虚无意志:尼采《道德谱系论》随笔

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Christopher Janaway
{"title":"虚无意志:尼采《道德谱系论》随笔","authors":"Christopher Janaway","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294474","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In Bernard Reginster’s account of On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche’s genealogical exercise is ‘functional.’ Nietzsche aims, in his view, to expose the functional role of moral beliefs in serving particular emotional needs of agents. The focus on this theme is tight, to the exclusion of some traditional topics, including perspectivism or truthfulness, as Reginster himself notes. Chapters 3, 4, and 5 tackle essays 1, 2, and 3 of the Genealogy, but virtually the first half of the book is devoted to Reginster’s overarching argumentative frame, which I will briefly sketch. Reginster sees Nietzsche’s demand that the value of moral values be called into question as a call to understand the function of moral beliefs, by providing a naturalistic explanation of them. History plays no role in Reginster’s analysis. He concentrates on the internal dynamics of a more or less timeless, generic, individual human agent. If this is Nietzsche’s focus, Reginster argues, then it is legitimate for some of his genealogical accounts to be fictional, because the target is generic types of psychological condition and because in real life the explanatory emotional factors are concealed from agents themselves. Function is the key notion here: what psychological work do moral beliefs perform for the agent? For Reginster, Nietzsche is not principally out to challenge the epistemic reliability of the route by which we have acquired our moral beliefs; rather he uncovers how moral beliefs affect the agent’s ‘emotional economy,’ in particular how they impact the agent’s sense of self, otherwise described as the agent’s ‘standing in the world,’ or sense of being ‘somebody.’Some well-known phrases haunt the literature on Nietzsche. One is ‘Moralities are only a sign language of the affects.’ Reginster gives a convincing reading of this slogan. He distinguishes between expressive and functional readings of the relation between value judgements and affects. On an expressive (or sentimentalist) reading, ‘evaluative experience is constituted by affective experience: what it is to experience something as “good” or “bad” is (roughly) to feel “inclination” or “aversion” toward it’ (25). Here there is a noncontingent and transparent relation between the evaluation and the affect: necessarily, if you are finding something good, you have a positive affect towards that same thing. But Nietzsche’s conception of ‘sign language’ is different: the affects that do the explanatory work are often related neither constitutively nor transparently to the object of the surface evaluation. For example, one’s making the judgement that it is right to help the needy may be explained not by a positive affect towards the needy, but by disgust, or by a feeling of one’s own superiority. Reginster is right that Nietzsche’s characteristic explanations are typically of this nature (though this fact is compatible with Nietzsche’s possibly holding the expressive view.)In its overall form, Reginster’s ‘pragmatic’ account does not seem radically new. As he says, ‘In the Preface to Genealogy, Nietzsche makes it unequivocally clear that when he calls the “value” of moral values into question, he is referring to their functional value’ (41), and this prominent passage has surely not gone unnoticed by previous commentators. However, if we interpret ‘value’ merely as ‘function,’ we risk losing sight of another sense of ‘value.’ For Nietzsche is not just trying to explain how emotional needs get satisfied, but suggesting that a particular way in which that occurs is not good. When morality fulfills its affective functions for some human agents, the effect, Nietzsche thinks, is to make humanity worse. Reginster is less clear throughout the book on why Nietzsche makes this latter valuation. He prioritizes the notion of a ‘self-undermining functionality,’ and the overall arc of the book reveals how a way of bolstering up one’s sense of self (or power) can lead to one’s own sickness and impoverishment. But it is not obvious that identifying this kind of functionality exhausts the valuation of morality Nietzsche calls for.Reginster sees ressentiment as the affective state that unites all three essays of the Genealogy. The cause of ressentiment is a tendency ‘to construe suffering as demeaning or degrading, as a challenge to the agent’s standing in the world’ (50). But instead of lingering with this sense of being demeaned, the person of ressentiment finds a way to restore his or her inner sense of ‘standing’ by viewing the suffering as an offense traceable to some perpetrator. Commentaries traditionally explain ressentiment by way of its most obvious instance in the psychology of the first essay’s ‘slaves,’ with their vengefulness and hatred directed at more powerful individuals in their society. By contrast, Reginster takes the concept in a wider sense, from which it emerges that ressentiment need not be construed primarily as a ‘social sentiment’ directed at other agents. It is more concerned with an agent’s own sense of self, can be directed at the world more generally, and can reflexively light on oneself as the object of blame, as in Nietzsche’s version of Christianity in the third essay.Reginster’s account makes will to power the driving instinct that causes the reaction of ressentiment. Eschewing discussion of whether will to power is any kind of cosmological view, he reads ‘power’ as a ‘conformity of the world to the agent’s will which is the product of the agent’s exercise of effective agency’ (65). Thus, one’s feeling of power is always relative to whatever is the overriding goal of one’s will. Reginster succinctly explains another Nietzschean slogan, ‘Ressentiment itself becomes creative’: a revaluation of values alters the agent’s will and thus ‘alters what counts as bending the world to it, that is, what counts as power for him’ (82). This clarifies what Nietzsche means by ‘creative’ here and shows how an aspiration to refrain from aggression toward others can also be an expression of will to power. By the end of the discussion, it is obvious how in Christian morality ‘ascetic self-denial is now what counts as power’ (160). Yet the precise status of will to power remains somewhat unclear. Nietzsche calls psychology ‘the doctrine of the development of the will to power,’ but Reginster says that this may be read as a biological rather than a psychological claim, and that Nietzsche is possibly exhorting us to ‘reconsider human psychology from the perspective of the new conception of life’ (63). It is hard to grasp the point here. It seems to amount to, ‘Thinking about how all living organisms function may help you see how the human mind is set up to preserve its own sense of standing in the world.’ But one would like to hear more about what kind of explanation is then supposed to be taking place.Having established this psychological structure of will to power, standing in the world, and ressentiment, Reginster applies it to the three essays of the Genealogy. It is not possible here to engage with details, but the analyses are penetrating, nuanced, and insightful. The reader will gain much by following the intricacies of the account through the major topics of equality, freedom of the will, imaginary revenge, guilt, punishment, and asceticism. Like Nietzsche, Reginster leaves any mention of the ‘will to nothingness’ to the end of his book. But we are left to figure out why Nietzsche writes specifically of ‘nothingness’ here. ‘Not willing’ is characterized as a kind of nihilism or meaninglessness in which one lacks any goal, and ‘there is nothing to will’ (167), or at least nothing that is achievable. The ascetic ideal provides the escape from ‘not willing’, eliminates the agent’s feeling of impotence, and ‘gives him a new lease of life’ (169). Reginster suggests that interpreting suffering as punishment allows the sense of power to be restored: suffering can both be justified as having stemmed from one’s own agency, and relieved because accepting the punishment restores one’s worth as a person. All of this is a pathological manifestation of will to power because in devaluing natural human well-being, it ‘decreases the organism’s capacity for life’—again a case of ‘self-undermining functionality.’ But one would like to hear more on why this condition of a relative ‘depletion of energy’ (187) deserves the absolute description of willing nothingness. Perhaps more could be made of the aspiration literally to lose the sense of self, to be nothing, which Nietzsche finds in Schopenhauerian negation of the will to life or in Buddhism.In Reginster’s final analysis, morality is a way for the weak to deal with a ‘depression’ that is endemic in human existence: ‘Morality poses a danger when it is put to a particular use, because this use is self-defeating. It poses such a danger … when it is made to serve the ressentiment of those who feel “weak and impotent”, by promising to restore their “feeling of power”, and thus offering them a way out of “depression” and “suicidal nihilism”’ (188). This seems to leave it open that morality might be objectionable only ‘in the wrong hands’ and that there could be unobjectionable uses of it for those who are not ‘weak and impotent.’ But there is no evidence of such a view in Nietzsche. Nietzsche’s usual attitude to the weak seems to be roughly ‘If morality functions to help them to get by, let them get on with it.’ He is more preoccupied with morality as a threat to the ‘strong.’ Reginster’s account addresses this point by introducing, in the last few pages, the thought that the ‘depression’ to which morality is a seductive remedy ‘is a chronic consequence of essential features of the human condition, and thus affects all human beings’ (188). Morality is a danger to the ‘strong’ because they are also sometimes, to some degree, weak and impotent. This theme would benefit from further development.Reginster in effect sees Nietzsche as giving a cool, timeless analysis of the ways in which the human mind functions to preserve its sense of power in relation to the world. That analysis is without doubt there in Nietzsche’s text, and Reginster’s sustained exposition advances our understanding of it. For that reason, everyone interested in Nietzsche should pay serious attention to this book. But, having collapsed the notion of ‘value’ into that of ‘function,’ Reginster effectively ends up locating the alleged disvalue of morality principally in the fact that its function is self-undermining: it is a ‘danger’ because it is self-defeating. It is hard to see this feature of morality as what motivates the alarm and disgust in Nietzsche’s narrative voice in the Genealogy. He sees himself at a historical juncture in which art, science, politics, and great human achievement are under threat as a consequence of moral beliefs and practices. That the psychology of the generic moral agent is self-defeating may be true, but it is not obviously Nietzsche’s chief evaluative concern.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"328 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"<i>The Will to Nothingness: An Essay on Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality</i>\",\"authors\":\"Christopher Janaway\",\"doi\":\"10.1215/00318108-10294474\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"In Bernard Reginster’s account of On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche’s genealogical exercise is ‘functional.’ Nietzsche aims, in his view, to expose the functional role of moral beliefs in serving particular emotional needs of agents. The focus on this theme is tight, to the exclusion of some traditional topics, including perspectivism or truthfulness, as Reginster himself notes. Chapters 3, 4, and 5 tackle essays 1, 2, and 3 of the Genealogy, but virtually the first half of the book is devoted to Reginster’s overarching argumentative frame, which I will briefly sketch. Reginster sees Nietzsche’s demand that the value of moral values be called into question as a call to understand the function of moral beliefs, by providing a naturalistic explanation of them. History plays no role in Reginster’s analysis. He concentrates on the internal dynamics of a more or less timeless, generic, individual human agent. If this is Nietzsche’s focus, Reginster argues, then it is legitimate for some of his genealogical accounts to be fictional, because the target is generic types of psychological condition and because in real life the explanatory emotional factors are concealed from agents themselves. Function is the key notion here: what psychological work do moral beliefs perform for the agent? For Reginster, Nietzsche is not principally out to challenge the epistemic reliability of the route by which we have acquired our moral beliefs; rather he uncovers how moral beliefs affect the agent’s ‘emotional economy,’ in particular how they impact the agent’s sense of self, otherwise described as the agent’s ‘standing in the world,’ or sense of being ‘somebody.’Some well-known phrases haunt the literature on Nietzsche. One is ‘Moralities are only a sign language of the affects.’ Reginster gives a convincing reading of this slogan. He distinguishes between expressive and functional readings of the relation between value judgements and affects. On an expressive (or sentimentalist) reading, ‘evaluative experience is constituted by affective experience: what it is to experience something as “good” or “bad” is (roughly) to feel “inclination” or “aversion” toward it’ (25). Here there is a noncontingent and transparent relation between the evaluation and the affect: necessarily, if you are finding something good, you have a positive affect towards that same thing. But Nietzsche’s conception of ‘sign language’ is different: the affects that do the explanatory work are often related neither constitutively nor transparently to the object of the surface evaluation. For example, one’s making the judgement that it is right to help the needy may be explained not by a positive affect towards the needy, but by disgust, or by a feeling of one’s own superiority. Reginster is right that Nietzsche’s characteristic explanations are typically of this nature (though this fact is compatible with Nietzsche’s possibly holding the expressive view.)In its overall form, Reginster’s ‘pragmatic’ account does not seem radically new. As he says, ‘In the Preface to Genealogy, Nietzsche makes it unequivocally clear that when he calls the “value” of moral values into question, he is referring to their functional value’ (41), and this prominent passage has surely not gone unnoticed by previous commentators. However, if we interpret ‘value’ merely as ‘function,’ we risk losing sight of another sense of ‘value.’ For Nietzsche is not just trying to explain how emotional needs get satisfied, but suggesting that a particular way in which that occurs is not good. When morality fulfills its affective functions for some human agents, the effect, Nietzsche thinks, is to make humanity worse. Reginster is less clear throughout the book on why Nietzsche makes this latter valuation. He prioritizes the notion of a ‘self-undermining functionality,’ and the overall arc of the book reveals how a way of bolstering up one’s sense of self (or power) can lead to one’s own sickness and impoverishment. But it is not obvious that identifying this kind of functionality exhausts the valuation of morality Nietzsche calls for.Reginster sees ressentiment as the affective state that unites all three essays of the Genealogy. The cause of ressentiment is a tendency ‘to construe suffering as demeaning or degrading, as a challenge to the agent’s standing in the world’ (50). But instead of lingering with this sense of being demeaned, the person of ressentiment finds a way to restore his or her inner sense of ‘standing’ by viewing the suffering as an offense traceable to some perpetrator. Commentaries traditionally explain ressentiment by way of its most obvious instance in the psychology of the first essay’s ‘slaves,’ with their vengefulness and hatred directed at more powerful individuals in their society. By contrast, Reginster takes the concept in a wider sense, from which it emerges that ressentiment need not be construed primarily as a ‘social sentiment’ directed at other agents. It is more concerned with an agent’s own sense of self, can be directed at the world more generally, and can reflexively light on oneself as the object of blame, as in Nietzsche’s version of Christianity in the third essay.Reginster’s account makes will to power the driving instinct that causes the reaction of ressentiment. Eschewing discussion of whether will to power is any kind of cosmological view, he reads ‘power’ as a ‘conformity of the world to the agent’s will which is the product of the agent’s exercise of effective agency’ (65). Thus, one’s feeling of power is always relative to whatever is the overriding goal of one’s will. Reginster succinctly explains another Nietzschean slogan, ‘Ressentiment itself becomes creative’: a revaluation of values alters the agent’s will and thus ‘alters what counts as bending the world to it, that is, what counts as power for him’ (82). This clarifies what Nietzsche means by ‘creative’ here and shows how an aspiration to refrain from aggression toward others can also be an expression of will to power. By the end of the discussion, it is obvious how in Christian morality ‘ascetic self-denial is now what counts as power’ (160). Yet the precise status of will to power remains somewhat unclear. Nietzsche calls psychology ‘the doctrine of the development of the will to power,’ but Reginster says that this may be read as a biological rather than a psychological claim, and that Nietzsche is possibly exhorting us to ‘reconsider human psychology from the perspective of the new conception of life’ (63). It is hard to grasp the point here. It seems to amount to, ‘Thinking about how all living organisms function may help you see how the human mind is set up to preserve its own sense of standing in the world.’ But one would like to hear more about what kind of explanation is then supposed to be taking place.Having established this psychological structure of will to power, standing in the world, and ressentiment, Reginster applies it to the three essays of the Genealogy. It is not possible here to engage with details, but the analyses are penetrating, nuanced, and insightful. The reader will gain much by following the intricacies of the account through the major topics of equality, freedom of the will, imaginary revenge, guilt, punishment, and asceticism. Like Nietzsche, Reginster leaves any mention of the ‘will to nothingness’ to the end of his book. But we are left to figure out why Nietzsche writes specifically of ‘nothingness’ here. ‘Not willing’ is characterized as a kind of nihilism or meaninglessness in which one lacks any goal, and ‘there is nothing to will’ (167), or at least nothing that is achievable. The ascetic ideal provides the escape from ‘not willing’, eliminates the agent’s feeling of impotence, and ‘gives him a new lease of life’ (169). Reginster suggests that interpreting suffering as punishment allows the sense of power to be restored: suffering can both be justified as having stemmed from one’s own agency, and relieved because accepting the punishment restores one’s worth as a person. All of this is a pathological manifestation of will to power because in devaluing natural human well-being, it ‘decreases the organism’s capacity for life’—again a case of ‘self-undermining functionality.’ But one would like to hear more on why this condition of a relative ‘depletion of energy’ (187) deserves the absolute description of willing nothingness. Perhaps more could be made of the aspiration literally to lose the sense of self, to be nothing, which Nietzsche finds in Schopenhauerian negation of the will to life or in Buddhism.In Reginster’s final analysis, morality is a way for the weak to deal with a ‘depression’ that is endemic in human existence: ‘Morality poses a danger when it is put to a particular use, because this use is self-defeating. It poses such a danger … when it is made to serve the ressentiment of those who feel “weak and impotent”, by promising to restore their “feeling of power”, and thus offering them a way out of “depression” and “suicidal nihilism”’ (188). This seems to leave it open that morality might be objectionable only ‘in the wrong hands’ and that there could be unobjectionable uses of it for those who are not ‘weak and impotent.’ But there is no evidence of such a view in Nietzsche. Nietzsche’s usual attitude to the weak seems to be roughly ‘If morality functions to help them to get by, let them get on with it.’ He is more preoccupied with morality as a threat to the ‘strong.’ Reginster’s account addresses this point by introducing, in the last few pages, the thought that the ‘depression’ to which morality is a seductive remedy ‘is a chronic consequence of essential features of the human condition, and thus affects all human beings’ (188). Morality is a danger to the ‘strong’ because they are also sometimes, to some degree, weak and impotent. This theme would benefit from further development.Reginster in effect sees Nietzsche as giving a cool, timeless analysis of the ways in which the human mind functions to preserve its sense of power in relation to the world. That analysis is without doubt there in Nietzsche’s text, and Reginster’s sustained exposition advances our understanding of it. For that reason, everyone interested in Nietzsche should pay serious attention to this book. But, having collapsed the notion of ‘value’ into that of ‘function,’ Reginster effectively ends up locating the alleged disvalue of morality principally in the fact that its function is self-undermining: it is a ‘danger’ because it is self-defeating. It is hard to see this feature of morality as what motivates the alarm and disgust in Nietzsche’s narrative voice in the Genealogy. He sees himself at a historical juncture in which art, science, politics, and great human achievement are under threat as a consequence of moral beliefs and practices. That the psychology of the generic moral agent is self-defeating may be true, but it is not obviously Nietzsche’s chief evaluative concern.\",\"PeriodicalId\":48129,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"volume\":\"328 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.8000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-04-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294474\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294474","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

它更关注的是一个主体的自我意识,可以更广泛地指向世界,可以反射性地把自己作为责备的对象,就像尼采在第三篇文章中对基督教的看法一样。雷吉斯特的叙述使意志成为驱动本能的动力,这种本能导致了怨恨的反应。他回避了关于权力意志是否属于某种宇宙论观点的讨论,他将“权力”解读为“世界对主体意志的遵从,这是主体行使有效代理的产物”(65)。因此,一个人的权力感总是与他意志的最高目标相关。Reginster简洁地解释了另一个尼采的口号,“怨恨本身成为创造性的”:价值的重新评估改变了代理人的意志,从而“改变了什么是使世界屈服于它,也就是说,什么是他的权力”(82)。这阐明了尼采在这里所说的“创造性”的意思,并展示了如何抑制对他人侵略的渴望也可以是权力意志的一种表达。在讨论结束时,很明显,在基督教道德中,“苦行的自我否定现在被视为权力”(160)。然而,权力意志的确切地位仍不太清楚。尼采称心理学为“权力意志发展的学说”,但Reginster说,这可能被解读为生物学而不是心理学的主张,尼采可能是在劝我们“从新的生命概念的角度重新考虑人类心理学”(63)。这里很难把握要点。这句话的意思似乎是:“思考所有生物体是如何运作的,可能有助于你了解人类的思维是如何建立起来的,以保持自己在世界上的地位。”“但人们希望听到更多关于应该发生的解释。”在建立了权力意志、社会地位和怨恨的心理结构之后,雷吉斯特将其运用到《家谱》的三篇文章中。这里不可能涉及细节,但分析是深入的,细致入微的,有见地的。通过平等、意志自由、想象中的复仇、内疚、惩罚和禁欲主义等主要主题,读者将从错综复杂的叙述中受益匪浅。和尼采一样,雷吉斯特在书的最后才提到“虚无意志”。但是我们要弄清楚为什么尼采在这里特别提到了“虚无”。“不愿意”被描述为一种虚无主义或无意义,在这种情况下,一个人缺乏任何目标,“没有什么可意愿的”(167),或者至少没有什么是可以实现的。苦行的理想提供了对“不愿意”的逃避,消除了主体的无能感,并“给予他新的生命”(169)。Reginster认为,将痛苦解释为惩罚可以恢复权力感:痛苦既可以被认为是源于自己的行为,也可以因为接受惩罚而恢复作为一个人的价值而得到缓解。所有这些都是权力意志的病态表现,因为在贬低人类的自然福祉时,它“降低了生物体的生存能力”——这又是一个“自我破坏功能”的例子。但是,人们希望听到更多关于为什么这种相对“能量枯竭”的情况(187)值得被绝对地描述为自愿的虚无。也许更多的是渴望失去自我意识,成为虚无,这是尼采在叔本华对生命意志的否定或佛教中发现的。在Reginster的最终分析中,道德是弱者应对人类生存中普遍存在的“抑郁”的一种方式:“当道德被用于特定用途时,它会带来危险,因为这种用途会弄死自己。”当它被用来满足那些感到“软弱和无能”的人的怨恨时,承诺恢复他们的“权力感”,从而为他们提供一条摆脱“抑郁”和“自杀虚无主义”的道路,这就构成了这样的危险(188)。这似乎留下了一个开放的空间,即道德可能只有“在错误的人手中”才会令人反感,而对于那些不“软弱无能”的人来说,道德可能有无可非议的用途。但在尼采的著作中并没有这种观点的证据。尼采通常对弱者的态度似乎是,如果道德能帮助他们过下去,那就让他们继续吧。他更关注的是道德对强者的威胁。在书的最后几页,Reginster通过介绍这样一种思想来解决这一问题,即道德是一种诱人的补救方法,“抑郁”是人类状况基本特征的长期后果,因此影响到所有人”(188)。道德对“强者”来说是一种危险,因为他们有时在某种程度上也是软弱和无能的。这一主题将受益于进一步发展。 Reginster实际上认为尼采给出了一个很酷的,永恒的分析,在这个分析中,人类的思维功能,保持了与世界相关的权力感。毫无疑问,尼采的文本中就有这种分析,雷吉斯特的持续阐述促进了我们对它的理解。因此,每个对尼采感兴趣的人都应该认真关注这本书。但是,在将“价值”的概念瓦解为“功能”的概念之后,雷吉斯特有效地最终将所谓的道德的不价值主要定位在其功能是自我破坏的事实中:它是一种“危险”,因为它是自我挫败的。很难看出道德的这一特征,是什么激发了尼采在《系谱》中叙事声音中的警觉和厌恶。他认为自己正处于一个历史关头,艺术、科学、政治和人类的伟大成就都受到道德信仰和实践的威胁。一般道德行为者的心理是自我挫败的,这可能是对的,但这显然不是尼采主要的评价关注点。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The Will to Nothingness: An Essay on Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality
In Bernard Reginster’s account of On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche’s genealogical exercise is ‘functional.’ Nietzsche aims, in his view, to expose the functional role of moral beliefs in serving particular emotional needs of agents. The focus on this theme is tight, to the exclusion of some traditional topics, including perspectivism or truthfulness, as Reginster himself notes. Chapters 3, 4, and 5 tackle essays 1, 2, and 3 of the Genealogy, but virtually the first half of the book is devoted to Reginster’s overarching argumentative frame, which I will briefly sketch. Reginster sees Nietzsche’s demand that the value of moral values be called into question as a call to understand the function of moral beliefs, by providing a naturalistic explanation of them. History plays no role in Reginster’s analysis. He concentrates on the internal dynamics of a more or less timeless, generic, individual human agent. If this is Nietzsche’s focus, Reginster argues, then it is legitimate for some of his genealogical accounts to be fictional, because the target is generic types of psychological condition and because in real life the explanatory emotional factors are concealed from agents themselves. Function is the key notion here: what psychological work do moral beliefs perform for the agent? For Reginster, Nietzsche is not principally out to challenge the epistemic reliability of the route by which we have acquired our moral beliefs; rather he uncovers how moral beliefs affect the agent’s ‘emotional economy,’ in particular how they impact the agent’s sense of self, otherwise described as the agent’s ‘standing in the world,’ or sense of being ‘somebody.’Some well-known phrases haunt the literature on Nietzsche. One is ‘Moralities are only a sign language of the affects.’ Reginster gives a convincing reading of this slogan. He distinguishes between expressive and functional readings of the relation between value judgements and affects. On an expressive (or sentimentalist) reading, ‘evaluative experience is constituted by affective experience: what it is to experience something as “good” or “bad” is (roughly) to feel “inclination” or “aversion” toward it’ (25). Here there is a noncontingent and transparent relation between the evaluation and the affect: necessarily, if you are finding something good, you have a positive affect towards that same thing. But Nietzsche’s conception of ‘sign language’ is different: the affects that do the explanatory work are often related neither constitutively nor transparently to the object of the surface evaluation. For example, one’s making the judgement that it is right to help the needy may be explained not by a positive affect towards the needy, but by disgust, or by a feeling of one’s own superiority. Reginster is right that Nietzsche’s characteristic explanations are typically of this nature (though this fact is compatible with Nietzsche’s possibly holding the expressive view.)In its overall form, Reginster’s ‘pragmatic’ account does not seem radically new. As he says, ‘In the Preface to Genealogy, Nietzsche makes it unequivocally clear that when he calls the “value” of moral values into question, he is referring to their functional value’ (41), and this prominent passage has surely not gone unnoticed by previous commentators. However, if we interpret ‘value’ merely as ‘function,’ we risk losing sight of another sense of ‘value.’ For Nietzsche is not just trying to explain how emotional needs get satisfied, but suggesting that a particular way in which that occurs is not good. When morality fulfills its affective functions for some human agents, the effect, Nietzsche thinks, is to make humanity worse. Reginster is less clear throughout the book on why Nietzsche makes this latter valuation. He prioritizes the notion of a ‘self-undermining functionality,’ and the overall arc of the book reveals how a way of bolstering up one’s sense of self (or power) can lead to one’s own sickness and impoverishment. But it is not obvious that identifying this kind of functionality exhausts the valuation of morality Nietzsche calls for.Reginster sees ressentiment as the affective state that unites all three essays of the Genealogy. The cause of ressentiment is a tendency ‘to construe suffering as demeaning or degrading, as a challenge to the agent’s standing in the world’ (50). But instead of lingering with this sense of being demeaned, the person of ressentiment finds a way to restore his or her inner sense of ‘standing’ by viewing the suffering as an offense traceable to some perpetrator. Commentaries traditionally explain ressentiment by way of its most obvious instance in the psychology of the first essay’s ‘slaves,’ with their vengefulness and hatred directed at more powerful individuals in their society. By contrast, Reginster takes the concept in a wider sense, from which it emerges that ressentiment need not be construed primarily as a ‘social sentiment’ directed at other agents. It is more concerned with an agent’s own sense of self, can be directed at the world more generally, and can reflexively light on oneself as the object of blame, as in Nietzsche’s version of Christianity in the third essay.Reginster’s account makes will to power the driving instinct that causes the reaction of ressentiment. Eschewing discussion of whether will to power is any kind of cosmological view, he reads ‘power’ as a ‘conformity of the world to the agent’s will which is the product of the agent’s exercise of effective agency’ (65). Thus, one’s feeling of power is always relative to whatever is the overriding goal of one’s will. Reginster succinctly explains another Nietzschean slogan, ‘Ressentiment itself becomes creative’: a revaluation of values alters the agent’s will and thus ‘alters what counts as bending the world to it, that is, what counts as power for him’ (82). This clarifies what Nietzsche means by ‘creative’ here and shows how an aspiration to refrain from aggression toward others can also be an expression of will to power. By the end of the discussion, it is obvious how in Christian morality ‘ascetic self-denial is now what counts as power’ (160). Yet the precise status of will to power remains somewhat unclear. Nietzsche calls psychology ‘the doctrine of the development of the will to power,’ but Reginster says that this may be read as a biological rather than a psychological claim, and that Nietzsche is possibly exhorting us to ‘reconsider human psychology from the perspective of the new conception of life’ (63). It is hard to grasp the point here. It seems to amount to, ‘Thinking about how all living organisms function may help you see how the human mind is set up to preserve its own sense of standing in the world.’ But one would like to hear more about what kind of explanation is then supposed to be taking place.Having established this psychological structure of will to power, standing in the world, and ressentiment, Reginster applies it to the three essays of the Genealogy. It is not possible here to engage with details, but the analyses are penetrating, nuanced, and insightful. The reader will gain much by following the intricacies of the account through the major topics of equality, freedom of the will, imaginary revenge, guilt, punishment, and asceticism. Like Nietzsche, Reginster leaves any mention of the ‘will to nothingness’ to the end of his book. But we are left to figure out why Nietzsche writes specifically of ‘nothingness’ here. ‘Not willing’ is characterized as a kind of nihilism or meaninglessness in which one lacks any goal, and ‘there is nothing to will’ (167), or at least nothing that is achievable. The ascetic ideal provides the escape from ‘not willing’, eliminates the agent’s feeling of impotence, and ‘gives him a new lease of life’ (169). Reginster suggests that interpreting suffering as punishment allows the sense of power to be restored: suffering can both be justified as having stemmed from one’s own agency, and relieved because accepting the punishment restores one’s worth as a person. All of this is a pathological manifestation of will to power because in devaluing natural human well-being, it ‘decreases the organism’s capacity for life’—again a case of ‘self-undermining functionality.’ But one would like to hear more on why this condition of a relative ‘depletion of energy’ (187) deserves the absolute description of willing nothingness. Perhaps more could be made of the aspiration literally to lose the sense of self, to be nothing, which Nietzsche finds in Schopenhauerian negation of the will to life or in Buddhism.In Reginster’s final analysis, morality is a way for the weak to deal with a ‘depression’ that is endemic in human existence: ‘Morality poses a danger when it is put to a particular use, because this use is self-defeating. It poses such a danger … when it is made to serve the ressentiment of those who feel “weak and impotent”, by promising to restore their “feeling of power”, and thus offering them a way out of “depression” and “suicidal nihilism”’ (188). This seems to leave it open that morality might be objectionable only ‘in the wrong hands’ and that there could be unobjectionable uses of it for those who are not ‘weak and impotent.’ But there is no evidence of such a view in Nietzsche. Nietzsche’s usual attitude to the weak seems to be roughly ‘If morality functions to help them to get by, let them get on with it.’ He is more preoccupied with morality as a threat to the ‘strong.’ Reginster’s account addresses this point by introducing, in the last few pages, the thought that the ‘depression’ to which morality is a seductive remedy ‘is a chronic consequence of essential features of the human condition, and thus affects all human beings’ (188). Morality is a danger to the ‘strong’ because they are also sometimes, to some degree, weak and impotent. This theme would benefit from further development.Reginster in effect sees Nietzsche as giving a cool, timeless analysis of the ways in which the human mind functions to preserve its sense of power in relation to the world. That analysis is without doubt there in Nietzsche’s text, and Reginster’s sustained exposition advances our understanding of it. For that reason, everyone interested in Nietzsche should pay serious attention to this book. But, having collapsed the notion of ‘value’ into that of ‘function,’ Reginster effectively ends up locating the alleged disvalue of morality principally in the fact that its function is self-undermining: it is a ‘danger’ because it is self-defeating. It is hard to see this feature of morality as what motivates the alarm and disgust in Nietzsche’s narrative voice in the Genealogy. He sees himself at a historical juncture in which art, science, politics, and great human achievement are under threat as a consequence of moral beliefs and practices. That the psychology of the generic moral agent is self-defeating may be true, but it is not obviously Nietzsche’s chief evaluative concern.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信