自然哲学:找回失落的学科想象

IF 0.2 0 RELIGION
Alister McGrath
{"title":"自然哲学:找回失落的学科想象","authors":"Alister McGrath","doi":"10.56315/pscf9-23mcgrath","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"NATURAL PHILOSOPHY: On Retrieving a Lost Disciplinary Imaginary by Alister McGrath. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2023. 256 pages. Hardcover; $39.95. ISBN: 9780192865731. *In this book, Alister McGrath provides an intellectual history and critique of what is now referred to as natural science, as well as a proposed re-conception of science going forward. The modern conception of science has its roots in something much older, referred to in the premodern world as \"natural philosophy,\" and this older conception--McGrath argues--is one which was both richer and much more integrated with the rest of knowledge than is natural philosophy's contemporary stepchild, \"science.\" The book has two parts. In Part 1, McGrath successfully labors to give an accessible introduction to the historical conception and development of natural philosophy and its trajectory/transformation towards contemporary \"science,\" followed in Part 2 by a proposed direction out of the predicament which he and others see modern/postmodern science to be in. *In Part 1, over the course of five chapters, McGrath first lays out this history. In chapter one, he starts with natural philosophy as an intellectual enterprise finding its origins in the pre-Christian Greeks via Aristotle. In chapter 2, McGrath outlines how natural philosophy then underwent significant development and enrichment through what McGrath calls the \"consolidation\" of natural philosophy up through the high Middle Ages. On this scheme, a study of the natural world was guided first and foremost by a reverence for God, and an impulse to find the operations of the natural world as understood and explained by principles which were consistent with what God has revealed through both scripture and the church. Natural philosophy was therefore seen as but one chapter of a much larger story, in which understanding this story could be had only if one's heart were grounded in religious piety and one's intellect governed by proper theology (as handed down by church hierarchs). *Chapters 3 through 5 outline the ways through which natural philosophy underwent fundamental metamorphosis for the worse. In stages brought about by the sociological effects of the Copernican revolution, the Protestant Reformation, the scientific revolution, the Enlightenment, and finally the Darwinian revolution, natural philosophy became disenchanted and dis-integrated from the cohesive place it once held as part of a totalizing theological-cosmological worldview of the premoderns; it devolved into a dis-integrated, compartmentalized, and fragmented version of itself, as evidenced by the ever increasing creation of new \"subdisciplines\" of modern science, which are all largely closed off from one another and which do not enjoy any kind of real synthesis as the premodern intellectual enterprises once did. This modern endeavor, furthermore, seems to be more concerned about extending human's domination over nature (technē) than it is about truly understanding (episteme) the world that God created. Thus, devoid of a \"disciplinary imaginary\" which serves as an organizing principle, the study of natural philosophy has become a shell of what it once was. This shell is the \"science\" that we speak of and study today. *In Part 2, McGrath spends the last five chapters of the book offering scientists and philosophers of science a proposed way forward, a way which might recover at least some of the integration and richness that natural philosophy once enjoyed. He does this by employing a heuristic that comes from Karl Popper's conception of what Popper called the \"three worlds,\" which Popper saw as distinct but related \"realms\" that encompass the scope of what can be known. On this scheme, the first world is that of objectivity or mind-independent objects, the world of \"physical objects or physical states.\" The second world is that of person or mind-dependent entities--the world of subjectivity, such as emotion, affect, and aesthetic value. The third world is one that acts as a sort of bridge between the first two, one which contains \"human intellectual constructions and artefacts\" such as scientific theories, moral values, and social constructions. McGrath points out that Popper's own development of this idea is not \"entirely satisfactory\" (p. 129), and McGrath proceeds to build his own conception using this framework of the \"three worlds\" as a heuristic tool, borrowing from Popper little else other than the basic idea itself. *McGrath begins his proposed \"disciplinary imaginary\" with an outline that builds from this third world, the world of theoria. This is the world of mental models and theories which serve to represent and organize bodies of data and evidence. For example, McGrath cites Dmitri Mendeleev's Periodic Table of the Elements. With this kind of organization in view, a certain \"beauty\" and \"coherency\" emerges, a kind of simple elegance that can inspire both (subjective) awe and enable further scientific (objective) investigation. It is in fact through these mentally constructed theories that we \"see\" and make sense of the external world, and these \"imaginaries\" should aim to engage both the intellect and the affect. *In chapter 8, McGrath visits the \"first world\" of objectivity, with the primary concern to show that, since humans are part of the very cosmos that objective science seeks to explain, there are inherent limits to the reach of a detached, person-neutral, objectivity. McGrath seeks to safeguard against a totalizing scientific reductionism by pointing out that a new natural philosophy will recognize that there are several aspects or layers of meaning to any given object of inquiry, and one needs to consider them all to get behind what's really there. He posits neo-Confucianism as one potential example of this kind of engagement with the external world. *Chapter 9 is about the importance of subjective experience, where McGrath seeks to show how aesthetic value and affective engagement are more than arbitrary states of mind. Instead, they often reflect true and proper responses to a world that really is pregnant with \"beauty and wonder.\" McGrath then wraps up the book by surveying what he has done and emphasizing the need for a retrieval of natural philosophy, a retrieval that can be enabled through a newfound imaginary or imaginaries. *I will offer two points of praise and two points of criticism. First, McGrath's keen ability to clearly explicate a very complex subject is on full display in this book. McGrath covers an impressive amount of historical ground in the first half of the book in a surprisingly small space (about a hundred pages), complete with explanatory and exploratory footnotes which enable the reader to delve deeper into subtopics. In this way, and like McGrath's many other monographs, the volume is worthwhile if for no other reason than that it acts as a sort of brief yet rich handbook to the subject at hand. Secondly, McGrath's effort is worth considerable praise because he not only seeks to give an intellectual history and critique of the modern epistemic predicament concerning science, but he also delivers up a thought-provoking proposal on what can be done to begin to address the problem. His re-conception of Popper's \"three worlds\" model is, I think, worthy of serious consideration. The broader point, however, is that McGrath is unafraid to wield both a critical acumen and a hopeful positivity regarding this issue, and such constructive attitude from a mind like his is welcome. *On the other hand, in Part 1, McGrath ends his historical survey and critique of natural science with the nineteenth-century secular Darwinists. It is, in fact quite arguably, the horrors and figures of the twentieth century which serve to hammer home the point concerning the consequences of abandoning the disciplinary imaginary for an elevation of (fragmented) scientific knowledge and scientific goals above most everything else. Thus, the first five chapters could have served as a setup for a polemical slam-dunk, but without this survey of the twentieth-century consequences, Part 1 left me with the feeling that McGrath proceeded a bit too prematurely. *Secondly, in Part 2, the way in which McGrath approaches the problem of modern science and his laying out a potential solution gives the impression that he views the issue, fundamentally, as an intellectual one. Is it perhaps more likely, as C. S. Lewis believed, that the problems which plague the modern scientific establishment (including the epistemological problems that stem from fragmentation) are fundamentally moral, not intellectual (see The Abolition of Man)? On this idea, civilization requires first and foremost a turn back toward God, in repentance. Only then can our institutions--knowledge producing and otherwise--begin to function properly. Moreover, given that our current state of scientific and technological advancement has far outstripped our moral scruples, one is left wondering what a scientific establishment could be capable of with the wrong (morally speaking), yet effective, disciplinary imaginary in place. The lesson from the biblical story of the Tower of Babel comes to mind, where an unprecedented attempt at evil was made possible only because corrupt humanity enjoyed a cohesive and integrated knowledge base, and the subsequent fragmentation of knowledge through the dispersion of languages acted not only as a divine judgment, but also as a paternal guardrail. *In all, nevertheless, McGrath's contribution to the topic is a timely and welcome addition, one which is sophisticated while remaining accessible, critical while remaining constructive. It is well worth picking up. *Reviewed by Alexander Fogassy, DPhil Candidate, Oriel College, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK OX1 4EW.","PeriodicalId":53927,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith","volume":"14 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Natural Philosophy: On Retrieving a Lost Disciplinary Imaginary\",\"authors\":\"Alister McGrath\",\"doi\":\"10.56315/pscf9-23mcgrath\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"NATURAL PHILOSOPHY: On Retrieving a Lost Disciplinary Imaginary by Alister McGrath. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2023. 256 pages. Hardcover; $39.95. ISBN: 9780192865731. *In this book, Alister McGrath provides an intellectual history and critique of what is now referred to as natural science, as well as a proposed re-conception of science going forward. The modern conception of science has its roots in something much older, referred to in the premodern world as \\\"natural philosophy,\\\" and this older conception--McGrath argues--is one which was both richer and much more integrated with the rest of knowledge than is natural philosophy's contemporary stepchild, \\\"science.\\\" The book has two parts. In Part 1, McGrath successfully labors to give an accessible introduction to the historical conception and development of natural philosophy and its trajectory/transformation towards contemporary \\\"science,\\\" followed in Part 2 by a proposed direction out of the predicament which he and others see modern/postmodern science to be in. *In Part 1, over the course of five chapters, McGrath first lays out this history. In chapter one, he starts with natural philosophy as an intellectual enterprise finding its origins in the pre-Christian Greeks via Aristotle. In chapter 2, McGrath outlines how natural philosophy then underwent significant development and enrichment through what McGrath calls the \\\"consolidation\\\" of natural philosophy up through the high Middle Ages. On this scheme, a study of the natural world was guided first and foremost by a reverence for God, and an impulse to find the operations of the natural world as understood and explained by principles which were consistent with what God has revealed through both scripture and the church. Natural philosophy was therefore seen as but one chapter of a much larger story, in which understanding this story could be had only if one's heart were grounded in religious piety and one's intellect governed by proper theology (as handed down by church hierarchs). *Chapters 3 through 5 outline the ways through which natural philosophy underwent fundamental metamorphosis for the worse. In stages brought about by the sociological effects of the Copernican revolution, the Protestant Reformation, the scientific revolution, the Enlightenment, and finally the Darwinian revolution, natural philosophy became disenchanted and dis-integrated from the cohesive place it once held as part of a totalizing theological-cosmological worldview of the premoderns; it devolved into a dis-integrated, compartmentalized, and fragmented version of itself, as evidenced by the ever increasing creation of new \\\"subdisciplines\\\" of modern science, which are all largely closed off from one another and which do not enjoy any kind of real synthesis as the premodern intellectual enterprises once did. This modern endeavor, furthermore, seems to be more concerned about extending human's domination over nature (technē) than it is about truly understanding (episteme) the world that God created. Thus, devoid of a \\\"disciplinary imaginary\\\" which serves as an organizing principle, the study of natural philosophy has become a shell of what it once was. This shell is the \\\"science\\\" that we speak of and study today. *In Part 2, McGrath spends the last five chapters of the book offering scientists and philosophers of science a proposed way forward, a way which might recover at least some of the integration and richness that natural philosophy once enjoyed. He does this by employing a heuristic that comes from Karl Popper's conception of what Popper called the \\\"three worlds,\\\" which Popper saw as distinct but related \\\"realms\\\" that encompass the scope of what can be known. On this scheme, the first world is that of objectivity or mind-independent objects, the world of \\\"physical objects or physical states.\\\" The second world is that of person or mind-dependent entities--the world of subjectivity, such as emotion, affect, and aesthetic value. The third world is one that acts as a sort of bridge between the first two, one which contains \\\"human intellectual constructions and artefacts\\\" such as scientific theories, moral values, and social constructions. McGrath points out that Popper's own development of this idea is not \\\"entirely satisfactory\\\" (p. 129), and McGrath proceeds to build his own conception using this framework of the \\\"three worlds\\\" as a heuristic tool, borrowing from Popper little else other than the basic idea itself. *McGrath begins his proposed \\\"disciplinary imaginary\\\" with an outline that builds from this third world, the world of theoria. This is the world of mental models and theories which serve to represent and organize bodies of data and evidence. For example, McGrath cites Dmitri Mendeleev's Periodic Table of the Elements. With this kind of organization in view, a certain \\\"beauty\\\" and \\\"coherency\\\" emerges, a kind of simple elegance that can inspire both (subjective) awe and enable further scientific (objective) investigation. It is in fact through these mentally constructed theories that we \\\"see\\\" and make sense of the external world, and these \\\"imaginaries\\\" should aim to engage both the intellect and the affect. *In chapter 8, McGrath visits the \\\"first world\\\" of objectivity, with the primary concern to show that, since humans are part of the very cosmos that objective science seeks to explain, there are inherent limits to the reach of a detached, person-neutral, objectivity. McGrath seeks to safeguard against a totalizing scientific reductionism by pointing out that a new natural philosophy will recognize that there are several aspects or layers of meaning to any given object of inquiry, and one needs to consider them all to get behind what's really there. He posits neo-Confucianism as one potential example of this kind of engagement with the external world. *Chapter 9 is about the importance of subjective experience, where McGrath seeks to show how aesthetic value and affective engagement are more than arbitrary states of mind. Instead, they often reflect true and proper responses to a world that really is pregnant with \\\"beauty and wonder.\\\" McGrath then wraps up the book by surveying what he has done and emphasizing the need for a retrieval of natural philosophy, a retrieval that can be enabled through a newfound imaginary or imaginaries. *I will offer two points of praise and two points of criticism. First, McGrath's keen ability to clearly explicate a very complex subject is on full display in this book. McGrath covers an impressive amount of historical ground in the first half of the book in a surprisingly small space (about a hundred pages), complete with explanatory and exploratory footnotes which enable the reader to delve deeper into subtopics. In this way, and like McGrath's many other monographs, the volume is worthwhile if for no other reason than that it acts as a sort of brief yet rich handbook to the subject at hand. Secondly, McGrath's effort is worth considerable praise because he not only seeks to give an intellectual history and critique of the modern epistemic predicament concerning science, but he also delivers up a thought-provoking proposal on what can be done to begin to address the problem. His re-conception of Popper's \\\"three worlds\\\" model is, I think, worthy of serious consideration. The broader point, however, is that McGrath is unafraid to wield both a critical acumen and a hopeful positivity regarding this issue, and such constructive attitude from a mind like his is welcome. *On the other hand, in Part 1, McGrath ends his historical survey and critique of natural science with the nineteenth-century secular Darwinists. It is, in fact quite arguably, the horrors and figures of the twentieth century which serve to hammer home the point concerning the consequences of abandoning the disciplinary imaginary for an elevation of (fragmented) scientific knowledge and scientific goals above most everything else. Thus, the first five chapters could have served as a setup for a polemical slam-dunk, but without this survey of the twentieth-century consequences, Part 1 left me with the feeling that McGrath proceeded a bit too prematurely. *Secondly, in Part 2, the way in which McGrath approaches the problem of modern science and his laying out a potential solution gives the impression that he views the issue, fundamentally, as an intellectual one. Is it perhaps more likely, as C. S. Lewis believed, that the problems which plague the modern scientific establishment (including the epistemological problems that stem from fragmentation) are fundamentally moral, not intellectual (see The Abolition of Man)? On this idea, civilization requires first and foremost a turn back toward God, in repentance. Only then can our institutions--knowledge producing and otherwise--begin to function properly. Moreover, given that our current state of scientific and technological advancement has far outstripped our moral scruples, one is left wondering what a scientific establishment could be capable of with the wrong (morally speaking), yet effective, disciplinary imaginary in place. The lesson from the biblical story of the Tower of Babel comes to mind, where an unprecedented attempt at evil was made possible only because corrupt humanity enjoyed a cohesive and integrated knowledge base, and the subsequent fragmentation of knowledge through the dispersion of languages acted not only as a divine judgment, but also as a paternal guardrail. *In all, nevertheless, McGrath's contribution to the topic is a timely and welcome addition, one which is sophisticated while remaining accessible, critical while remaining constructive. It is well worth picking up. *Reviewed by Alexander Fogassy, DPhil Candidate, Oriel College, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK OX1 4EW.\",\"PeriodicalId\":53927,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith\",\"volume\":\"14 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-09-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.56315/pscf9-23mcgrath\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"RELIGION\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.56315/pscf9-23mcgrath","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"RELIGION","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

阿利斯特·麦格拉思的《自然哲学:找回失落的学科想象》。牛津,英国:牛津大学出版社,2023。256页。精装书;39.95美元。ISBN: 9780192865731。*在这本书中,阿利斯特·麦格拉思提供了一个思想史和对现在被称为自然科学的批判,以及对未来科学的重新概念的建议。现代科学观的根源要古老得多,在前现代世界被称为“自然哲学”,麦格拉思认为,这个更古老的概念比自然哲学的当代继子“科学”更丰富,更能与其他知识相结合。这本书有两部分。在第一部分中,McGrath成功地对自然哲学的历史概念和发展及其向当代“科学”的轨迹/转变提供了一个易于理解的介绍,随后在第二部分中提出了一个摆脱他和其他人认为现代/后现代科学所处困境的方向。*在第一部分中,麦格拉思首先用五章的篇幅阐述了这段历史。在第一章中,他从自然哲学作为一种智力事业开始,通过亚里士多德在基督教之前的希腊找到了它的起源。在第二章中,McGrath概述了自然哲学是如何经历了重要的发展和丰富的,通过McGrath所谓的自然哲学的“巩固”,直到中世纪盛期。在这个计划中,对自然世界的研究首先是由对上帝的敬畏所引导的,以及一种发现自然世界运作的冲动,这种运作是由与上帝通过圣经和教会所揭示的一致的原则所理解和解释的。因此,自然哲学被视为一个更大故事的一个章节,只有当一个人的心建立在宗教虔诚的基础上,一个人的智力受到正确的神学(如教会等级制度所传授的)的支配时,才能理解这个故事。*第3章至第5章概述了自然哲学经历基本蜕变的途径。在哥白尼革命、新教改革、科学革命、启蒙运动和达尔文革命等社会学影响的影响下,自然哲学在各个阶段都变得不再迷人,不再具有凝聚力,它曾经是前现代人的整体神学宇宙论世界观的一部分;现代科学不断涌现出新的“分支学科”,证明了这一点。这些分支学科在很大程度上彼此隔绝,不像前现代的知识企业那样享有任何形式的真正综合。此外,这种现代的努力似乎更关心的是扩大人类对自然的统治(技术),而不是真正理解上帝创造的世界(知识)。因此,缺乏作为组织原则的“学科想象”,自然哲学的研究就变成了它曾经的一个外壳。这个外壳就是我们今天谈论和研究的“科学”。*在第二部分中,麦格拉思用了本书的最后五章,为科学科学家和哲学家们提供了一条前进的道路,这条道路至少可以恢复自然哲学曾经享有的一些完整性和丰富性。他采用了卡尔·波普尔(Karl Popper)所谓的“三个世界”(three worlds)概念中的启发式方法来做到这一点,波普尔认为这是不同但相关的“领域”,涵盖了已知事物的范围。在这个体系中,第一世界是客观世界或独立于心智的客体世界,即"物理客体或物理状态"的世界第二个世界是人或精神依赖实体的世界——主观性的世界,如情感、情感和审美价值。第三世界是前两个世界之间的桥梁,其中包含“人类智力结构和人工制品”,如科学理论、道德价值观和社会结构。McGrath指出,波普尔对这一观点的发展并不“完全令人满意”(第129页),McGrath将“三个世界”的框架作为一种启发式工具来构建自己的概念,除了基本观点本身之外,他几乎没有从波普尔那里借鉴什么。*麦格拉思在他提出的“学科想象”的开头,勾勒了一个第三世界——理论世界——的轮廓。这是一个心智模型和理论的世界,它们用来表示和组织大量的数据和证据。例如,麦格拉思引用了德米特里·门捷列夫的元素周期表。 有了这种组织,就会产生某种“美”和“连贯”,一种简单的优雅,既能激发(主观)敬畏,又能促进进一步的(客观)科学研究。事实上,正是通过这些心理建构的理论,我们才能“看到”并理解外部世界,而这些“想象”应该以智力和情感为目标。*在第8章中,McGrath访问了客观性的“第一世界”,主要是为了表明,既然人类是客观科学试图解释的宇宙的一部分,那么超然的、个人中立的客观性的范围就存在固有的限制。麦格拉思指出,一种新的自然哲学将认识到,任何给定的研究对象都有几个方面或层次的意义,人们需要全面考虑它们,以了解真正存在的东西,以此来防范一种全盘化的科学还原论。他认为新儒学是这种与外部世界接触的一个潜在例子。*第9章是关于主观体验的重要性,其中McGrath试图展示审美价值和情感参与如何超越武断的心理状态。相反,它们往往反映了对一个真正孕育着“美丽与奇迹”的世界的真实和适当的反应。然后,麦格拉思回顾了他所做的工作,并强调了对自然哲学进行检索的必要性,这种检索可以通过一个或多个新发现的想象来实现。我将提出两点赞扬和两点批评。首先,麦格拉思清晰地解释一个非常复杂的主题的敏锐能力在这本书中得到了充分的展示。在这本书的前半部分,麦格拉思用非常小的篇幅(大约100页)涵盖了大量令人印象深刻的历史背景,并配有解释性和探索性的脚注,使读者能够更深入地研究副标题。从这个角度来看,就像麦格拉思的许多其他专著一样,这本书是值得的,如果没有别的原因,它就像一本简短而丰富的手头主题手册。其次,麦格拉思的努力值得相当多的赞扬,因为他不仅试图给出关于科学的现代认知困境的思想史和批判,而且他还提出了一个发人深省的建议,说明可以做些什么来开始解决这个问题。他对波普尔“三个世界”模式的重新构想,我认为值得认真思考。然而,更广泛的观点是,在这个问题上,麦格拉思毫不畏惧地运用了批判的敏锐和充满希望的积极态度,而像他这样的思想的建设性态度是受欢迎的。*另一方面,在第一部分中,麦格拉思以19世纪的世俗达尔文主义者结束了他对自然科学的历史调查和批判。事实上,很有争议的是,二十世纪的恐怖事件和数字,让我们清楚地认识到,放弃学科想象,把(支离破碎的)科学知识和科学目标提升到高于大多数其他事物的水平,会带来什么后果。因此,前五章本可以作为一篇论战性的扣篮之作,但如果没有对二十世纪的后果进行调查,第一部分让我觉得麦格拉思写得有点太早了。*其次,在第二部分中,McGrath处理现代科学问题的方式以及他提出的潜在解决方案给人的印象是,他从根本上认为这个问题是一个智力问题。是否更有可能,正如c.s.刘易斯所相信的那样,困扰现代科学机构的问题(包括源于分裂的认识论问题)从根本上说是道德问题,而不是知识问题(参见《人类的废除》)?根据这种观点,文明首先需要在忏悔中转向上帝。只有这样,我们的机构——无论是知识生产机构还是其他机构——才能开始正常运作。此外,考虑到我们目前的科学和技术进步已经远远超过了我们的道德顾虑,人们不禁要问,在错误(从道德上讲)但有效的学科想象到位的情况下,科学机构能做些什么。我想起了《圣经》中巴别塔的故事,在那里,一次前所未有的邪恶尝试之所以成为可能,只是因为腐败的人类拥有一个凝聚力和整合的知识基础,而随后由于语言的分散而导致的知识碎片化,不仅是上帝的审判,也是父亲的护栏。*总之,McGrath对这个话题的贡献是及时而受欢迎的,它既复杂又易于理解,既批判性又具有建设性。这本书很值得一读。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Natural Philosophy: On Retrieving a Lost Disciplinary Imaginary
NATURAL PHILOSOPHY: On Retrieving a Lost Disciplinary Imaginary by Alister McGrath. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2023. 256 pages. Hardcover; $39.95. ISBN: 9780192865731. *In this book, Alister McGrath provides an intellectual history and critique of what is now referred to as natural science, as well as a proposed re-conception of science going forward. The modern conception of science has its roots in something much older, referred to in the premodern world as "natural philosophy," and this older conception--McGrath argues--is one which was both richer and much more integrated with the rest of knowledge than is natural philosophy's contemporary stepchild, "science." The book has two parts. In Part 1, McGrath successfully labors to give an accessible introduction to the historical conception and development of natural philosophy and its trajectory/transformation towards contemporary "science," followed in Part 2 by a proposed direction out of the predicament which he and others see modern/postmodern science to be in. *In Part 1, over the course of five chapters, McGrath first lays out this history. In chapter one, he starts with natural philosophy as an intellectual enterprise finding its origins in the pre-Christian Greeks via Aristotle. In chapter 2, McGrath outlines how natural philosophy then underwent significant development and enrichment through what McGrath calls the "consolidation" of natural philosophy up through the high Middle Ages. On this scheme, a study of the natural world was guided first and foremost by a reverence for God, and an impulse to find the operations of the natural world as understood and explained by principles which were consistent with what God has revealed through both scripture and the church. Natural philosophy was therefore seen as but one chapter of a much larger story, in which understanding this story could be had only if one's heart were grounded in religious piety and one's intellect governed by proper theology (as handed down by church hierarchs). *Chapters 3 through 5 outline the ways through which natural philosophy underwent fundamental metamorphosis for the worse. In stages brought about by the sociological effects of the Copernican revolution, the Protestant Reformation, the scientific revolution, the Enlightenment, and finally the Darwinian revolution, natural philosophy became disenchanted and dis-integrated from the cohesive place it once held as part of a totalizing theological-cosmological worldview of the premoderns; it devolved into a dis-integrated, compartmentalized, and fragmented version of itself, as evidenced by the ever increasing creation of new "subdisciplines" of modern science, which are all largely closed off from one another and which do not enjoy any kind of real synthesis as the premodern intellectual enterprises once did. This modern endeavor, furthermore, seems to be more concerned about extending human's domination over nature (technē) than it is about truly understanding (episteme) the world that God created. Thus, devoid of a "disciplinary imaginary" which serves as an organizing principle, the study of natural philosophy has become a shell of what it once was. This shell is the "science" that we speak of and study today. *In Part 2, McGrath spends the last five chapters of the book offering scientists and philosophers of science a proposed way forward, a way which might recover at least some of the integration and richness that natural philosophy once enjoyed. He does this by employing a heuristic that comes from Karl Popper's conception of what Popper called the "three worlds," which Popper saw as distinct but related "realms" that encompass the scope of what can be known. On this scheme, the first world is that of objectivity or mind-independent objects, the world of "physical objects or physical states." The second world is that of person or mind-dependent entities--the world of subjectivity, such as emotion, affect, and aesthetic value. The third world is one that acts as a sort of bridge between the first two, one which contains "human intellectual constructions and artefacts" such as scientific theories, moral values, and social constructions. McGrath points out that Popper's own development of this idea is not "entirely satisfactory" (p. 129), and McGrath proceeds to build his own conception using this framework of the "three worlds" as a heuristic tool, borrowing from Popper little else other than the basic idea itself. *McGrath begins his proposed "disciplinary imaginary" with an outline that builds from this third world, the world of theoria. This is the world of mental models and theories which serve to represent and organize bodies of data and evidence. For example, McGrath cites Dmitri Mendeleev's Periodic Table of the Elements. With this kind of organization in view, a certain "beauty" and "coherency" emerges, a kind of simple elegance that can inspire both (subjective) awe and enable further scientific (objective) investigation. It is in fact through these mentally constructed theories that we "see" and make sense of the external world, and these "imaginaries" should aim to engage both the intellect and the affect. *In chapter 8, McGrath visits the "first world" of objectivity, with the primary concern to show that, since humans are part of the very cosmos that objective science seeks to explain, there are inherent limits to the reach of a detached, person-neutral, objectivity. McGrath seeks to safeguard against a totalizing scientific reductionism by pointing out that a new natural philosophy will recognize that there are several aspects or layers of meaning to any given object of inquiry, and one needs to consider them all to get behind what's really there. He posits neo-Confucianism as one potential example of this kind of engagement with the external world. *Chapter 9 is about the importance of subjective experience, where McGrath seeks to show how aesthetic value and affective engagement are more than arbitrary states of mind. Instead, they often reflect true and proper responses to a world that really is pregnant with "beauty and wonder." McGrath then wraps up the book by surveying what he has done and emphasizing the need for a retrieval of natural philosophy, a retrieval that can be enabled through a newfound imaginary or imaginaries. *I will offer two points of praise and two points of criticism. First, McGrath's keen ability to clearly explicate a very complex subject is on full display in this book. McGrath covers an impressive amount of historical ground in the first half of the book in a surprisingly small space (about a hundred pages), complete with explanatory and exploratory footnotes which enable the reader to delve deeper into subtopics. In this way, and like McGrath's many other monographs, the volume is worthwhile if for no other reason than that it acts as a sort of brief yet rich handbook to the subject at hand. Secondly, McGrath's effort is worth considerable praise because he not only seeks to give an intellectual history and critique of the modern epistemic predicament concerning science, but he also delivers up a thought-provoking proposal on what can be done to begin to address the problem. His re-conception of Popper's "three worlds" model is, I think, worthy of serious consideration. The broader point, however, is that McGrath is unafraid to wield both a critical acumen and a hopeful positivity regarding this issue, and such constructive attitude from a mind like his is welcome. *On the other hand, in Part 1, McGrath ends his historical survey and critique of natural science with the nineteenth-century secular Darwinists. It is, in fact quite arguably, the horrors and figures of the twentieth century which serve to hammer home the point concerning the consequences of abandoning the disciplinary imaginary for an elevation of (fragmented) scientific knowledge and scientific goals above most everything else. Thus, the first five chapters could have served as a setup for a polemical slam-dunk, but without this survey of the twentieth-century consequences, Part 1 left me with the feeling that McGrath proceeded a bit too prematurely. *Secondly, in Part 2, the way in which McGrath approaches the problem of modern science and his laying out a potential solution gives the impression that he views the issue, fundamentally, as an intellectual one. Is it perhaps more likely, as C. S. Lewis believed, that the problems which plague the modern scientific establishment (including the epistemological problems that stem from fragmentation) are fundamentally moral, not intellectual (see The Abolition of Man)? On this idea, civilization requires first and foremost a turn back toward God, in repentance. Only then can our institutions--knowledge producing and otherwise--begin to function properly. Moreover, given that our current state of scientific and technological advancement has far outstripped our moral scruples, one is left wondering what a scientific establishment could be capable of with the wrong (morally speaking), yet effective, disciplinary imaginary in place. The lesson from the biblical story of the Tower of Babel comes to mind, where an unprecedented attempt at evil was made possible only because corrupt humanity enjoyed a cohesive and integrated knowledge base, and the subsequent fragmentation of knowledge through the dispersion of languages acted not only as a divine judgment, but also as a paternal guardrail. *In all, nevertheless, McGrath's contribution to the topic is a timely and welcome addition, one which is sophisticated while remaining accessible, critical while remaining constructive. It is well worth picking up. *Reviewed by Alexander Fogassy, DPhil Candidate, Oriel College, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK OX1 4EW.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
57.10%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信