未知的同行

IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Marc Andree Weber
{"title":"未知的同行","authors":"Marc Andree Weber","doi":"10.1080/09672559.2023.2263711","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTUnknown peers create a problem for those epistemologists who argue that we should be conciliatory in cases of peer disagreement. The standard interpretation of ‘being conciliatory’ has it that we should revise our opinions concerning a specific subject matter whenever we encounter someone who is as competent and well informed as we are concerning this subject matter (and thus is our peer) and holds a different opinion. As a consequence, peers whom we have never encountered and who are hence unknown to us are not taken into account. This, however, appears odd; not only because it is an accidental matter which peers we happen to encounter and which not, but also because it would allow people to deliberately isolate themselves from any kind of intellectual exchange on the topic under consideration. The paper argues that we should take the problem of unknown peers seriously, and that disregarding the problem is an instance of the more general mistake of assuming that evidential quality and justified believability can be dealt with separately. Moreover, a solution to the problem of unknown peers is suggested.KEYWORDS: EpistemologyevidencedisagreementpeersEqual Weight Viewjustification AcknowledgementThe paper benefitted a lot from comments and impulses by Wolfgang Freitag (who also convinced me of the need to clarify how EW is to be defined), Sanford Goldberg, Jonathan Matheson, Christoph Schamberger, Nadja-Mira Yolcu, Elia Zardini, Q1 Alexandra Zinke, and several anonymous referees.Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. For the purpose of the present paper, this rough characterization of epistemic peerhood suffices. See, e.g., Matheson (Citation2015, 24–25), Elga (Citation2007, 499, fn. 21), King (Citation2011), Vorobej (Citation2011), and my Weber (Citation2017b) for a more detailed discussion of the concept.2. See Lasonen-Aarnio (Citation2014, 317) and Rosenkranz and Schulz (Citation2015, 570–572).3. Analogously, it does not speak against the A-Variant that it is compatible with giving no weight to both one’s own view and that of one’s epistemic peer. For it does not follow that one could instead focus on first-order evidence alone, since one cannot consider first-order evidence withing interpreting it, which means that there must be at least one person to whose interpretation one gives more than zero weight. This person need not be oneself or one’s peer: arguably, giving no weight to both one’s own view and that of one’s epistemic peer is exactly what one should do if there is an epistemic superior regarding the matter under debate.4. A case in point is Kelly (Citation2010, 112).5. David Enoch also distinguishes what I call the A-, B-, and C-Variant and argues for the latter; see Enoch (Citation2010, 970–972).6. This position is usually called the Right Reasons View. For versions this view, see Kelly (Citation2005, 180) and Titelbaum (Citation2015). A strong externalist element is also part of Lackey’s justificationist view (see especially Lackey Citation2010, 320) as well as of Weatherson’s evidence aggregation view (Weatherson Citation2019, ch. 12).7. See, e.g., Hall and Johnson (Citation1998) for a vindication of a strong epistemic version of this principle.8. We should bear in mind that there are experts who hardly ever attend conferences or publish papers, although they are among the best of their profession. This may occur more often in philosophy or mathematics than in those sciences in which research depends, at least partly, on expensive equipment. (I guess many of us know some philosopher who is an expert in a certain field but has never published anything noticeable on it – someone like Gettier, but without a famous three-page paper).9. There is an ongoing discussion about whether numbers matter, i.e., whether we should, in case of a peer disagreement, adopt the belief held by the majority, or whether we should withhold belief even if there is a clear majority among mutually independent peers for one of the contested positions. See Lackey (Citation2013) for a vindication of the former view. In Weber unpublished, I argue for the latter. If numbers do not matter, it is harder to rule out the existence of a peer disagreement that would require belief revision.10. Strictly speaking, two steps are to be distinguished: One should first interview people to find out whether they are one’s epistemic peers or even superiors concerning the relevant domain, and then discuss the specific matter one is interested in with one’s peers or superiors (if there are any). For ease of presentation, I will simply say in what follows that one should talk to all philosophers if the matter under debate is of philosophical nature, talk to all biologists if the matter under debate concerns biology, etc.11. A common feature of these disagreements is that they are what Goldberg calls systematic. Systematic disagreements are non-local insofar as they extend to neighbouring issues as well, widespread insofar as they occur between two or more large groups of people, and entrenched insofar as they have persisted for quite some time, with each side continuing to defend and advance their position (see Goldberg Citation2013). There are, however, systematic disagreements on matters that need to be decided sooner rather than later, so that we then are allowed to stop gathering potentially relevant evidence for pragmatic reasons (although we may not be allowed to form decisive beliefs about the controversial issue).12. Ballantyne would disagree; see his (Citation2015). Ballantyne’s argument also involves samples that are claimed to be not representative. As his samples are samples of pieces of evidence and not, as in the present paper, samples of experts, his argument differs from mine to a great extent. For example, while pieces of evidence have to be balanced according to their quality, this is not what proponents of EW want to do with expert opinions in cases of a peer disagreement.13. My line of reasoning for this thesis is an indirect argument: it claims that rival positions have unbearable consequences, so that we have to adopt the Equipotence Thesis as the only way out. There are also direct arguments for this thesis (most notably in Kelly Citation2005) as well as objections to them (most notably in Christensen Citation2007), but I cannot discuss them here due to lack of space. See instead Weber Citation2017a. My purpose in the present paper is not to establish the Equipotence Thesis – in order to do this, one has to discuss all its pros and cons – but to present one single argument in its favour.14. See Williamson (Citation2000, 192) for a detailed vindication of an almost identical claim.Additional informationFundingThe publication of this work was made possible with funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under grant agreement No 870883. Research for this paper was funded by the Volkswagen Foundation.","PeriodicalId":51828,"journal":{"name":"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"6 1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2023-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Unknown Peers\",\"authors\":\"Marc Andree Weber\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/09672559.2023.2263711\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"ABSTRACTUnknown peers create a problem for those epistemologists who argue that we should be conciliatory in cases of peer disagreement. The standard interpretation of ‘being conciliatory’ has it that we should revise our opinions concerning a specific subject matter whenever we encounter someone who is as competent and well informed as we are concerning this subject matter (and thus is our peer) and holds a different opinion. As a consequence, peers whom we have never encountered and who are hence unknown to us are not taken into account. This, however, appears odd; not only because it is an accidental matter which peers we happen to encounter and which not, but also because it would allow people to deliberately isolate themselves from any kind of intellectual exchange on the topic under consideration. The paper argues that we should take the problem of unknown peers seriously, and that disregarding the problem is an instance of the more general mistake of assuming that evidential quality and justified believability can be dealt with separately. Moreover, a solution to the problem of unknown peers is suggested.KEYWORDS: EpistemologyevidencedisagreementpeersEqual Weight Viewjustification AcknowledgementThe paper benefitted a lot from comments and impulses by Wolfgang Freitag (who also convinced me of the need to clarify how EW is to be defined), Sanford Goldberg, Jonathan Matheson, Christoph Schamberger, Nadja-Mira Yolcu, Elia Zardini, Q1 Alexandra Zinke, and several anonymous referees.Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. For the purpose of the present paper, this rough characterization of epistemic peerhood suffices. See, e.g., Matheson (Citation2015, 24–25), Elga (Citation2007, 499, fn. 21), King (Citation2011), Vorobej (Citation2011), and my Weber (Citation2017b) for a more detailed discussion of the concept.2. See Lasonen-Aarnio (Citation2014, 317) and Rosenkranz and Schulz (Citation2015, 570–572).3. Analogously, it does not speak against the A-Variant that it is compatible with giving no weight to both one’s own view and that of one’s epistemic peer. For it does not follow that one could instead focus on first-order evidence alone, since one cannot consider first-order evidence withing interpreting it, which means that there must be at least one person to whose interpretation one gives more than zero weight. This person need not be oneself or one’s peer: arguably, giving no weight to both one’s own view and that of one’s epistemic peer is exactly what one should do if there is an epistemic superior regarding the matter under debate.4. A case in point is Kelly (Citation2010, 112).5. David Enoch also distinguishes what I call the A-, B-, and C-Variant and argues for the latter; see Enoch (Citation2010, 970–972).6. This position is usually called the Right Reasons View. For versions this view, see Kelly (Citation2005, 180) and Titelbaum (Citation2015). A strong externalist element is also part of Lackey’s justificationist view (see especially Lackey Citation2010, 320) as well as of Weatherson’s evidence aggregation view (Weatherson Citation2019, ch. 12).7. See, e.g., Hall and Johnson (Citation1998) for a vindication of a strong epistemic version of this principle.8. We should bear in mind that there are experts who hardly ever attend conferences or publish papers, although they are among the best of their profession. This may occur more often in philosophy or mathematics than in those sciences in which research depends, at least partly, on expensive equipment. (I guess many of us know some philosopher who is an expert in a certain field but has never published anything noticeable on it – someone like Gettier, but without a famous three-page paper).9. There is an ongoing discussion about whether numbers matter, i.e., whether we should, in case of a peer disagreement, adopt the belief held by the majority, or whether we should withhold belief even if there is a clear majority among mutually independent peers for one of the contested positions. See Lackey (Citation2013) for a vindication of the former view. In Weber unpublished, I argue for the latter. If numbers do not matter, it is harder to rule out the existence of a peer disagreement that would require belief revision.10. Strictly speaking, two steps are to be distinguished: One should first interview people to find out whether they are one’s epistemic peers or even superiors concerning the relevant domain, and then discuss the specific matter one is interested in with one’s peers or superiors (if there are any). For ease of presentation, I will simply say in what follows that one should talk to all philosophers if the matter under debate is of philosophical nature, talk to all biologists if the matter under debate concerns biology, etc.11. A common feature of these disagreements is that they are what Goldberg calls systematic. Systematic disagreements are non-local insofar as they extend to neighbouring issues as well, widespread insofar as they occur between two or more large groups of people, and entrenched insofar as they have persisted for quite some time, with each side continuing to defend and advance their position (see Goldberg Citation2013). There are, however, systematic disagreements on matters that need to be decided sooner rather than later, so that we then are allowed to stop gathering potentially relevant evidence for pragmatic reasons (although we may not be allowed to form decisive beliefs about the controversial issue).12. Ballantyne would disagree; see his (Citation2015). Ballantyne’s argument also involves samples that are claimed to be not representative. As his samples are samples of pieces of evidence and not, as in the present paper, samples of experts, his argument differs from mine to a great extent. For example, while pieces of evidence have to be balanced according to their quality, this is not what proponents of EW want to do with expert opinions in cases of a peer disagreement.13. My line of reasoning for this thesis is an indirect argument: it claims that rival positions have unbearable consequences, so that we have to adopt the Equipotence Thesis as the only way out. There are also direct arguments for this thesis (most notably in Kelly Citation2005) as well as objections to them (most notably in Christensen Citation2007), but I cannot discuss them here due to lack of space. See instead Weber Citation2017a. My purpose in the present paper is not to establish the Equipotence Thesis – in order to do this, one has to discuss all its pros and cons – but to present one single argument in its favour.14. See Williamson (Citation2000, 192) for a detailed vindication of an almost identical claim.Additional informationFundingThe publication of this work was made possible with funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under grant agreement No 870883. Research for this paper was funded by the Volkswagen Foundation.\",\"PeriodicalId\":51828,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES\",\"volume\":\"6 1 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-05-27\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2023.2263711\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2023.2263711","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

不知名的同伴给那些认识论家带来了一个问题,他们认为我们应该在同伴分歧的情况下进行调解。“和解”的标准解释是,每当我们遇到与我们一样有能力和消息灵通的人(因此是我们的同行)并持有不同意见时,我们就应该修改我们对特定主题的意见。因此,那些我们从未见过、因此不认识的同伴就没有被考虑在内。然而,这看起来很奇怪;不仅因为我们碰巧遇到哪些同伴,哪些没有,这是一个偶然的问题,而且还因为它会让人们故意将自己与正在考虑的话题的任何智力交流隔绝开来。这篇论文认为,我们应该认真对待未知同行的问题,忽视这个问题是一个更普遍的错误的例子,即假设证据质量和合理的可信度可以分开处理。此外,还提出了未知对等体问题的解决方案。本文从Wolfgang Freitag(他也让我相信有必要澄清EW的定义)、Sanford Goldberg、Jonathan Matheson、Christoph Schamberger、Nadja-Mira Yolcu、Elia Zardini、Q1 Alexandra Zinke和几位匿名审稿人的评论和推动中获益良多。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。对于本文的目的而言,这种对认知对等的粗略描述就足够了。参见Matheson (Citation2015, 24-25), Elga (Citation2007, 499, fn)。21), King (Citation2011), Vorobej (Citation2011)和我的Weber (Citation2017b)对这个概念进行了更详细的讨论。参见Lasonen-Aarnio (Citation2014, 317)和Rosenkranz and Schulz (Citation2015, 570-572)。类似地,它并不反对a变体,因为它与不重视自己的观点和认识论同行的观点是相容的。因为这并不意味着人们可以转而只关注一阶证据,因为人们不能在解释一阶证据时考虑它,这意味着必须至少有一个人对其解释给予超过零的权重。这个人不必是自己或自己的同行:可以说,如果在争论的问题上有一个认识上的优势,那么一个人就应该既不重视自己的观点,也不重视认识上的同行的观点。一个恰当的例子是Kelly (Citation2010, 112)。David Enoch也区分了我所说的A-, B-和c -变体,并支持后者;参见以诺(Citation2010, 970-972)。这一立场通常被称为正确理由观点。有关此视图的版本,请参阅Kelly (Citation2005, 180)和Titelbaum (Citation2015)。强烈的外在主义元素也是拉基的辩护主义观点的一部分(特别是参见拉基引文2010,320),以及威瑟森的证据聚合观点(威瑟森引文2019,第12章)。例如,参见Hall和Johnson (Citation1998)对这一原则强有力的认识论版本的辩护。我们应该记住,有些专家几乎从不参加会议或发表论文,尽管他们是他们行业中的佼佼者。这种情况在哲学或数学领域可能比那些研究至少部分依赖于昂贵设备的科学领域更为常见。(我想我们很多人都认识一些哲学家,他们是某一领域的专家,但从未在该领域发表过任何值得注意的文章——比如盖蒂埃,但没有一篇著名的三页论文)。有一个关于数字是否重要的讨论正在进行,也就是说,我们是否应该,在同伴不同意的情况下,采用大多数人持有的信念,或者我们是否应该保留信念,即使在相互独立的同伴中有明显的多数人支持有争议的立场之一。参见Lackey (Citation2013)对前一种观点的证明。在韦伯未出版的书中,我支持后者。如果数字无关紧要,就很难排除同伴之间存在分歧的可能性,这就需要对信念进行修正。严格地说,要区分两个步骤:首先要采访别人,了解他们是自己在相关领域的认识上的同辈,甚至是上级,然后与自己的同辈或上级(如果有的话)讨论自己感兴趣的具体问题。为了表述方便,我将在下面简单地说,如果争论的问题是哲学性质的,就应该与所有哲学家交谈;如果争论的问题涉及生物学,就应该与所有生物学家交谈,等等。这些分歧的一个共同特征是戈德堡所说的系统性。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Unknown Peers
ABSTRACTUnknown peers create a problem for those epistemologists who argue that we should be conciliatory in cases of peer disagreement. The standard interpretation of ‘being conciliatory’ has it that we should revise our opinions concerning a specific subject matter whenever we encounter someone who is as competent and well informed as we are concerning this subject matter (and thus is our peer) and holds a different opinion. As a consequence, peers whom we have never encountered and who are hence unknown to us are not taken into account. This, however, appears odd; not only because it is an accidental matter which peers we happen to encounter and which not, but also because it would allow people to deliberately isolate themselves from any kind of intellectual exchange on the topic under consideration. The paper argues that we should take the problem of unknown peers seriously, and that disregarding the problem is an instance of the more general mistake of assuming that evidential quality and justified believability can be dealt with separately. Moreover, a solution to the problem of unknown peers is suggested.KEYWORDS: EpistemologyevidencedisagreementpeersEqual Weight Viewjustification AcknowledgementThe paper benefitted a lot from comments and impulses by Wolfgang Freitag (who also convinced me of the need to clarify how EW is to be defined), Sanford Goldberg, Jonathan Matheson, Christoph Schamberger, Nadja-Mira Yolcu, Elia Zardini, Q1 Alexandra Zinke, and several anonymous referees.Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. For the purpose of the present paper, this rough characterization of epistemic peerhood suffices. See, e.g., Matheson (Citation2015, 24–25), Elga (Citation2007, 499, fn. 21), King (Citation2011), Vorobej (Citation2011), and my Weber (Citation2017b) for a more detailed discussion of the concept.2. See Lasonen-Aarnio (Citation2014, 317) and Rosenkranz and Schulz (Citation2015, 570–572).3. Analogously, it does not speak against the A-Variant that it is compatible with giving no weight to both one’s own view and that of one’s epistemic peer. For it does not follow that one could instead focus on first-order evidence alone, since one cannot consider first-order evidence withing interpreting it, which means that there must be at least one person to whose interpretation one gives more than zero weight. This person need not be oneself or one’s peer: arguably, giving no weight to both one’s own view and that of one’s epistemic peer is exactly what one should do if there is an epistemic superior regarding the matter under debate.4. A case in point is Kelly (Citation2010, 112).5. David Enoch also distinguishes what I call the A-, B-, and C-Variant and argues for the latter; see Enoch (Citation2010, 970–972).6. This position is usually called the Right Reasons View. For versions this view, see Kelly (Citation2005, 180) and Titelbaum (Citation2015). A strong externalist element is also part of Lackey’s justificationist view (see especially Lackey Citation2010, 320) as well as of Weatherson’s evidence aggregation view (Weatherson Citation2019, ch. 12).7. See, e.g., Hall and Johnson (Citation1998) for a vindication of a strong epistemic version of this principle.8. We should bear in mind that there are experts who hardly ever attend conferences or publish papers, although they are among the best of their profession. This may occur more often in philosophy or mathematics than in those sciences in which research depends, at least partly, on expensive equipment. (I guess many of us know some philosopher who is an expert in a certain field but has never published anything noticeable on it – someone like Gettier, but without a famous three-page paper).9. There is an ongoing discussion about whether numbers matter, i.e., whether we should, in case of a peer disagreement, adopt the belief held by the majority, or whether we should withhold belief even if there is a clear majority among mutually independent peers for one of the contested positions. See Lackey (Citation2013) for a vindication of the former view. In Weber unpublished, I argue for the latter. If numbers do not matter, it is harder to rule out the existence of a peer disagreement that would require belief revision.10. Strictly speaking, two steps are to be distinguished: One should first interview people to find out whether they are one’s epistemic peers or even superiors concerning the relevant domain, and then discuss the specific matter one is interested in with one’s peers or superiors (if there are any). For ease of presentation, I will simply say in what follows that one should talk to all philosophers if the matter under debate is of philosophical nature, talk to all biologists if the matter under debate concerns biology, etc.11. A common feature of these disagreements is that they are what Goldberg calls systematic. Systematic disagreements are non-local insofar as they extend to neighbouring issues as well, widespread insofar as they occur between two or more large groups of people, and entrenched insofar as they have persisted for quite some time, with each side continuing to defend and advance their position (see Goldberg Citation2013). There are, however, systematic disagreements on matters that need to be decided sooner rather than later, so that we then are allowed to stop gathering potentially relevant evidence for pragmatic reasons (although we may not be allowed to form decisive beliefs about the controversial issue).12. Ballantyne would disagree; see his (Citation2015). Ballantyne’s argument also involves samples that are claimed to be not representative. As his samples are samples of pieces of evidence and not, as in the present paper, samples of experts, his argument differs from mine to a great extent. For example, while pieces of evidence have to be balanced according to their quality, this is not what proponents of EW want to do with expert opinions in cases of a peer disagreement.13. My line of reasoning for this thesis is an indirect argument: it claims that rival positions have unbearable consequences, so that we have to adopt the Equipotence Thesis as the only way out. There are also direct arguments for this thesis (most notably in Kelly Citation2005) as well as objections to them (most notably in Christensen Citation2007), but I cannot discuss them here due to lack of space. See instead Weber Citation2017a. My purpose in the present paper is not to establish the Equipotence Thesis – in order to do this, one has to discuss all its pros and cons – but to present one single argument in its favour.14. See Williamson (Citation2000, 192) for a detailed vindication of an almost identical claim.Additional informationFundingThe publication of this work was made possible with funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under grant agreement No 870883. Research for this paper was funded by the Volkswagen Foundation.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.90
自引率
0.00%
发文量
29
期刊介绍: The International Journal of Philosophical Studies (IJPS) publishes academic articles of the highest quality from both analytic and continental traditions and provides a forum for publishing on a broader range of issues than is currently available in philosophical journals. IJPS also publishes annual special issues devoted to key thematic areas or to critical engagements with contemporary philosophers of note. Through its Discussion section, it provides a lively forum for exchange of ideas and encourages dialogue and mutual comprehension across all philosophical traditions. The journal also contains an extensive book review section, including occasional book symposia. It also provides Critical Notices which review major books or themes in depth.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信