without in fact reaching consensus on those being the right values. However, if no other social scientific indicators than the democratically selected ones are widely available to the public and to social scientists, this raises, I argue, a problem of epistemic inequality: Only those who share the democratically selected value judgments embedded in the chosen indicators can make full and reliable use of them in public deliberation and when holding policy-makers to account. Others are at an epistemic disadvantage, since the available indicators only partially capture what they take to be important, and at worst, there may be no available measurements of the things most crucial to them given their values and interests. In an important respect, then, those others do not enter further public deliberation as equals, and are not to the same extent able to hold the government to account. While the values were, by hypothesis, originally chosen in a democratically legitimate way, there is a danger they become entrenched, undermining the good functioning of democracy going forward. What is needed to address this problem, I will argue, is for social science to aim for an output that is value pluralist, in order to help ensure a distribution of the epistemic goods needed for good public deliberation that is sufficiently equal to achieve important democratic values. In the case of the measurement of value-laden social scientific indicators, two feasible strategies to ensure greater value pluralism are the availability of publicly accessible dashboards of multiple indicators on the one hand, and tools that allow policy-makers and the public to adjust the weightings of different components of aggregate indicators, on the other. Unfortunately, this conclusion runs counter to trends in several important fields of research in policy-relevant social science, where there are ambitions of and political pressures toward a single metric to guide policy. An important upshot of my argument is that these ambitions are highly problematic from a democratic point of view. And insofar as pluralism is already practiced or advocated for in the social sciences, I provide an additional and neglected democratic justification for it. The next section will outline what I take to be some uncontroversial ideas regarding social scientific indicators, values and science to serve as a backdrop to my argument. It will draw some implications for the common ambition of a single, dominant policy-guiding indicator. Section III will spell out a first democratic challenge for such indicators, and show how it motivates existing philosophical accounts of how this democratic challenge can be addressed. I go on, in Section IV, to characterize the notion of epistemic equality at the core of my new democratic challenge, and explain how existing philosophical attempts to reconcile social science and democracy fail to address it. Section V contains my positive proposal along with examples of existing good practice. My argument in this article concerns scientific outputs that serve both an epistemic as well as a policy-guiding function. Social scientific indicators are paradigmatic examples of such scientific outputs. Let me start by outlining five uncontroversial ideas concerning social scientific indicators. Many of the most policy-relevant social scientific indicators measure “thick concepts,” which are concepts that are partly descriptive, and partly evaluative. As discussed in the introduction, “cost of living” is one such concept. Other important examples include wellbeing (more on which in what follows), economic welfare, economic inequality, poverty, and health, all of which are measured and studied by the social sciences.7 Disagreement may be about how a particular concept should be understood in a particular context. For instance, in our opening example, part of the controversy over the ONS's inflation measurements are about whether the notion of the cost of living to be measured should be the cost of consuming our actual consumption baskets, or the cost of meeting basic needs. In other domains, it may be about what it means to be poor, or healthy, or, as we'll see, about what wellbeing consists in. This is disagreement about concepts, that is, disagreement about what we should count. There is, in addition, also often disagreement about how we should count it: How do we compare the cost of living, wellbeing, health, or economic welfare of different people, and how do we aggregate them in order to study population-level effects? There are two aspects to this: First, we often need to determine how to compare and meaningfully add up two kinds of effects in the first place, how to compare apples and oranges, as it were (quite literally, in the case of inflation measurement!). Call disagreement about this disagreement about commensuration. Second, there is the question of how much weight to assign to different effects once we have in principle decided how we can compare them. The crucial question here is often how much weight to give to effects on different people, e.g., different people's wellbeing or cost of living. Call disagreement about this disagreement about aggregation. Finally, there is also often disagreement about the relative importance of the values captured by a social scientific indicator. We may, for instance, agree on what poverty is, but may disagree on how important it is relative to other policy priorities. Call this disagreement about priorities. For the purposes of this article, when people give priority to their own interests relative to others, and as a consequence favor a way of aggregating, for instance, wellbeing in a way that gives more weight to the wellbeing of people like them, I will treat this as a kind of value disagreement (where interests are not explicitly specified alongside values, this should be read to be included). And so, value disagreement in the relevant sense can be expected to be especially common where the interests of different segments of society are in conflict with one another. To some extent, the process of sharing reasons with each other may resolve some of these disagreements, especially where people's views may have been based on insufficient reflection or experience. We may come to see each other's point of view and adjust our own, regarding, for instance the nature and relative importance of poverty. However, professional philosophy provides good evidence that complete consensus on fundamental questions of value, such as, for instance, the correct theory of wellbeing, is not a realistic prospect even in an environment where the constant exchange of arguments is routine. Here, I have in mind mainly two senses in which an indicator can be aggregate: It can aggregate effects on many different people, and it can aggregate different kinds of effect. For instance, the CPI is aggregate in both respects: It aggregates the changes in the cost of living of many different people. And it also aggregates price changes of many different types of goods. Compared to disaggregated price indices for individual people or individual types of goods, this involves making additional value judgments: First, there are judgments about commensuration, about how to compare different types of effects on different people in the first place. And second, there are judgments of aggregation proper, of how much weight to give to different people and different kinds of effect. For instance, do different households count equally or proportionately to share in overall spending? These additional value judgments mean that there is more room for value disagreement, namely for what we above called disagreement about commensuration and disagreement about aggregation. This makes it less likely that consensus can be reached even in an extensive process of public deliberation. Policy-makers can only effectively serve society, and society can only engage in fruitful public deliberation, if we have reliable and usable information on what the likely consequences of the different available policy options are. Many of the most important consequences of public policy concern phenomena studied by the social sciences, and these sciences offer the best means of reliable knowledge about the effects of public policy. And so, it is commonplace, among both social scientists and philosophers of science, to treat it as a desideratum that social science should provide useful policy-guidance. While the general idea is very intuitive, on closer inspection, there are at least two important ambiguities to this desideratum. The first relates to whether what is desirable is that social science (a) studies some of the effects of policy that are choice-relevant, (b) studies all of the effects of policy that are choice-relevant, or (c) supplies a measure of how choice-worthy different policy options are all-things-considered. These differ in the extent of guidance demanded from social science. The second ambiguity arises from the fact that which effects are choice-relevant depends on the goals and values to be pursued. Some salient possibilities of what these could be are either (i) those of the actual policy-maker, (ii) those that would be decided on in a democratically legitimate process, or (iii) all policy-relevant values reasonably held by members of the population. The point of applying (i) or (ii) would be that social science should assist (democratic) public decision-making, and demands for policy-relevance have usually focused on these notions of policy-relevance. Sense (iii) is salient once we take seriously an idea explored below: that social science should also inform the public deliberation preceding public choice, and the holding to account of public decision-makers. Once we clear up these ambiguities, some of the weakest formulations of the desideratum are clearly uncontroversial: Social science should produce reliable and usable information on some of the policy effects that are choice-relevant relative to some values reasonably held by members of the population. Plausibly, they should also, in particular, produce reliable and usable information that is choice-relevant relative to the values a policy-maker is pursuing in a democratically legitimate way. As we will see, in some debates, however, the desideratum is understood in stronger terms, namely as requiring social science to produce all-things-considered measures of policy-evaluation. Call this strong policy-guidance, an idea admittedly (and fortunately) far from policy-making practice. In these discussions, the relevant values to be pursued are typically thought of as the values policy-makers are either assumed to actually have or ought to have. Such measures would provide action-guidance to policy-makers in the most direct terms. We will see below that the desideratum of strong policy-guidance is highly problematic. Ultimately, policy-makers do need to take into account all relevant effects of the policy options open to them, weigh up their relative importance and arrive at an all-things-considered judgment as to what the best policy option is. This will typically require them to perform some kind of aggregation of effects on different people and of different types, either explicitly or implicitly. Now suppose you subscribe to the desideratum of strong policy-guidance, and so take it to be desirable for the social sciences to produce measures that tell policy-makers how well different policy options serve policy-makers' goals all-things-considered. Given the need for aggregation, this implies that social science should be producing the most aggregate social scientific indicator, one single metric to integrate all positive and negative effects of different policy options on different people and of different types, to be used to directly guide public policy. This, in a nutshell, is the motivation for a number of projects in the social sciences to provide policy-makers with, in the words of Anna Alexandrova, a “master number” to guide public decision-making.8 Sometimes these projects have included efforts to push for the preferred metric of policy analysis to be integrated in the standard procedures of the administrative machinery of government. A recent phenomenon of this type is the advocacy of behavioral scientists and happiness economists subscribing to the subjective wellbeing approach to treat an aggregate subjective wellbeing metric as just such a “master number” to provide an all-things-considered evaluation of policy.9 In the United Kingdom, these efforts have had some success, with subjective wellbeing now being included in the government's Green Book.10 Note, however, that while the academic ambition in the relevant social scientific communities is a truly all-things-considered metric for policy evaluation, in practice, of course, even sympathetic policy-makers will inevitably take other things into account, in a way that is sensitive to context and the purpose at hand. Past projects that don't aim at a measure that is strictly speaking all-things-considered, but still aim at a fairly comprehensive assessment of how well a country is serving its people's interests, have been Gross Domestic Product (GDP), and, building on that measure's weaknesses, the UN's Human Development Index (HDI). Going back to our list of uncontroversial claims, one consequence of any such “master number” approach, if it insists on a single all-things-considered metric, is that there is likely going to be widespread disagreement about the values embedded in this single highly aggregate metric. The same is true, to a slightly lesser extent, of metrics that are less “all-things-considered” but yet highly aggregate. Specific measures of the cost of living, poverty, or inequality aim to capture only one type of policy-relevant effect. Still, they embed value judgments about which there is widespread disagreement. Within these domains, too, however, debate between social scientists often focuses on finding the one best metric, to then present to public decision-makers and the public as policy-guiding. This tendency toward monism within the social sciences, be it regarding a single all-things-considered “master number” or within individual sub-domains of policy interest is reinforced by political and pragmatic pressures11: political pressures to provide unambiguous policy-guidance, enabling policy-makers to say they were merely “guided by the science”; and pragmatic pressure based on the fact that the cost of the measurement of social scientific indicators, such as the measurement of inflation, is very high. The result is that in the case of many of the social and economic effects of policy, a single or a small number of indicators at once serve to guide policy and inform public debate, while alternative measures are either lacking or much less known and accessible—just think of the dominance of GDP in reporting and public deliberation about the economy. And notably, these measures by and large remain the same over time even in the face of shifts in public opinion and changes in government. The next section spells out one type of threat this phenomenon can pose to democracy, familiar from more general discussions on values in science. It will then outline philosophical accounts of the democratization of science that have aimed to address this threat, all of which aim at some form of what I call democratic alignment. I will ultimately argue that there is another democratic threat that these accounts do not sufficiently address, and which can only be countered with greater value pluralism. Consider this hypothetical example of how value-laden social science may guide policy: A social scientist develops a measure of national wellbeing, making all required value judgments on the basis of only her own moral intuitions, theorizing, and reading of the philosophical literature on wellbeing. Her theorizing remains inaccessible to the public and policy-makers, but she and her team produce both regular measurements of national wellbeing, as well as studies estimating the effects of different potential policies on national wellbeing. Policy-makers use the results of these studies in an effort to maximize national wellbeing, explaining to the public that they are merely “following the science.” This is clearly an example of a problematic kind of technocracy that runs counter to core democratic values on any normative theory of democracy. The scientist was neither publicly elected, nor is her reasoning about which values to capture with her national wellbeing measure open for public scrutiny. Her reasoning is also not responsive to the values of either the public or democratically elected public decision-makers. For the reasons discussed in the last section, it is moreover unlikely that the values the scientist ends up capturing are uncontroversial, given the aggregate nature of a measure of national wellbeing. Yet, her choice of measure ends up having a substantial effect on public policy, in a process that bypasses ordinary processes of democratic legitimization. It is clear that our imagined example is not a case of democratic decision-making—power is not exercised by the people here, either directly or indirectly. Different normative accounts of democracy explain what is bad about this in slightly different ways. One important branch of democratic theory sees democracy as a way of treating everybody as equals. There is a variety of such egalitarian conceptions of democracy. One idea is that democracy is the best way to ensure public equality, that public institutions and decision-making procedures treat everybody equally, giving everybody an equal say over how the communal aspects of our lives ought to be organized.12 Another is that democracy ensures relational equality, that citizens stand in relationships of equality to each other, and not in relations of domination and subordination.13 Technocracy of the type I described is problematically inegalitarian on each of these types of views. The social scientist has disproportionate power over her fellow citizens, being able to impose her value judgments on everybody else. This is relationally inegalitarian, and she is being given that power by the way in which public decision-making is structured. Disproportionate power is also at the heart of other potential explanations of what is bad, from a democratic perspective, about the kind of technocracy just described. According to some accounts, the crucial value of democracy consists in enabling the public justification of the institutions and policies that rule our lives.14 Public justification requires, at a minimum, that the reasons for and against different policy options are made public and subjected to a process of public deliberation among equals. But in the technocratic scenario, not only does the scientist have a disproportionate say, but the reasons for public decisions also remain opaque. Well-informed public deliberation has been emphasized more generally by advocates of the deliberative democracy movement. Aside from the ones already mentioned, it is also crucial on other prominent views of democracy. For instance, on perfectionist views of democracy, such as that put forward in Mill,15 democracy is good because it gives citizens the opportunity to exercise their moral capacities. On instrumentalist conceptions of the value of democracy, democracy is good because it tends to lead to good decisions, for which a well-informed process of public deliberation is in turn important.16 While our scientist has important technical and scientific expertise, she likely does not have significantly more expertise on questions of value than any other citizen, so that decision-making could be improved by including others in the deliberative process.17 The example I started this section with is of course only a cautionary tale. But it is not far off the vision pursued by some of the advocates of “master number” approaches discussed in the last section.18 And it highlights a certain kind of danger for policy-relevant social science more generally. The danger comes from the fact that contentious value judgments need to be made in such research, and that such research in turn often directly influences public policy. Now it might seem that to address this problem, all that needs to be ensured is that the values that enter the social scientific research are selected in a democratically more legitimate way than in our cautionary t","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.3000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Social Science, Policy and Democracy\",\"authors\":\"Johanna Thoma\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/papa.12250\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Can social science provide policy-guidance without undermining some basic democratic values? It would clearly be devastating if the answer was “no”: Most people are deeply committed both to democracy, as well as to the idea that policy decisions should be informed by the best available science, including the best available social science. Accordingly, the many philosophers who have worried about potential tensions between science and democracy have come out arguing that, if done right, good science and democracy mutually support rather than undermine each other, John Dewey and Philip Kitcher being paradigmatic examples.1 This article argues that there is an under-appreciated democratic challenge for policy-relevant science, which I will articulate specifically in the context of value-laden social scientific indicators. Value-ladenness has long been acknowledged to pose an obstacle for reconciling science and democracy: It creates the potential for the value judgments made by a small subset of the population to have a significant impact on policy decisions, in a way that bypasses normal processes of democratic legitimization. Consequently, solutions to this challenge have either defended the value-free ideal,2 or stressed the need to, in one way or another, democratically align the values entering science, in a way that is parallel to how democratic legitimacy is given to public decision-making more generally. The nature of many social scientific indicators makes the value-free ideal wholly unworkable, lest we give up the entire project of aiming to measure poverty, inequality, or wellbeing. And so only the second common type of response seems to be available in their case. But, I will argue, this response misses a significant part of the challenge value-ladenness poses to democracy. The solution, I will argue, is greater value pluralism rather than democratic alignment. As I write, the United Kingdom, like many countries around the world, is facing a devastating cost of living crisis. The incomes of large numbers of households cannot keep up with the rising prices of the goods and services they consume, pushing increasing numbers into poverty. To tackle this crisis, it is important that policy-makers have a clear picture of inflation—of how much the cost of living has increased, how it is projected to further increase, and how different policy options will affect the rate of change. In the United Kingdom, the Office of National Statistics (ONS) supplies a number of measures of inflation that are treated as key indicators by policy-makers, by the public and media holding them to account, and by social scientists studying the causal relationships between inflation and other social scientific variables or policy interventions. The most widely used and reported indicator is the Consumer Price Index (CPI). But what is the cost of living? The first thing to note is that it is clearly a value-laden concept and treated as such by those using it. Saying that the cost of living has gone up involves making a comparative evaluation of the kinds of goods and lifestyles that can be afforded by households before and after changes in prices. In the most general terms, it is good for people to be able to afford to live well, and measures of changes in the cost of living aim to capture the extent to which households can do that. Clearly, however, there are different ways of making this idea precise. Two salient ways of making it at least somewhat more precise would be to either think of it as the cost of meeting one's basic needs, or to conceive of it as the cost of consuming the kinds of things one is actually consuming—which in many cases will go beyond meeting one's basic needs. In either case, the cost of living in fact differs between different people. Clearly, different people actually consume different things, the prices of which may change to different extents. But even the cost of meeting basic needs may differ between different people; I need corrective lenses to function in daily life, while you may not. A measure of inflation useful for large scale policy needs to capture changes in the aggregate cost of living despite this heterogeneity.3 Both the choice of concept of “cost of living” as well as choices about how to aggregate over a diverse population involve important value judgments, about what makes life good, about who matters how much, about what we are entitled to expect compensation for from each other and the state, and about our policy priorities. Actual measures of inflation embed these value judgments. In practice, the headline CPI published by the ONS aspires to capture changes in the prices of the things households are actually consuming.4 It uses a representative basket of 700 goods, regularly collecting price quotations from different kinds of outlets all over the country. In deciding on the quantities of each good in the basket, the headline CPI defers to the consumption decisions of households. More specifically, it gives weight to different households in proportion to their share of the total expenditure of all households, making the CPI more sensitive to the consumption decisions of richer households. The ONS has been under increased pressure from anti-poverty campaigners in recent years arguing that the headline inflation figures do not capture well the extent of the cost of living crisis experienced by the poorest households.5 The criticism is both that the standard basket used by the ONS does not include enough of the items the poorest households are consuming to meet basic needs, such as supermarket own-brand products, and that, as an effect of aggregation, higher price increases on those products are washed out by lower price increases in the goods disproportionately consumed by richer households. Periodic disaggregation carried out by the ONS can address the second concern to some extent, but not the first. The central controversy here is at heart about values and policy priorities: Relative to the other purposes inflation measures may help to serve, campaigners want greater policy priority given to compensating the worst-off households for increases in the cost of meeting basic needs, or to preventing such increases from happening in the first place. Consequently, they want inflation measures to be designed for serving those purposes to the greatest extent possible, which they traditionally have not. The ONS is currently making some changes to address these challenges better, to which we will return below.6 To get to the heart of my concern in this article, note that there are two levels to this controversy. On the one hand, there is disagreement about the values that, in virtue of being captured by policy-guiding social scientific indicators, will end up shaping public policy. In that respect, the controversy is much like any other disagreement in the political sphere. But on the other hand, there is also the complaint that one side to this debate does not have access to the measurements (and scientific studies employing them) that would help them make their case in public debate, while the other side does. One side can appeal to official statistics capturing what they care about, while the other needs to rely on evidence that remains anecdotal. They are not entering public deliberation as equals. This is a distinct issue from the first, and, I argue, one that is neglected by the literature aiming to reconcile democracy and the value-ladenness of science. It is also an issue that, for reasons explored below, is unlikely to sufficiently self-correct in democratic societies. Measures of inflation are just one type of social scientific indicator that is at once value-laden, and highly relevant for guiding policy. Were it the case that the value judgments in question were made entirely by unelected social scientists, based exclusively on personal values unrepresentative of the population at large, this would be problematic on any plausible normative theory of democracy. To the extent that value judgments have an impact on policy, we may want to ensure that the values embedded in them are picked in a democratically legitimate way, just like we aim to ensure democratic legitimacy for any significant policy decision. But there is another important aspect of the relationship between policy-relevant science and democracy. The outputs of policy-relevant science, such as social scientific indicators, are not only used to inform the choices of policy-makers. They also feed back into public deliberation, and are used to hold policy-makers to account. Focusing only on the democratic selection of the values that enter the research that is then used to guide policy choice ignores this second purpose of policy-relevant science. This is problematic specifically in contexts of significant value disagreement. Modern democracies often find themselves confronted with irresolvable disagreement about the values at stake in a policy decision, including the types of values that are embedded in policy-relevant social scientific indicators. Still, most accounts of democracy allow for such decisions to be made without requiring that consensus is in fact reached. Likewise, we may, in a democratically legitimate way, settle on the values to be embedded in the social scientific indicators that are then used to guide specific types of policy, without in fact reaching consensus on those being the right values. However, if no other social scientific indicators than the democratically selected ones are widely available to the public and to social scientists, this raises, I argue, a problem of epistemic inequality: Only those who share the democratically selected value judgments embedded in the chosen indicators can make full and reliable use of them in public deliberation and when holding policy-makers to account. Others are at an epistemic disadvantage, since the available indicators only partially capture what they take to be important, and at worst, there may be no available measurements of the things most crucial to them given their values and interests. In an important respect, then, those others do not enter further public deliberation as equals, and are not to the same extent able to hold the government to account. While the values were, by hypothesis, originally chosen in a democratically legitimate way, there is a danger they become entrenched, undermining the good functioning of democracy going forward. What is needed to address this problem, I will argue, is for social science to aim for an output that is value pluralist, in order to help ensure a distribution of the epistemic goods needed for good public deliberation that is sufficiently equal to achieve important democratic values. In the case of the measurement of value-laden social scientific indicators, two feasible strategies to ensure greater value pluralism are the availability of publicly accessible dashboards of multiple indicators on the one hand, and tools that allow policy-makers and the public to adjust the weightings of different components of aggregate indicators, on the other. Unfortunately, this conclusion runs counter to trends in several important fields of research in policy-relevant social science, where there are ambitions of and political pressures toward a single metric to guide policy. An important upshot of my argument is that these ambitions are highly problematic from a democratic point of view. And insofar as pluralism is already practiced or advocated for in the social sciences, I provide an additional and neglected democratic justification for it. The next section will outline what I take to be some uncontroversial ideas regarding social scientific indicators, values and science to serve as a backdrop to my argument. It will draw some implications for the common ambition of a single, dominant policy-guiding indicator. Section III will spell out a first democratic challenge for such indicators, and show how it motivates existing philosophical accounts of how this democratic challenge can be addressed. I go on, in Section IV, to characterize the notion of epistemic equality at the core of my new democratic challenge, and explain how existing philosophical attempts to reconcile social science and democracy fail to address it. Section V contains my positive proposal along with examples of existing good practice. My argument in this article concerns scientific outputs that serve both an epistemic as well as a policy-guiding function. Social scientific indicators are paradigmatic examples of such scientific outputs. Let me start by outlining five uncontroversial ideas concerning social scientific indicators. Many of the most policy-relevant social scientific indicators measure “thick concepts,” which are concepts that are partly descriptive, and partly evaluative. As discussed in the introduction, “cost of living” is one such concept. Other important examples include wellbeing (more on which in what follows), economic welfare, economic inequality, poverty, and health, all of which are measured and studied by the social sciences.7 Disagreement may be about how a particular concept should be understood in a particular context. For instance, in our opening example, part of the controversy over the ONS's inflation measurements are about whether the notion of the cost of living to be measured should be the cost of consuming our actual consumption baskets, or the cost of meeting basic needs. In other domains, it may be about what it means to be poor, or healthy, or, as we'll see, about what wellbeing consists in. This is disagreement about concepts, that is, disagreement about what we should count. There is, in addition, also often disagreement about how we should count it: How do we compare the cost of living, wellbeing, health, or economic welfare of different people, and how do we aggregate them in order to study population-level effects? There are two aspects to this: First, we often need to determine how to compare and meaningfully add up two kinds of effects in the first place, how to compare apples and oranges, as it were (quite literally, in the case of inflation measurement!). Call disagreement about this disagreement about commensuration. Second, there is the question of how much weight to assign to different effects once we have in principle decided how we can compare them. The crucial question here is often how much weight to give to effects on different people, e.g., different people's wellbeing or cost of living. Call disagreement about this disagreement about aggregation. Finally, there is also often disagreement about the relative importance of the values captured by a social scientific indicator. We may, for instance, agree on what poverty is, but may disagree on how important it is relative to other policy priorities. Call this disagreement about priorities. For the purposes of this article, when people give priority to their own interests relative to others, and as a consequence favor a way of aggregating, for instance, wellbeing in a way that gives more weight to the wellbeing of people like them, I will treat this as a kind of value disagreement (where interests are not explicitly specified alongside values, this should be read to be included). And so, value disagreement in the relevant sense can be expected to be especially common where the interests of different segments of society are in conflict with one another. To some extent, the process of sharing reasons with each other may resolve some of these disagreements, especially where people's views may have been based on insufficient reflection or experience. We may come to see each other's point of view and adjust our own, regarding, for instance the nature and relative importance of poverty. However, professional philosophy provides good evidence that complete consensus on fundamental questions of value, such as, for instance, the correct theory of wellbeing, is not a realistic prospect even in an environment where the constant exchange of arguments is routine. Here, I have in mind mainly two senses in which an indicator can be aggregate: It can aggregate effects on many different people, and it can aggregate different kinds of effect. For instance, the CPI is aggregate in both respects: It aggregates the changes in the cost of living of many different people. And it also aggregates price changes of many different types of goods. Compared to disaggregated price indices for individual people or individual types of goods, this involves making additional value judgments: First, there are judgments about commensuration, about how to compare different types of effects on different people in the first place. And second, there are judgments of aggregation proper, of how much weight to give to different people and different kinds of effect. For instance, do different households count equally or proportionately to share in overall spending? These additional value judgments mean that there is more room for value disagreement, namely for what we above called disagreement about commensuration and disagreement about aggregation. This makes it less likely that consensus can be reached even in an extensive process of public deliberation. Policy-makers can only effectively serve society, and society can only engage in fruitful public deliberation, if we have reliable and usable information on what the likely consequences of the different available policy options are. Many of the most important consequences of public policy concern phenomena studied by the social sciences, and these sciences offer the best means of reliable knowledge about the effects of public policy. And so, it is commonplace, among both social scientists and philosophers of science, to treat it as a desideratum that social science should provide useful policy-guidance. While the general idea is very intuitive, on closer inspection, there are at least two important ambiguities to this desideratum. The first relates to whether what is desirable is that social science (a) studies some of the effects of policy that are choice-relevant, (b) studies all of the effects of policy that are choice-relevant, or (c) supplies a measure of how choice-worthy different policy options are all-things-considered. These differ in the extent of guidance demanded from social science. The second ambiguity arises from the fact that which effects are choice-relevant depends on the goals and values to be pursued. Some salient possibilities of what these could be are either (i) those of the actual policy-maker, (ii) those that would be decided on in a democratically legitimate process, or (iii) all policy-relevant values reasonably held by members of the population. The point of applying (i) or (ii) would be that social science should assist (democratic) public decision-making, and demands for policy-relevance have usually focused on these notions of policy-relevance. Sense (iii) is salient once we take seriously an idea explored below: that social science should also inform the public deliberation preceding public choice, and the holding to account of public decision-makers. Once we clear up these ambiguities, some of the weakest formulations of the desideratum are clearly uncontroversial: Social science should produce reliable and usable information on some of the policy effects that are choice-relevant relative to some values reasonably held by members of the population. Plausibly, they should also, in particular, produce reliable and usable information that is choice-relevant relative to the values a policy-maker is pursuing in a democratically legitimate way. As we will see, in some debates, however, the desideratum is understood in stronger terms, namely as requiring social science to produce all-things-considered measures of policy-evaluation. Call this strong policy-guidance, an idea admittedly (and fortunately) far from policy-making practice. In these discussions, the relevant values to be pursued are typically thought of as the values policy-makers are either assumed to actually have or ought to have. Such measures would provide action-guidance to policy-makers in the most direct terms. We will see below that the desideratum of strong policy-guidance is highly problematic. Ultimately, policy-makers do need to take into account all relevant effects of the policy options open to them, weigh up their relative importance and arrive at an all-things-considered judgment as to what the best policy option is. This will typically require them to perform some kind of aggregation of effects on different people and of different types, either explicitly or implicitly. Now suppose you subscribe to the desideratum of strong policy-guidance, and so take it to be desirable for the social sciences to produce measures that tell policy-makers how well different policy options serve policy-makers' goals all-things-considered. Given the need for aggregation, this implies that social science should be producing the most aggregate social scientific indicator, one single metric to integrate all positive and negative effects of different policy options on different people and of different types, to be used to directly guide public policy. This, in a nutshell, is the motivation for a number of projects in the social sciences to provide policy-makers with, in the words of Anna Alexandrova, a “master number” to guide public decision-making.8 Sometimes these projects have included efforts to push for the preferred metric of policy analysis to be integrated in the standard procedures of the administrative machinery of government. A recent phenomenon of this type is the advocacy of behavioral scientists and happiness economists subscribing to the subjective wellbeing approach to treat an aggregate subjective wellbeing metric as just such a “master number” to provide an all-things-considered evaluation of policy.9 In the United Kingdom, these efforts have had some success, with subjective wellbeing now being included in the government's Green Book.10 Note, however, that while the academic ambition in the relevant social scientific communities is a truly all-things-considered metric for policy evaluation, in practice, of course, even sympathetic policy-makers will inevitably take other things into account, in a way that is sensitive to context and the purpose at hand. Past projects that don't aim at a measure that is strictly speaking all-things-considered, but still aim at a fairly comprehensive assessment of how well a country is serving its people's interests, have been Gross Domestic Product (GDP), and, building on that measure's weaknesses, the UN's Human Development Index (HDI). Going back to our list of uncontroversial claims, one consequence of any such “master number” approach, if it insists on a single all-things-considered metric, is that there is likely going to be widespread disagreement about the values embedded in this single highly aggregate metric. The same is true, to a slightly lesser extent, of metrics that are less “all-things-considered” but yet highly aggregate. Specific measures of the cost of living, poverty, or inequality aim to capture only one type of policy-relevant effect. Still, they embed value judgments about which there is widespread disagreement. Within these domains, too, however, debate between social scientists often focuses on finding the one best metric, to then present to public decision-makers and the public as policy-guiding. This tendency toward monism within the social sciences, be it regarding a single all-things-considered “master number” or within individual sub-domains of policy interest is reinforced by political and pragmatic pressures11: political pressures to provide unambiguous policy-guidance, enabling policy-makers to say they were merely “guided by the science”; and pragmatic pressure based on the fact that the cost of the measurement of social scientific indicators, such as the measurement of inflation, is very high. The result is that in the case of many of the social and economic effects of policy, a single or a small number of indicators at once serve to guide policy and inform public debate, while alternative measures are either lacking or much less known and accessible—just think of the dominance of GDP in reporting and public deliberation about the economy. And notably, these measures by and large remain the same over time even in the face of shifts in public opinion and changes in government. The next section spells out one type of threat this phenomenon can pose to democracy, familiar from more general discussions on values in science. It will then outline philosophical accounts of the democratization of science that have aimed to address this threat, all of which aim at some form of what I call democratic alignment. I will ultimately argue that there is another democratic threat that these accounts do not sufficiently address, and which can only be countered with greater value pluralism. Consider this hypothetical example of how value-laden social science may guide policy: A social scientist develops a measure of national wellbeing, making all required value judgments on the basis of only her own moral intuitions, theorizing, and reading of the philosophical literature on wellbeing. Her theorizing remains inaccessible to the public and policy-makers, but she and her team produce both regular measurements of national wellbeing, as well as studies estimating the effects of different potential policies on national wellbeing. Policy-makers use the results of these studies in an effort to maximize national wellbeing, explaining to the public that they are merely “following the science.” This is clearly an example of a problematic kind of technocracy that runs counter to core democratic values on any normative theory of democracy. The scientist was neither publicly elected, nor is her reasoning about which values to capture with her national wellbeing measure open for public scrutiny. Her reasoning is also not responsive to the values of either the public or democratically elected public decision-makers. For the reasons discussed in the last section, it is moreover unlikely that the values the scientist ends up capturing are uncontroversial, given the aggregate nature of a measure of national wellbeing. Yet, her choice of measure ends up having a substantial effect on public policy, in a process that bypasses ordinary processes of democratic legitimization. It is clear that our imagined example is not a case of democratic decision-making—power is not exercised by the people here, either directly or indirectly. Different normative accounts of democracy explain what is bad about this in slightly different ways. One important branch of democratic theory sees democracy as a way of treating everybody as equals. There is a variety of such egalitarian conceptions of democracy. One idea is that democracy is the best way to ensure public equality, that public institutions and decision-making procedures treat everybody equally, giving everybody an equal say over how the communal aspects of our lives ought to be organized.12 Another is that democracy ensures relational equality, that citizens stand in relationships of equality to each other, and not in relations of domination and subordination.13 Technocracy of the type I described is problematically inegalitarian on each of these types of views. The social scientist has disproportionate power over her fellow citizens, being able to impose her value judgments on everybody else. This is relationally inegalitarian, and she is being given that power by the way in which public decision-making is structured. Disproportionate power is also at the heart of other potential explanations of what is bad, from a democratic perspective, about the kind of technocracy just described. According to some accounts, the crucial value of democracy consists in enabling the public justification of the institutions and policies that rule our lives.14 Public justification requires, at a minimum, that the reasons for and against different policy options are made public and subjected to a process of public deliberation among equals. But in the technocratic scenario, not only does the scientist have a disproportionate say, but the reasons for public decisions also remain opaque. Well-informed public deliberation has been emphasized more generally by advocates of the deliberative democracy movement. Aside from the ones already mentioned, it is also crucial on other prominent views of democracy. For instance, on perfectionist views of democracy, such as that put forward in Mill,15 democracy is good because it gives citizens the opportunity to exercise their moral capacities. On instrumentalist conceptions of the value of democracy, democracy is good because it tends to lead to good decisions, for which a well-informed process of public deliberation is in turn important.16 While our scientist has important technical and scientific expertise, she likely does not have significantly more expertise on questions of value than any other citizen, so that decision-making could be improved by including others in the deliberative process.17 The example I started this section with is of course only a cautionary tale. But it is not far off the vision pursued by some of the advocates of “master number” approaches discussed in the last section.18 And it highlights a certain kind of danger for policy-relevant social science more generally. The danger comes from the fact that contentious value judgments need to be made in such research, and that such research in turn often directly influences public policy. Now it might seem that to address this problem, all that needs to be ensured is that the values that enter the social scientific research are selected in a democratically more legitimate way than in our cautionary t\",\"PeriodicalId\":47999,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Philosophy & Public Affairs\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":3.3000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-10-17\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Philosophy & Public Affairs\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12250\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"ETHICS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12250","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

社会科学能在不破坏某些基本民主价值观的情况下提供政策指导吗?如果答案是“不”,那显然是毁灭性的:大多数人都深深信奉民主,以及政策决定应该由现有的最佳科学(包括现有的最佳社会科学)提供信息的观点。因此,许多担心科学与民主之间潜在紧张关系的哲学家已经站出来辩称,如果处理得当,好的科学和民主是相互支持而不是相互破坏的,约翰·杜威和菲利普·基彻就是典型的例子本文认为,与政策相关的科学面临着一个未被充分认识的民主挑战,我将在充满价值的社会科学指标的背景下具体阐述这一点。长期以来,价值负担一直被认为是调和科学与民主的障碍:它使一小部分人做出的价值判断有可能绕过民主合法化的正常过程,对政策决策产生重大影响。因此,应对这一挑战的解决方案要么捍卫价值自由的理想,2要么强调以某种方式民主地调整进入科学的价值观的必要性,这种方式与更普遍地赋予公共决策的民主合法性是平行的。许多社会科学指标的性质使得价值无关的理想完全不可行,否则我们就会放弃旨在衡量贫困、不平等或福祉的整个项目。所以在他们的情况下,似乎只有第二种常见的反应。但是,我认为,这种反应忽略了价值负担对民主构成挑战的一个重要部分。我认为,解决方案是更大程度的价值多元化,而不是民主结盟。在我写这篇文章的时候,英国和世界上许多国家一样,正面临着一场毁灭性的生活成本危机。大量家庭的收入跟不上他们消费的商品和服务价格的上涨,使越来越多的人陷入贫困。为了应对这场危机,重要的是政策制定者要对通货膨胀有一个清晰的认识——生活成本增加了多少,预计将如何进一步增加,以及不同的政策选择将如何影响变化的速度。在英国,国家统计局(ONS)提供了一系列衡量通货膨胀的指标,这些指标被决策者、要求他们承担责任的公众和媒体以及研究通货膨胀与其他社会科学变量或政策干预之间因果关系的社会科学家视为关键指标。最广泛使用和报道的指标是消费者价格指数(CPI)。但是生活成本是多少呢?首先要注意的是,它显然是一个充满价值的概念,并且被使用它的人视为这样的概念。说生活成本上升是指对价格变化前后家庭能够负担的商品种类和生活方式进行比较评估。一般来说,人们能够负担得起过得好是件好事,而生活成本变化的衡量标准旨在捕捉家庭能够做到这一点的程度。然而,很明显,有不同的方法可以使这个想法变得精确。有两种明显的方法可以使它至少在某种程度上更加精确,一种是把它看作满足一个人基本需求的成本,另一种是把它看作消费人们实际消费的东西的成本——在许多情况下,这些东西将超出满足一个人的基本需求。无论哪种情况,生活成本实际上是因人而异的。显然,不同的人实际上消费不同的东西,这些东西的价格可能会有不同程度的变化。但即使是满足基本需求的成本也可能因人而异;我需要矫正眼镜才能正常生活,而你可能不需要。尽管存在这种异质性,但对大规模政策有用的通货膨胀衡量标准需要捕捉总生活成本的变化“生活成本”概念的选择,以及如何在多样化的人口中聚集的选择,都涉及到重要的价值判断,关于什么让生活变得美好,关于谁重要多少,关于我们有权期望从彼此和国家得到什么补偿,以及关于我们的政策重点。实际的通胀指标包含了这些价值判断。在实践中,国家统计局发布的标题CPI渴望捕捉家庭实际消费的东西的价格变化它使用700种商品的代表性篮子,定期从全国不同类型的商店收集价格报价。在决定篮子中每种商品的数量时,总体CPI服从于家庭的消费决策。 更具体地说,它根据不同家庭在所有家庭总支出中所占的比例赋予不同家庭的权重,使CPI对较富裕家庭的消费决策更加敏感。近年来,反贫困活动人士对国家统计局施加了越来越大的压力,他们认为,总体通胀数据并没有很好地反映出最贫困家庭所经历的生活成本危机的程度批评的声音一方面是,国家统计局使用的标准篮子没有包括最贫困家庭满足基本需求所消费的足够多的商品,比如超市自有品牌的产品;另一方面,作为汇总效应,这些产品的较高价格上涨被较富裕家庭不成比例地消费的商品的较低价格上涨所抵消。国家统计局进行的定期分类在一定程度上可以解决第二个问题,但不能解决第一个问题。这里的核心争议在于价值观和政策优先事项:相对于通胀措施可能有助于实现的其他目的,活动人士希望在政策上更优先考虑为满足基本需求的成本增加而补偿最贫困家庭,或者从一开始就防止这种增长发生。因此,他们希望通胀措施的设计能够最大程度地服务于这些目的,而他们传统上并没有做到这一点。国家统计局目前正在做出一些改变,以更好地应对这些挑战,我们将在下面回到为了深入了解我在本文中关注的核心问题,请注意这个争议有两个层面。一方面,由于被政策导向的社会科学指标所捕捉,最终将影响公共政策的价值观存在分歧。在这方面,这场争议就像政治领域的任何其他分歧一样。但另一方面,也有人抱怨说,这场辩论的一方无法获得有助于他们在公开辩论中提出自己观点的测量方法(以及使用这些方法的科学研究),而另一方却可以。一方可以诉诸官方统计数据,抓住他们关心的问题,而另一方则需要依靠轶事证据。他们并没有平等地进入公众审议。这是一个与第一个截然不同的问题,我认为,这是一个被旨在调和民主与科学价值的文献所忽视的问题。由于下文探讨的原因,这也是一个在民主社会不太可能充分自我纠正的问题。通货膨胀指标只是一种社会科学指标,它既承载着价值,又与指导政策高度相关。如果所讨论的价值判断完全是由未经选举的社会科学家做出的,完全基于个人价值观,而不代表广大人口,那么任何合理的民主规范理论都将存在问题。在价值判断对政策产生影响的程度上,我们可能希望确保其中嵌入的价值观是以民主合法的方式选出的,就像我们的目标是确保任何重大政策决定的民主合法性一样。但是,与政策相关的科学与民主之间的关系还有另一个重要方面。与政策相关的科学产出,如社会科学指标,不仅用于为决策者的选择提供信息。它们也会反馈到公众审议中,并被用来问责政策制定者。只关注进入研究的价值的民主选择,然后用于指导政策选择,忽略了与政策相关的科学的第二个目的。这在价值观存在重大分歧的情况下尤其成问题。现代民主国家经常发现自己在一项政策决策中面临着无法解决的价值观分歧,包括与政策相关的社会科学指标中所包含的价值观类型。尽管如此,大多数关于民主的解释都允许在不要求实际上达成共识的情况下做出这样的决定。同样,我们可以以民主合法的方式确定嵌入社会科学指标的价值观,然后用来指导特定类型的政策,而实际上没有就这些价值观是否正确达成共识。然而,如果除了民主选择的指标之外,没有其他社会科学指标可供公众和社会科学家广泛使用,我认为,这就提出了一个认识不平等的问题:只有那些认同所选指标中嵌入的民主选择的价值判断的人,才能在公共审议中充分可靠地使用这些指标,并在要求政策制定者承担责任时使用它们。 下一节详细阐述了这种现象可能对民主构成的一种威胁,这种威胁在关于科学价值的更广泛讨论中很常见。然后,它将概述旨在解决这一威胁的科学民主化的哲学解释,所有这些都旨在某种形式的我称之为民主联盟。最后,我将论证,还有另一种民主威胁是这些论述没有充分解决的,而这种威胁只能通过更大的价值多元化来应对。考虑一下这个假设的充满价值的社会科学如何指导政策的例子:一个社会科学家开发了一种衡量国民福祉的方法,仅根据她自己的道德直觉,理论化和阅读关于福祉的哲学文献,做出所有必要的价值判断。公众和政策制定者仍然无法了解她的理论,但她和她的团队既对国民福祉进行了定期测量,也对不同潜在政策对国民福祉的影响进行了评估。政策制定者利用这些研究的结果来最大限度地提高国民的福祉,向公众解释他们只是“遵循科学”。这显然是一个有问题的技术官僚主义的例子,它与任何民主规范理论的核心民主价值观背道而驰。这位科学家既不是由公众选举产生的,她关于用她的国家福祉衡量标准来衡量哪些价值观的推理也没有公开供公众监督。她的推理也不符合公众或民主选举的公共决策者的价值观。鉴于上一节讨论的原因,考虑到衡量国民福祉的总体性质,科学家最终捕获的价值观不太可能没有争议。然而,她选择的措施最终对公共政策产生了实质性影响,这一过程绕过了民主合法化的一般过程。很明显,我们想象中的例子不是民主决策的例子- -这里的人民没有直接或间接地行使权力。对民主的不同规范描述以略微不同的方式解释了民主的坏处。民主理论的一个重要分支认为,民主是平等对待每个人的一种方式。有各种平等主义的民主概念。一种观点认为,民主是确保公共平等的最佳方式,公共机构和决策程序平等对待每个人,在如何组织我们生活的公共方面给予每个人平等的发言权另一个是民主确保关系平等,即公民之间处于平等的关系中,而不是处于支配和从属的关系中从这两种观点来看,我所描述的技术官僚都是有问题的不平等主义。社会科学家对她的同胞拥有不成比例的权力,能够将她的价值判断强加给其他人。这在关系上是不平等的,她被赋予这种权力是因为公共决策的结构。从民主的角度来看,对于刚刚描述的那种技术官僚政治,不成比例的权力也是其他潜在解释的核心。根据一些说法,民主的关键价值在于使统治我们生活的制度和政策能够得到公众的认可公开辩护至少需要公开支持和反对不同政策选择的理由,并经过平等的公众审议过程。但在技术官僚的情况下,不仅科学家有不成比例的发言权,而且公共决策的原因也仍然不透明。协商民主运动的倡导者更普遍地强调知情的公众审议。除了前面提到的,它对其他重要的民主观点也至关重要。例如,在密尔所提出的完美主义民主观点中,民主是好的,因为它给公民机会行使他们的道德能力。根据民主价值的工具主义概念,民主是好的,因为它往往会导致良好的决策,而对这些决策来说,信息灵通的公众审议过程反过来也很重要虽然我们的科学家有重要的技术和科学专业知识,但在有价值的问题上,她可能并不比任何其他公民有更多的专业知识,因此,通过让其他人参与审议过程,可以改进决策我在本节开头举的例子当然只是一个警示故事。但它与上一节讨论的“主数”方法的一些倡导者所追求的愿景相差不远。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Social Science, Policy and Democracy
Can social science provide policy-guidance without undermining some basic democratic values? It would clearly be devastating if the answer was “no”: Most people are deeply committed both to democracy, as well as to the idea that policy decisions should be informed by the best available science, including the best available social science. Accordingly, the many philosophers who have worried about potential tensions between science and democracy have come out arguing that, if done right, good science and democracy mutually support rather than undermine each other, John Dewey and Philip Kitcher being paradigmatic examples.1 This article argues that there is an under-appreciated democratic challenge for policy-relevant science, which I will articulate specifically in the context of value-laden social scientific indicators. Value-ladenness has long been acknowledged to pose an obstacle for reconciling science and democracy: It creates the potential for the value judgments made by a small subset of the population to have a significant impact on policy decisions, in a way that bypasses normal processes of democratic legitimization. Consequently, solutions to this challenge have either defended the value-free ideal,2 or stressed the need to, in one way or another, democratically align the values entering science, in a way that is parallel to how democratic legitimacy is given to public decision-making more generally. The nature of many social scientific indicators makes the value-free ideal wholly unworkable, lest we give up the entire project of aiming to measure poverty, inequality, or wellbeing. And so only the second common type of response seems to be available in their case. But, I will argue, this response misses a significant part of the challenge value-ladenness poses to democracy. The solution, I will argue, is greater value pluralism rather than democratic alignment. As I write, the United Kingdom, like many countries around the world, is facing a devastating cost of living crisis. The incomes of large numbers of households cannot keep up with the rising prices of the goods and services they consume, pushing increasing numbers into poverty. To tackle this crisis, it is important that policy-makers have a clear picture of inflation—of how much the cost of living has increased, how it is projected to further increase, and how different policy options will affect the rate of change. In the United Kingdom, the Office of National Statistics (ONS) supplies a number of measures of inflation that are treated as key indicators by policy-makers, by the public and media holding them to account, and by social scientists studying the causal relationships between inflation and other social scientific variables or policy interventions. The most widely used and reported indicator is the Consumer Price Index (CPI). But what is the cost of living? The first thing to note is that it is clearly a value-laden concept and treated as such by those using it. Saying that the cost of living has gone up involves making a comparative evaluation of the kinds of goods and lifestyles that can be afforded by households before and after changes in prices. In the most general terms, it is good for people to be able to afford to live well, and measures of changes in the cost of living aim to capture the extent to which households can do that. Clearly, however, there are different ways of making this idea precise. Two salient ways of making it at least somewhat more precise would be to either think of it as the cost of meeting one's basic needs, or to conceive of it as the cost of consuming the kinds of things one is actually consuming—which in many cases will go beyond meeting one's basic needs. In either case, the cost of living in fact differs between different people. Clearly, different people actually consume different things, the prices of which may change to different extents. But even the cost of meeting basic needs may differ between different people; I need corrective lenses to function in daily life, while you may not. A measure of inflation useful for large scale policy needs to capture changes in the aggregate cost of living despite this heterogeneity.3 Both the choice of concept of “cost of living” as well as choices about how to aggregate over a diverse population involve important value judgments, about what makes life good, about who matters how much, about what we are entitled to expect compensation for from each other and the state, and about our policy priorities. Actual measures of inflation embed these value judgments. In practice, the headline CPI published by the ONS aspires to capture changes in the prices of the things households are actually consuming.4 It uses a representative basket of 700 goods, regularly collecting price quotations from different kinds of outlets all over the country. In deciding on the quantities of each good in the basket, the headline CPI defers to the consumption decisions of households. More specifically, it gives weight to different households in proportion to their share of the total expenditure of all households, making the CPI more sensitive to the consumption decisions of richer households. The ONS has been under increased pressure from anti-poverty campaigners in recent years arguing that the headline inflation figures do not capture well the extent of the cost of living crisis experienced by the poorest households.5 The criticism is both that the standard basket used by the ONS does not include enough of the items the poorest households are consuming to meet basic needs, such as supermarket own-brand products, and that, as an effect of aggregation, higher price increases on those products are washed out by lower price increases in the goods disproportionately consumed by richer households. Periodic disaggregation carried out by the ONS can address the second concern to some extent, but not the first. The central controversy here is at heart about values and policy priorities: Relative to the other purposes inflation measures may help to serve, campaigners want greater policy priority given to compensating the worst-off households for increases in the cost of meeting basic needs, or to preventing such increases from happening in the first place. Consequently, they want inflation measures to be designed for serving those purposes to the greatest extent possible, which they traditionally have not. The ONS is currently making some changes to address these challenges better, to which we will return below.6 To get to the heart of my concern in this article, note that there are two levels to this controversy. On the one hand, there is disagreement about the values that, in virtue of being captured by policy-guiding social scientific indicators, will end up shaping public policy. In that respect, the controversy is much like any other disagreement in the political sphere. But on the other hand, there is also the complaint that one side to this debate does not have access to the measurements (and scientific studies employing them) that would help them make their case in public debate, while the other side does. One side can appeal to official statistics capturing what they care about, while the other needs to rely on evidence that remains anecdotal. They are not entering public deliberation as equals. This is a distinct issue from the first, and, I argue, one that is neglected by the literature aiming to reconcile democracy and the value-ladenness of science. It is also an issue that, for reasons explored below, is unlikely to sufficiently self-correct in democratic societies. Measures of inflation are just one type of social scientific indicator that is at once value-laden, and highly relevant for guiding policy. Were it the case that the value judgments in question were made entirely by unelected social scientists, based exclusively on personal values unrepresentative of the population at large, this would be problematic on any plausible normative theory of democracy. To the extent that value judgments have an impact on policy, we may want to ensure that the values embedded in them are picked in a democratically legitimate way, just like we aim to ensure democratic legitimacy for any significant policy decision. But there is another important aspect of the relationship between policy-relevant science and democracy. The outputs of policy-relevant science, such as social scientific indicators, are not only used to inform the choices of policy-makers. They also feed back into public deliberation, and are used to hold policy-makers to account. Focusing only on the democratic selection of the values that enter the research that is then used to guide policy choice ignores this second purpose of policy-relevant science. This is problematic specifically in contexts of significant value disagreement. Modern democracies often find themselves confronted with irresolvable disagreement about the values at stake in a policy decision, including the types of values that are embedded in policy-relevant social scientific indicators. Still, most accounts of democracy allow for such decisions to be made without requiring that consensus is in fact reached. Likewise, we may, in a democratically legitimate way, settle on the values to be embedded in the social scientific indicators that are then used to guide specific types of policy, without in fact reaching consensus on those being the right values. However, if no other social scientific indicators than the democratically selected ones are widely available to the public and to social scientists, this raises, I argue, a problem of epistemic inequality: Only those who share the democratically selected value judgments embedded in the chosen indicators can make full and reliable use of them in public deliberation and when holding policy-makers to account. Others are at an epistemic disadvantage, since the available indicators only partially capture what they take to be important, and at worst, there may be no available measurements of the things most crucial to them given their values and interests. In an important respect, then, those others do not enter further public deliberation as equals, and are not to the same extent able to hold the government to account. While the values were, by hypothesis, originally chosen in a democratically legitimate way, there is a danger they become entrenched, undermining the good functioning of democracy going forward. What is needed to address this problem, I will argue, is for social science to aim for an output that is value pluralist, in order to help ensure a distribution of the epistemic goods needed for good public deliberation that is sufficiently equal to achieve important democratic values. In the case of the measurement of value-laden social scientific indicators, two feasible strategies to ensure greater value pluralism are the availability of publicly accessible dashboards of multiple indicators on the one hand, and tools that allow policy-makers and the public to adjust the weightings of different components of aggregate indicators, on the other. Unfortunately, this conclusion runs counter to trends in several important fields of research in policy-relevant social science, where there are ambitions of and political pressures toward a single metric to guide policy. An important upshot of my argument is that these ambitions are highly problematic from a democratic point of view. And insofar as pluralism is already practiced or advocated for in the social sciences, I provide an additional and neglected democratic justification for it. The next section will outline what I take to be some uncontroversial ideas regarding social scientific indicators, values and science to serve as a backdrop to my argument. It will draw some implications for the common ambition of a single, dominant policy-guiding indicator. Section III will spell out a first democratic challenge for such indicators, and show how it motivates existing philosophical accounts of how this democratic challenge can be addressed. I go on, in Section IV, to characterize the notion of epistemic equality at the core of my new democratic challenge, and explain how existing philosophical attempts to reconcile social science and democracy fail to address it. Section V contains my positive proposal along with examples of existing good practice. My argument in this article concerns scientific outputs that serve both an epistemic as well as a policy-guiding function. Social scientific indicators are paradigmatic examples of such scientific outputs. Let me start by outlining five uncontroversial ideas concerning social scientific indicators. Many of the most policy-relevant social scientific indicators measure “thick concepts,” which are concepts that are partly descriptive, and partly evaluative. As discussed in the introduction, “cost of living” is one such concept. Other important examples include wellbeing (more on which in what follows), economic welfare, economic inequality, poverty, and health, all of which are measured and studied by the social sciences.7 Disagreement may be about how a particular concept should be understood in a particular context. For instance, in our opening example, part of the controversy over the ONS's inflation measurements are about whether the notion of the cost of living to be measured should be the cost of consuming our actual consumption baskets, or the cost of meeting basic needs. In other domains, it may be about what it means to be poor, or healthy, or, as we'll see, about what wellbeing consists in. This is disagreement about concepts, that is, disagreement about what we should count. There is, in addition, also often disagreement about how we should count it: How do we compare the cost of living, wellbeing, health, or economic welfare of different people, and how do we aggregate them in order to study population-level effects? There are two aspects to this: First, we often need to determine how to compare and meaningfully add up two kinds of effects in the first place, how to compare apples and oranges, as it were (quite literally, in the case of inflation measurement!). Call disagreement about this disagreement about commensuration. Second, there is the question of how much weight to assign to different effects once we have in principle decided how we can compare them. The crucial question here is often how much weight to give to effects on different people, e.g., different people's wellbeing or cost of living. Call disagreement about this disagreement about aggregation. Finally, there is also often disagreement about the relative importance of the values captured by a social scientific indicator. We may, for instance, agree on what poverty is, but may disagree on how important it is relative to other policy priorities. Call this disagreement about priorities. For the purposes of this article, when people give priority to their own interests relative to others, and as a consequence favor a way of aggregating, for instance, wellbeing in a way that gives more weight to the wellbeing of people like them, I will treat this as a kind of value disagreement (where interests are not explicitly specified alongside values, this should be read to be included). And so, value disagreement in the relevant sense can be expected to be especially common where the interests of different segments of society are in conflict with one another. To some extent, the process of sharing reasons with each other may resolve some of these disagreements, especially where people's views may have been based on insufficient reflection or experience. We may come to see each other's point of view and adjust our own, regarding, for instance the nature and relative importance of poverty. However, professional philosophy provides good evidence that complete consensus on fundamental questions of value, such as, for instance, the correct theory of wellbeing, is not a realistic prospect even in an environment where the constant exchange of arguments is routine. Here, I have in mind mainly two senses in which an indicator can be aggregate: It can aggregate effects on many different people, and it can aggregate different kinds of effect. For instance, the CPI is aggregate in both respects: It aggregates the changes in the cost of living of many different people. And it also aggregates price changes of many different types of goods. Compared to disaggregated price indices for individual people or individual types of goods, this involves making additional value judgments: First, there are judgments about commensuration, about how to compare different types of effects on different people in the first place. And second, there are judgments of aggregation proper, of how much weight to give to different people and different kinds of effect. For instance, do different households count equally or proportionately to share in overall spending? These additional value judgments mean that there is more room for value disagreement, namely for what we above called disagreement about commensuration and disagreement about aggregation. This makes it less likely that consensus can be reached even in an extensive process of public deliberation. Policy-makers can only effectively serve society, and society can only engage in fruitful public deliberation, if we have reliable and usable information on what the likely consequences of the different available policy options are. Many of the most important consequences of public policy concern phenomena studied by the social sciences, and these sciences offer the best means of reliable knowledge about the effects of public policy. And so, it is commonplace, among both social scientists and philosophers of science, to treat it as a desideratum that social science should provide useful policy-guidance. While the general idea is very intuitive, on closer inspection, there are at least two important ambiguities to this desideratum. The first relates to whether what is desirable is that social science (a) studies some of the effects of policy that are choice-relevant, (b) studies all of the effects of policy that are choice-relevant, or (c) supplies a measure of how choice-worthy different policy options are all-things-considered. These differ in the extent of guidance demanded from social science. The second ambiguity arises from the fact that which effects are choice-relevant depends on the goals and values to be pursued. Some salient possibilities of what these could be are either (i) those of the actual policy-maker, (ii) those that would be decided on in a democratically legitimate process, or (iii) all policy-relevant values reasonably held by members of the population. The point of applying (i) or (ii) would be that social science should assist (democratic) public decision-making, and demands for policy-relevance have usually focused on these notions of policy-relevance. Sense (iii) is salient once we take seriously an idea explored below: that social science should also inform the public deliberation preceding public choice, and the holding to account of public decision-makers. Once we clear up these ambiguities, some of the weakest formulations of the desideratum are clearly uncontroversial: Social science should produce reliable and usable information on some of the policy effects that are choice-relevant relative to some values reasonably held by members of the population. Plausibly, they should also, in particular, produce reliable and usable information that is choice-relevant relative to the values a policy-maker is pursuing in a democratically legitimate way. As we will see, in some debates, however, the desideratum is understood in stronger terms, namely as requiring social science to produce all-things-considered measures of policy-evaluation. Call this strong policy-guidance, an idea admittedly (and fortunately) far from policy-making practice. In these discussions, the relevant values to be pursued are typically thought of as the values policy-makers are either assumed to actually have or ought to have. Such measures would provide action-guidance to policy-makers in the most direct terms. We will see below that the desideratum of strong policy-guidance is highly problematic. Ultimately, policy-makers do need to take into account all relevant effects of the policy options open to them, weigh up their relative importance and arrive at an all-things-considered judgment as to what the best policy option is. This will typically require them to perform some kind of aggregation of effects on different people and of different types, either explicitly or implicitly. Now suppose you subscribe to the desideratum of strong policy-guidance, and so take it to be desirable for the social sciences to produce measures that tell policy-makers how well different policy options serve policy-makers' goals all-things-considered. Given the need for aggregation, this implies that social science should be producing the most aggregate social scientific indicator, one single metric to integrate all positive and negative effects of different policy options on different people and of different types, to be used to directly guide public policy. This, in a nutshell, is the motivation for a number of projects in the social sciences to provide policy-makers with, in the words of Anna Alexandrova, a “master number” to guide public decision-making.8 Sometimes these projects have included efforts to push for the preferred metric of policy analysis to be integrated in the standard procedures of the administrative machinery of government. A recent phenomenon of this type is the advocacy of behavioral scientists and happiness economists subscribing to the subjective wellbeing approach to treat an aggregate subjective wellbeing metric as just such a “master number” to provide an all-things-considered evaluation of policy.9 In the United Kingdom, these efforts have had some success, with subjective wellbeing now being included in the government's Green Book.10 Note, however, that while the academic ambition in the relevant social scientific communities is a truly all-things-considered metric for policy evaluation, in practice, of course, even sympathetic policy-makers will inevitably take other things into account, in a way that is sensitive to context and the purpose at hand. Past projects that don't aim at a measure that is strictly speaking all-things-considered, but still aim at a fairly comprehensive assessment of how well a country is serving its people's interests, have been Gross Domestic Product (GDP), and, building on that measure's weaknesses, the UN's Human Development Index (HDI). Going back to our list of uncontroversial claims, one consequence of any such “master number” approach, if it insists on a single all-things-considered metric, is that there is likely going to be widespread disagreement about the values embedded in this single highly aggregate metric. The same is true, to a slightly lesser extent, of metrics that are less “all-things-considered” but yet highly aggregate. Specific measures of the cost of living, poverty, or inequality aim to capture only one type of policy-relevant effect. Still, they embed value judgments about which there is widespread disagreement. Within these domains, too, however, debate between social scientists often focuses on finding the one best metric, to then present to public decision-makers and the public as policy-guiding. This tendency toward monism within the social sciences, be it regarding a single all-things-considered “master number” or within individual sub-domains of policy interest is reinforced by political and pragmatic pressures11: political pressures to provide unambiguous policy-guidance, enabling policy-makers to say they were merely “guided by the science”; and pragmatic pressure based on the fact that the cost of the measurement of social scientific indicators, such as the measurement of inflation, is very high. The result is that in the case of many of the social and economic effects of policy, a single or a small number of indicators at once serve to guide policy and inform public debate, while alternative measures are either lacking or much less known and accessible—just think of the dominance of GDP in reporting and public deliberation about the economy. And notably, these measures by and large remain the same over time even in the face of shifts in public opinion and changes in government. The next section spells out one type of threat this phenomenon can pose to democracy, familiar from more general discussions on values in science. It will then outline philosophical accounts of the democratization of science that have aimed to address this threat, all of which aim at some form of what I call democratic alignment. I will ultimately argue that there is another democratic threat that these accounts do not sufficiently address, and which can only be countered with greater value pluralism. Consider this hypothetical example of how value-laden social science may guide policy: A social scientist develops a measure of national wellbeing, making all required value judgments on the basis of only her own moral intuitions, theorizing, and reading of the philosophical literature on wellbeing. Her theorizing remains inaccessible to the public and policy-makers, but she and her team produce both regular measurements of national wellbeing, as well as studies estimating the effects of different potential policies on national wellbeing. Policy-makers use the results of these studies in an effort to maximize national wellbeing, explaining to the public that they are merely “following the science.” This is clearly an example of a problematic kind of technocracy that runs counter to core democratic values on any normative theory of democracy. The scientist was neither publicly elected, nor is her reasoning about which values to capture with her national wellbeing measure open for public scrutiny. Her reasoning is also not responsive to the values of either the public or democratically elected public decision-makers. For the reasons discussed in the last section, it is moreover unlikely that the values the scientist ends up capturing are uncontroversial, given the aggregate nature of a measure of national wellbeing. Yet, her choice of measure ends up having a substantial effect on public policy, in a process that bypasses ordinary processes of democratic legitimization. It is clear that our imagined example is not a case of democratic decision-making—power is not exercised by the people here, either directly or indirectly. Different normative accounts of democracy explain what is bad about this in slightly different ways. One important branch of democratic theory sees democracy as a way of treating everybody as equals. There is a variety of such egalitarian conceptions of democracy. One idea is that democracy is the best way to ensure public equality, that public institutions and decision-making procedures treat everybody equally, giving everybody an equal say over how the communal aspects of our lives ought to be organized.12 Another is that democracy ensures relational equality, that citizens stand in relationships of equality to each other, and not in relations of domination and subordination.13 Technocracy of the type I described is problematically inegalitarian on each of these types of views. The social scientist has disproportionate power over her fellow citizens, being able to impose her value judgments on everybody else. This is relationally inegalitarian, and she is being given that power by the way in which public decision-making is structured. Disproportionate power is also at the heart of other potential explanations of what is bad, from a democratic perspective, about the kind of technocracy just described. According to some accounts, the crucial value of democracy consists in enabling the public justification of the institutions and policies that rule our lives.14 Public justification requires, at a minimum, that the reasons for and against different policy options are made public and subjected to a process of public deliberation among equals. But in the technocratic scenario, not only does the scientist have a disproportionate say, but the reasons for public decisions also remain opaque. Well-informed public deliberation has been emphasized more generally by advocates of the deliberative democracy movement. Aside from the ones already mentioned, it is also crucial on other prominent views of democracy. For instance, on perfectionist views of democracy, such as that put forward in Mill,15 democracy is good because it gives citizens the opportunity to exercise their moral capacities. On instrumentalist conceptions of the value of democracy, democracy is good because it tends to lead to good decisions, for which a well-informed process of public deliberation is in turn important.16 While our scientist has important technical and scientific expertise, she likely does not have significantly more expertise on questions of value than any other citizen, so that decision-making could be improved by including others in the deliberative process.17 The example I started this section with is of course only a cautionary tale. But it is not far off the vision pursued by some of the advocates of “master number” approaches discussed in the last section.18 And it highlights a certain kind of danger for policy-relevant social science more generally. The danger comes from the fact that contentious value judgments need to be made in such research, and that such research in turn often directly influences public policy. Now it might seem that to address this problem, all that needs to be ensured is that the values that enter the social scientific research are selected in a democratically more legitimate way than in our cautionary t
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
3.90
自引率
4.50%
发文量
23
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信