{"title":"公投投票率:强制还是自愿?","authors":"Graeme Orr","doi":"10.1080/09615768.2023.2245120","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Notes1 ‘Back’ implies that sovereignty derives from the people. ‘Referring’ reminds that a process of choosing which issues to send to a vote – and how to frame them – is involved.2 Eg, Jason Brennan and Lisa Hill, Compulsory Voting: For and Against (Cambridge University Press, 2014), Sarah Birch, Full Participation: a Comparative Study of Compulsory Voting (United Nations University Press, 2009) and Shane P Singh, Beyond Turnout: How Compulsory Voting Shapes Citizens and Political Parties (Oxford University Press, 2021).3 Eg, Costas Panagopoulos, ‘The Calculus of Voting in Compulsory Voting Systems’ (2008) 30 Political Behavior 455 cf Alberto Chong and Mauricio Olivera, ‘On Compulsory Voting and Income Equality’ (Inter-American Development Bank, Working Paper #33, 5/2005).4 Eg, Loren E Lomasky and Geoffrey Brennan, ‘Is There a Duty to Vote?’ (2000) 17 Social Philosophy and Policy 62 cf Michael M Bechtel et al, ‘Compulsory Voting, Habit Formation, and Political Participation’ (2018) 100 The Review of Economics and Statistics 467.5 Eg, Bart Engelen, ‘Why Compulsory Voting Can Enhance Democracy’ (2007) 42 Acta Politica 23. Conversely, it has been argued that compulsion could be used to accentuate a slippage into anti-democratic populism: Pete Crabb, ‘Compulsory Voting and Populism’ (SSRN, doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3662725, 5/9/2020).6 Eg, Xenophon Contiades and Alkmene Fotiadou, Participatory Constitutional Change: The People as Amenders of the Constitution (Routledge, 2016) and Julie Smith, The Palgrave Handbook of European Referendums (Palgrave Macmillan, 2021).7 Respectively: Karin Gilland Lutz and Simon Hug (eds), Financing Referendum Campaigns (Palgrave Macmillan, 2009), Sandrine Baume et al (eds); Misinformation in Referenda (Routledge, 2020); and Ron Levy et al, Deliberative Peace Referendums (Oxford University Press, 2021).8 Eg, Emilee Booth Chapman, ‘The Distinctive Value of Elections and the Case of Compulsory Voting’ (2019) 63 American Journal of Political Science 101, 102 (parenthetically suggesting that the case for compulsion in large-scale elections ‘potentially’ applies to referendums).9 See distinctions in Larry LeDuc, The Politics of Direct Democracy: Referendums in Global Perspective (University of Toronto Press, 2003) 39. I do not otherwise adopt LeDuc’s four-part typology of referendum topics (‘constitutional issues’, ‘treaties and international agreements’, ‘sovereignty, national self-determination and devolution’, and ‘public policy issues’). Whilst useful for a political scientist, they involve too much overlap to be categorically useful.10 Rick Hasen, ‘Voting Without Law?’ (1996) 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 2135, 2135.11 In some systems of course, citizens can initiate constitutional referendums, as in Italy and some smaller European democracies: Alan Renwick and Jess Sergeant, ‘The Rules of Referendums’ in Smith, above n 6, 71.12 ‘The concept of representation is misleadingly simple; everyone seems to know what it is, yet few can agree on any particular definition … of this elusive concept’: Suzanne Dovi, ‘Political Representation’, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (Stanford University, 2018 revision). Its paradoxes were identified in Hannah Fenichel Pitkin’s The Concept of Representation (University of California Press, 1967).13 Graeme Orr, ‘The Law of Electoral Democracy: Theory and Purpose’ in Alan Bogg et al (eds), The Constitution of Social Democracy (Hart, 2020)173–75. These are constructive or insider perspectives; a fourth is the cynical or outsider perspective, where electoral democracy is just a game masking entrenched inequities or oppression.14 I use ‘ultimate’ here not in the of ‘necessary if not sufficient’: a sense of legitimacy, perceived and real, being essential to trust and stability within any political order.15 See further Graeme Orr, Ritual and Rhythm in Electoral Systems: A Comparative Legal Account (Routledge, 2015).16 Justin Buchler, Hiring and Firing Officials: Rethinking the Purpose of Elections (Oxford University Press, 2011).17 International IDEA currently reckons that 27 countries (out of 203) employ some form of compulsion in turnout; and that 40 have ever used it (including three only ever at some sub-national elections: Austria, Switzerland and the US). See ‘Compulsory Voting’ <https://www.idea.int/data-tools/data/voter-turnout/compulsory-voting>.18 A 2006 survey identified 23 countries where electoral compulsion was then legislated for (including two only at sub-national level). Of these 16 were ‘free’, six ‘partly free’ and only one (Egypt) classed as ‘not free’: Joint Standing Committee on Electoral Matters, The 2004 Federal Election: Report of the Inquiry into the Conduct of the 2004 Federal Election and Matters Related Thereto (Parliament of the Commonwealth of Australia, 2006) Appendix G.19 See discussion in the Australian High Court in Faderson v Bridger (1971) 126 CLR 271. The more pragmatic question is whether ballot instructions imply that the voter must mark the ballot formally or whether the ability to spoil the ballot is noted: Graeme Orr, ‘The Choice Not to Choose: Commonwealth Law and the Withholding of Preferences’ (1997) 23 Monash University Law Review 285.20 Lisa Hill, ‘Increasing Turnout Using Compulsory Voting’ (2011) 31 Politics 27, 33. This is to ensure that elections in the short term are not skewed, eg, by party campaigns focusing on depressing the turnout of their rivals’ supporters; and in the longer term that whole classes of the electorate are not alienated such that their voices are unheeded.21 Chapman, above n 8, 104.22 International IDEA, above n 17. This excludes countries that merely compel voter registration, such as New Zealand. ‘Some’ compulsion includes countries where very young, very old or overseas electors are not compelled.23 Eg, s 128 of the Australian Constitution mandates referendums. But one-off legislation was used to run every referendum until 1984: Graeme Orr, ‘The Conduct of Referenda and Plebiscites in Australia: a Legal Perspective’ (2000) 11 Public Law Review 117. Conversely, referendums are mostly discretionary at the sub-national level in Australia, yet all bar one State now has standing legislation for them: Paul Kildea, ‘The Law and History of State and Territory Referendums' (2022) 44 Sydney Law Review 31, 49 n 111.24 Election observation and capacity-building means that electoral acts are now widely published.25 Eg, Singapore National Referendum Ordinance 1961, s 21 (standing referendum law) and Loi du 4 février 2005 relative au référendum au niveau national (Luxembourg) art 37 (one-off referendum law).26 Eg, Regulación del Referéndum (Ley 8492, 4/4/2006, Costa Rica) art 5 (standing referendum law).27 Constitution of the Federal Republic of Brazil (1988) art 14. Whilst this is not restated in the general procedures for plebiscites and referendums (Lei 9,709 de 18 de Novembro 1998) it is explicit in regulations for particular events (eg Lei 8,624 de 4 de Fevereiro 1993, art 3).28 A rare exception is described in Bechtel et al, above n 4: the Swiss canton of Vaud compelled participation in federal referendums – typically legislative rather than constitutional – whilst not mandating turnout for elections.29 Alvaro Marques and Thomas B Smith, ‘Referendums in the Third World’ (1984) 3 Electoral Studies 85, 10130 Ibid, 91.31 Ibid, 100.32 Duncan McCargo et al, ‘Ordering Peace: Thailand’s 2016 Constitutional Referendum’ (2017) 65 Contemporary Southeast Asia 65.33 Oran Doyle, ‘Order from Chaos? Typologies and Models of Constitutional Change’ in Contiades and Fotiadou (eds), above n 6, 182, 182. For a different typology of referendum issues to mine, see LeDuc, above n 9.34 A dichotomy mirrored in debates about whether the rule of law is primarily a substantive or procedural value.35 In 2018, another referendum repealed the prohibition. This referendum was quasi-institutional, since the question did not guarantee abortion rights as opposed to permitting the legislature to regulate. But it remained focused on social values, given the context was a strong push for legislation to liberalise the law.36 When Aristotle held that humans are zoon politikon, he was talking generally not specifically.37 Graeme Orr, ‘Deliberation and Electoral Law’ (2013) 12 Election Law Journal 421.38 LeDuc, above n 9, 72.39 Taiwan even has both: legislative supermajority to propose a referendum, then approval by 50% of all eligible voters.40 Regulación del Referéndum (Ley 8492, 4/4/2006, Costa Rica) art 4.41 Singh, above n 2, 24–25. Co-incidentally, that referendum concerned whether to retain electoral compulsion.42 For instance, the Brexit referendum achieved a vote of 37.5% of the enrolled electorate (on a turnout of 72%). It would have failed under a 40% quorum rule, but passed if turnout were 78%. Few commentators believe turnout skewed the Brexit result.43 Ron Levy, ‘Deliberative Case for Constitutional Referenda’ (2017) 16 Election Law Journal 213.44 Even deliberative democrats despair at elections ever being deliberative events: Dennis Thompson, ‘Deliberate About, Not In, Elections’ (2013) Election Law Journal 372 (arguing that deliberative democrats should focus on popular deliberation in reforming the rules of elections, rather than election campaigns themselves). For an argument that elections are flat-out deliberative wastelands best suited to the aggregation of pre-existing partisan views, see James A Gardner, What are Campaigns For? The Role of Persuasion in Electoral Law and Politics (Oxford University Press, 2009).45 Neil Gow, ‘The Introduction of Compulsory Voting in the Australian Commonwealth’ (1971) 6 Politics 201. Today, egalitarians value compulsion more than libertarians. But it was the centre-right parties who introduced compulsory voting in Australia, fearing that the labour movement had an advantage in turning out working class electors.46 See various chapters in Paul Strangio and Matteo Bonotti, A Century of Compulsory Voting in Australia: Genesis, Impact and Future (Palgrave Macmillan, 2021).47 Graeme Orr, ‘Choice of the Manner in Which Thou Wilt Die’: The Australian Courts on Compulsory Voting’ in Strangio and Bonotti (eds), ibid, 141.48 Sarah Cameron and Ian MacAllister, Trends in Australian Public Opinion: Results from the Australian Election Study 1987–2022, 75 (including data back to 1967). A shallow dip in the 1980s coincided with the one period when a major party has questioned compulsion (primarily within the liberal wing of the South Australian Liberal Party).49 For statistics see Glenn Rhodes, Votes for Australia: How Colonials Voted at the 1899–1900 Federation Referendums (Centre for Australian Public Sector Management, Griffith University, 2002) 16–17. The (un)predictability of outcomes was not a factor: turnout was only 1–4% higher than average in the two colonies where the vote was close.50 Australian Constitution, s 128.51 George Williams and David Hume, People Power: the History and Future of the Referendum in Australia (UNSW Press, 2010).52 At the last four national referendum days, in 1977, 1984, 1988 and 1999, turnout has been over 92%. It peaked at 95% for the last such event, the 1999 Republic referendum. Only one of those four events coincided with an election. Turnout remained high even when the proposals were narrow and purely institutionalist (as in 1977).53 Elisa Arcioni and Adrienne Stone, ‘Constitutional Change in Australia: The Paradox of the Frozen Continent’ in Xenophon Contiades and Alkmene Fotiadou (eds), Routledge Handbook on Comparative Constitutional Change (Routledge, 2022) 388 argue that this thinness has been a saving grace. By not locking-in too much, informal constitutional change has been able to compensate for the failure of explicit amendments.54 In an avian metaphor, it is a ‘small brown bird’ compared to the US constitutional ‘eagle’: Justice Patrick Keane, ‘In Celebration of the Constitution’ (Constitution Founders Lecture, 12/6/2008).55 See further, Graeme Orr, ‘Voluntary Voting for Referendums in Australia: Old Wine, New Bottle’ in Ron Levy et al (eds), New Directions for Law in Australian: Essays in Contemporary Law Reform (ANU Press, 2017) 359.56 Williams and Hume, above n 51, 205. I am not saying that all institutional questions are arcane. Sometimes they relate to key democratic structures: Rick LaRue, ‘We Love the Bill of Rights. Can We Like a Bill of Structures’ (2022) 21 Election Law Journal 308.57 Commonwealth of Australia, Yes/No – Referendum ’99 – Your Official Referendum Pamphlet (Australian Electoral Commission, 1999) 17.58 As distinctly argued under the slogan ‘If it ain’t broke, don’t fix it’: ibid, 15.59 Klaas Woldring, ‘The Case for Voluntary Voting in Referendums’ (1976) 11 Politics 209.60 Williams and Hume, above n 51, ch 4 and appendix 2.61 The last successful national referendum day in Australia was in 1977: three relatively minor amendments were approved, one more substantial one failed.62 Examples in the past decade that have not reached a referendum despite all sides agreeing constitutional reform is necessary include modernising dated rules limiting qualifications of MPs and candidates, and regularising the vital practice of Commonwealth funding of local governments.63 Exemplified in House of Representatives Standing Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs, A Time for Change: Yes/No? Inquiry into the Machinery of Referendums (Parliament of the Commonwealth of Australia, 2009) chs 4–5. See also Williams and Hume, above n 51, ch 7.64 The official result, of a 67% ‘yes’ vote, has been the subject of suspicion. Technically that vote was a non-binding plebiscite. But, as noted in the introduction, that does not concern us. In liminal moments, of constitutional transition, there may be no pre-existing constitutional order ‘mandating’ a referendum for reform. Further, whilst an authoritarian regime could ignore the rejection of one of its proposals, it is more likely to tilt the scales to try to ensure a favourable outcome and, if necessary, modify the proposal and the voting scales and try again.65 Voluntary registration had until then been a constitutional rule in Chile as far back as 1925.66 Tiffany D Barnes and Gabriela Rangel, ‘Election Law Reform in Chile: the Implementation of Automatic Registration and Voluntary Voting’ (2014) 13 Election Law Journal 570, 571. Pinochet lost.67 Ibid, 572–73.68 Ibid, 573–76.69 Pamela Figueroa, Constitutional Referendum During the Covid-19 Pandemic: the Case of Chile (International IDEA, Case Study, 27/8/2021) 6.70 Ibid, 7.71 Ibid, 14.72 Recognising this, Australia employed voluntary voting for its Republican Constitutional Convention election: Graeme Orr, ‘Tinkering with Convention: Voluntary Voting at Australia's 1997 Constitutional Convention Election’ (1998) 17 Electoral Studies 575.73 With voluntary voting for 16–17 year olds: Propuesta Constitución Política de la República de Chile 2022, art 160.1.74 Bechtel et al, above n 4. The study followed the repeal of referendum compulsion in the Vaud canton of Switzerland. Despite a strong turnout boost whilst it was in place (30–36%, depending on the proposal’s salience) and a clear ‘spillover’ effect on turnout at otherwise voluntary federal elections was less (12% extra turnout, rising to 24% if a referendum coincided with an election day) these effects quickly subsided after Vaud repealed compulsion.75 The US takes the opposite approach, throwing all manner of ballots, local/state/federal, onto a common day.76 Indeed provisional article 16 of the Constitution of the Republic of Türkiye (1982) itself included deprivation of electoral and candidacy rights, for five years following, for those who failed to vote at that referendum.77 Ergun Özbudun and Ömer Faruk Gençkaya, Democratization and the Politics of Constitution-Making in Turkey (Central European University Press, 2009) 20.78 Mads Qvortup, Direct Democracy: A Comparative Study of the Theory and Practice of Government by the People (Manchester UP, 2015) 147.79 Just as standing and fairly stable electoral laws are an aspect of the ‘repeat play’ (generating ongoing commitment to elections as a means of renewing representative mandates) that is a key element of democracy: Samuel Issacharoff, Democracy Unmoored: Populism and the Corruption of Popular Sovereignty (Oxford University Press, 2023) ch 4.","PeriodicalId":38410,"journal":{"name":"King''s Law Journal","volume":"33 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-08-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Referendum Turnout: Compulsory or Voluntary?\",\"authors\":\"Graeme Orr\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/09615768.2023.2245120\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Notes1 ‘Back’ implies that sovereignty derives from the people. ‘Referring’ reminds that a process of choosing which issues to send to a vote – and how to frame them – is involved.2 Eg, Jason Brennan and Lisa Hill, Compulsory Voting: For and Against (Cambridge University Press, 2014), Sarah Birch, Full Participation: a Comparative Study of Compulsory Voting (United Nations University Press, 2009) and Shane P Singh, Beyond Turnout: How Compulsory Voting Shapes Citizens and Political Parties (Oxford University Press, 2021).3 Eg, Costas Panagopoulos, ‘The Calculus of Voting in Compulsory Voting Systems’ (2008) 30 Political Behavior 455 cf Alberto Chong and Mauricio Olivera, ‘On Compulsory Voting and Income Equality’ (Inter-American Development Bank, Working Paper #33, 5/2005).4 Eg, Loren E Lomasky and Geoffrey Brennan, ‘Is There a Duty to Vote?’ (2000) 17 Social Philosophy and Policy 62 cf Michael M Bechtel et al, ‘Compulsory Voting, Habit Formation, and Political Participation’ (2018) 100 The Review of Economics and Statistics 467.5 Eg, Bart Engelen, ‘Why Compulsory Voting Can Enhance Democracy’ (2007) 42 Acta Politica 23. Conversely, it has been argued that compulsion could be used to accentuate a slippage into anti-democratic populism: Pete Crabb, ‘Compulsory Voting and Populism’ (SSRN, doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3662725, 5/9/2020).6 Eg, Xenophon Contiades and Alkmene Fotiadou, Participatory Constitutional Change: The People as Amenders of the Constitution (Routledge, 2016) and Julie Smith, The Palgrave Handbook of European Referendums (Palgrave Macmillan, 2021).7 Respectively: Karin Gilland Lutz and Simon Hug (eds), Financing Referendum Campaigns (Palgrave Macmillan, 2009), Sandrine Baume et al (eds); Misinformation in Referenda (Routledge, 2020); and Ron Levy et al, Deliberative Peace Referendums (Oxford University Press, 2021).8 Eg, Emilee Booth Chapman, ‘The Distinctive Value of Elections and the Case of Compulsory Voting’ (2019) 63 American Journal of Political Science 101, 102 (parenthetically suggesting that the case for compulsion in large-scale elections ‘potentially’ applies to referendums).9 See distinctions in Larry LeDuc, The Politics of Direct Democracy: Referendums in Global Perspective (University of Toronto Press, 2003) 39. I do not otherwise adopt LeDuc’s four-part typology of referendum topics (‘constitutional issues’, ‘treaties and international agreements’, ‘sovereignty, national self-determination and devolution’, and ‘public policy issues’). Whilst useful for a political scientist, they involve too much overlap to be categorically useful.10 Rick Hasen, ‘Voting Without Law?’ (1996) 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 2135, 2135.11 In some systems of course, citizens can initiate constitutional referendums, as in Italy and some smaller European democracies: Alan Renwick and Jess Sergeant, ‘The Rules of Referendums’ in Smith, above n 6, 71.12 ‘The concept of representation is misleadingly simple; everyone seems to know what it is, yet few can agree on any particular definition … of this elusive concept’: Suzanne Dovi, ‘Political Representation’, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (Stanford University, 2018 revision). Its paradoxes were identified in Hannah Fenichel Pitkin’s The Concept of Representation (University of California Press, 1967).13 Graeme Orr, ‘The Law of Electoral Democracy: Theory and Purpose’ in Alan Bogg et al (eds), The Constitution of Social Democracy (Hart, 2020)173–75. These are constructive or insider perspectives; a fourth is the cynical or outsider perspective, where electoral democracy is just a game masking entrenched inequities or oppression.14 I use ‘ultimate’ here not in the of ‘necessary if not sufficient’: a sense of legitimacy, perceived and real, being essential to trust and stability within any political order.15 See further Graeme Orr, Ritual and Rhythm in Electoral Systems: A Comparative Legal Account (Routledge, 2015).16 Justin Buchler, Hiring and Firing Officials: Rethinking the Purpose of Elections (Oxford University Press, 2011).17 International IDEA currently reckons that 27 countries (out of 203) employ some form of compulsion in turnout; and that 40 have ever used it (including three only ever at some sub-national elections: Austria, Switzerland and the US). See ‘Compulsory Voting’ <https://www.idea.int/data-tools/data/voter-turnout/compulsory-voting>.18 A 2006 survey identified 23 countries where electoral compulsion was then legislated for (including two only at sub-national level). Of these 16 were ‘free’, six ‘partly free’ and only one (Egypt) classed as ‘not free’: Joint Standing Committee on Electoral Matters, The 2004 Federal Election: Report of the Inquiry into the Conduct of the 2004 Federal Election and Matters Related Thereto (Parliament of the Commonwealth of Australia, 2006) Appendix G.19 See discussion in the Australian High Court in Faderson v Bridger (1971) 126 CLR 271. The more pragmatic question is whether ballot instructions imply that the voter must mark the ballot formally or whether the ability to spoil the ballot is noted: Graeme Orr, ‘The Choice Not to Choose: Commonwealth Law and the Withholding of Preferences’ (1997) 23 Monash University Law Review 285.20 Lisa Hill, ‘Increasing Turnout Using Compulsory Voting’ (2011) 31 Politics 27, 33. This is to ensure that elections in the short term are not skewed, eg, by party campaigns focusing on depressing the turnout of their rivals’ supporters; and in the longer term that whole classes of the electorate are not alienated such that their voices are unheeded.21 Chapman, above n 8, 104.22 International IDEA, above n 17. This excludes countries that merely compel voter registration, such as New Zealand. ‘Some’ compulsion includes countries where very young, very old or overseas electors are not compelled.23 Eg, s 128 of the Australian Constitution mandates referendums. But one-off legislation was used to run every referendum until 1984: Graeme Orr, ‘The Conduct of Referenda and Plebiscites in Australia: a Legal Perspective’ (2000) 11 Public Law Review 117. Conversely, referendums are mostly discretionary at the sub-national level in Australia, yet all bar one State now has standing legislation for them: Paul Kildea, ‘The Law and History of State and Territory Referendums' (2022) 44 Sydney Law Review 31, 49 n 111.24 Election observation and capacity-building means that electoral acts are now widely published.25 Eg, Singapore National Referendum Ordinance 1961, s 21 (standing referendum law) and Loi du 4 février 2005 relative au référendum au niveau national (Luxembourg) art 37 (one-off referendum law).26 Eg, Regulación del Referéndum (Ley 8492, 4/4/2006, Costa Rica) art 5 (standing referendum law).27 Constitution of the Federal Republic of Brazil (1988) art 14. Whilst this is not restated in the general procedures for plebiscites and referendums (Lei 9,709 de 18 de Novembro 1998) it is explicit in regulations for particular events (eg Lei 8,624 de 4 de Fevereiro 1993, art 3).28 A rare exception is described in Bechtel et al, above n 4: the Swiss canton of Vaud compelled participation in federal referendums – typically legislative rather than constitutional – whilst not mandating turnout for elections.29 Alvaro Marques and Thomas B Smith, ‘Referendums in the Third World’ (1984) 3 Electoral Studies 85, 10130 Ibid, 91.31 Ibid, 100.32 Duncan McCargo et al, ‘Ordering Peace: Thailand’s 2016 Constitutional Referendum’ (2017) 65 Contemporary Southeast Asia 65.33 Oran Doyle, ‘Order from Chaos? Typologies and Models of Constitutional Change’ in Contiades and Fotiadou (eds), above n 6, 182, 182. For a different typology of referendum issues to mine, see LeDuc, above n 9.34 A dichotomy mirrored in debates about whether the rule of law is primarily a substantive or procedural value.35 In 2018, another referendum repealed the prohibition. This referendum was quasi-institutional, since the question did not guarantee abortion rights as opposed to permitting the legislature to regulate. But it remained focused on social values, given the context was a strong push for legislation to liberalise the law.36 When Aristotle held that humans are zoon politikon, he was talking generally not specifically.37 Graeme Orr, ‘Deliberation and Electoral Law’ (2013) 12 Election Law Journal 421.38 LeDuc, above n 9, 72.39 Taiwan even has both: legislative supermajority to propose a referendum, then approval by 50% of all eligible voters.40 Regulación del Referéndum (Ley 8492, 4/4/2006, Costa Rica) art 4.41 Singh, above n 2, 24–25. Co-incidentally, that referendum concerned whether to retain electoral compulsion.42 For instance, the Brexit referendum achieved a vote of 37.5% of the enrolled electorate (on a turnout of 72%). It would have failed under a 40% quorum rule, but passed if turnout were 78%. Few commentators believe turnout skewed the Brexit result.43 Ron Levy, ‘Deliberative Case for Constitutional Referenda’ (2017) 16 Election Law Journal 213.44 Even deliberative democrats despair at elections ever being deliberative events: Dennis Thompson, ‘Deliberate About, Not In, Elections’ (2013) Election Law Journal 372 (arguing that deliberative democrats should focus on popular deliberation in reforming the rules of elections, rather than election campaigns themselves). For an argument that elections are flat-out deliberative wastelands best suited to the aggregation of pre-existing partisan views, see James A Gardner, What are Campaigns For? The Role of Persuasion in Electoral Law and Politics (Oxford University Press, 2009).45 Neil Gow, ‘The Introduction of Compulsory Voting in the Australian Commonwealth’ (1971) 6 Politics 201. Today, egalitarians value compulsion more than libertarians. But it was the centre-right parties who introduced compulsory voting in Australia, fearing that the labour movement had an advantage in turning out working class electors.46 See various chapters in Paul Strangio and Matteo Bonotti, A Century of Compulsory Voting in Australia: Genesis, Impact and Future (Palgrave Macmillan, 2021).47 Graeme Orr, ‘Choice of the Manner in Which Thou Wilt Die’: The Australian Courts on Compulsory Voting’ in Strangio and Bonotti (eds), ibid, 141.48 Sarah Cameron and Ian MacAllister, Trends in Australian Public Opinion: Results from the Australian Election Study 1987–2022, 75 (including data back to 1967). A shallow dip in the 1980s coincided with the one period when a major party has questioned compulsion (primarily within the liberal wing of the South Australian Liberal Party).49 For statistics see Glenn Rhodes, Votes for Australia: How Colonials Voted at the 1899–1900 Federation Referendums (Centre for Australian Public Sector Management, Griffith University, 2002) 16–17. The (un)predictability of outcomes was not a factor: turnout was only 1–4% higher than average in the two colonies where the vote was close.50 Australian Constitution, s 128.51 George Williams and David Hume, People Power: the History and Future of the Referendum in Australia (UNSW Press, 2010).52 At the last four national referendum days, in 1977, 1984, 1988 and 1999, turnout has been over 92%. It peaked at 95% for the last such event, the 1999 Republic referendum. Only one of those four events coincided with an election. Turnout remained high even when the proposals were narrow and purely institutionalist (as in 1977).53 Elisa Arcioni and Adrienne Stone, ‘Constitutional Change in Australia: The Paradox of the Frozen Continent’ in Xenophon Contiades and Alkmene Fotiadou (eds), Routledge Handbook on Comparative Constitutional Change (Routledge, 2022) 388 argue that this thinness has been a saving grace. By not locking-in too much, informal constitutional change has been able to compensate for the failure of explicit amendments.54 In an avian metaphor, it is a ‘small brown bird’ compared to the US constitutional ‘eagle’: Justice Patrick Keane, ‘In Celebration of the Constitution’ (Constitution Founders Lecture, 12/6/2008).55 See further, Graeme Orr, ‘Voluntary Voting for Referendums in Australia: Old Wine, New Bottle’ in Ron Levy et al (eds), New Directions for Law in Australian: Essays in Contemporary Law Reform (ANU Press, 2017) 359.56 Williams and Hume, above n 51, 205. I am not saying that all institutional questions are arcane. Sometimes they relate to key democratic structures: Rick LaRue, ‘We Love the Bill of Rights. Can We Like a Bill of Structures’ (2022) 21 Election Law Journal 308.57 Commonwealth of Australia, Yes/No – Referendum ’99 – Your Official Referendum Pamphlet (Australian Electoral Commission, 1999) 17.58 As distinctly argued under the slogan ‘If it ain’t broke, don’t fix it’: ibid, 15.59 Klaas Woldring, ‘The Case for Voluntary Voting in Referendums’ (1976) 11 Politics 209.60 Williams and Hume, above n 51, ch 4 and appendix 2.61 The last successful national referendum day in Australia was in 1977: three relatively minor amendments were approved, one more substantial one failed.62 Examples in the past decade that have not reached a referendum despite all sides agreeing constitutional reform is necessary include modernising dated rules limiting qualifications of MPs and candidates, and regularising the vital practice of Commonwealth funding of local governments.63 Exemplified in House of Representatives Standing Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs, A Time for Change: Yes/No? Inquiry into the Machinery of Referendums (Parliament of the Commonwealth of Australia, 2009) chs 4–5. See also Williams and Hume, above n 51, ch 7.64 The official result, of a 67% ‘yes’ vote, has been the subject of suspicion. Technically that vote was a non-binding plebiscite. But, as noted in the introduction, that does not concern us. In liminal moments, of constitutional transition, there may be no pre-existing constitutional order ‘mandating’ a referendum for reform. Further, whilst an authoritarian regime could ignore the rejection of one of its proposals, it is more likely to tilt the scales to try to ensure a favourable outcome and, if necessary, modify the proposal and the voting scales and try again.65 Voluntary registration had until then been a constitutional rule in Chile as far back as 1925.66 Tiffany D Barnes and Gabriela Rangel, ‘Election Law Reform in Chile: the Implementation of Automatic Registration and Voluntary Voting’ (2014) 13 Election Law Journal 570, 571. Pinochet lost.67 Ibid, 572–73.68 Ibid, 573–76.69 Pamela Figueroa, Constitutional Referendum During the Covid-19 Pandemic: the Case of Chile (International IDEA, Case Study, 27/8/2021) 6.70 Ibid, 7.71 Ibid, 14.72 Recognising this, Australia employed voluntary voting for its Republican Constitutional Convention election: Graeme Orr, ‘Tinkering with Convention: Voluntary Voting at Australia's 1997 Constitutional Convention Election’ (1998) 17 Electoral Studies 575.73 With voluntary voting for 16–17 year olds: Propuesta Constitución Política de la República de Chile 2022, art 160.1.74 Bechtel et al, above n 4. The study followed the repeal of referendum compulsion in the Vaud canton of Switzerland. Despite a strong turnout boost whilst it was in place (30–36%, depending on the proposal’s salience) and a clear ‘spillover’ effect on turnout at otherwise voluntary federal elections was less (12% extra turnout, rising to 24% if a referendum coincided with an election day) these effects quickly subsided after Vaud repealed compulsion.75 The US takes the opposite approach, throwing all manner of ballots, local/state/federal, onto a common day.76 Indeed provisional article 16 of the Constitution of the Republic of Türkiye (1982) itself included deprivation of electoral and candidacy rights, for five years following, for those who failed to vote at that referendum.77 Ergun Özbudun and Ömer Faruk Gençkaya, Democratization and the Politics of Constitution-Making in Turkey (Central European University Press, 2009) 20.78 Mads Qvortup, Direct Democracy: A Comparative Study of the Theory and Practice of Government by the People (Manchester UP, 2015) 147.79 Just as standing and fairly stable electoral laws are an aspect of the ‘repeat play’ (generating ongoing commitment to elections as a means of renewing representative mandates) that is a key element of democracy: Samuel Issacharoff, Democracy Unmoored: Populism and the Corruption of Popular Sovereignty (Oxford University Press, 2023) ch 4.\",\"PeriodicalId\":38410,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"King''s Law Journal\",\"volume\":\"33 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-08-09\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"King''s Law Journal\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/09615768.2023.2245120\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q2\",\"JCRName\":\"Social Sciences\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"King''s Law Journal","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09615768.2023.2245120","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"Social Sciences","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
摘要
点击增大图片尺寸点击缩小图片尺寸注释1“后”意味着主权来自人民。“参考”一词提醒人们,这是一个选择将哪些问题提交投票的过程,以及如何构建这些问题的框架例如,杰森·布伦南和丽莎·希尔,《强制投票:支持和反对》(剑桥大学出版社,2014年),莎拉·伯奇,《充分参与:强制投票的比较研究》(联合国大学出版社,2009年),谢恩·P·辛格,《超越投票率:强制投票如何塑造公民和政党》(牛津大学出版社,2021年)例如,Costas Panagopoulos,“强制投票系统中的投票计算”(2008)30政治行为455 cf Alberto Chong和Mauricio Olivera,“关于强制投票和收入平等”(泛美开发银行,工作文件#33,2005年5月)例如,洛伦·洛马斯基和杰弗里·布伦南的《投票有义务吗?》(2000) 17社会哲学与政策62 cf Michael M Bechtel等人,“强制投票,习惯形成和政治参与”(2018)100经济学与统计学评论467.5 Eg, Bart Engelen,“为什么强制投票可以增强民主”(2007)42 Acta Politica 23。相反,有人认为,强制可以用来强调滑向反民主的民粹主义:皮特·克拉布,“强制投票和民粹主义”(SSRN, doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3662725, 5/9/2020)例如,Xenophon Contiades和Alkmene Fotiadou,参与式宪法变革:人民作为宪法的修改者(Routledge, 2016)和Julie Smith,欧洲公投Palgrave手册(Palgrave Macmillan, 2021)分别:Karin Gilland Lutz和Simon Hug(编),《全民公决运动融资》(Palgrave Macmillan出版社,2009),Sandrine Baume等人(编);公投中的错误信息(Routledge, 2020);和罗恩·利维等人,审议和平公投(牛津大学出版社,2021年)例如,Emilee Booth Chapman,“选举的独特价值和强制投票的案例”(2019)63《美国政治学杂志》101,102(附带说明,大规模选举中强制投票的案例“潜在地”适用于公投)见拉里·勒杜克的《直接民主的政治:全球视角下的公民投票》(多伦多大学出版社,2003年)39。除此之外,我不采用勒杜克的全民公决主题的四部分类型(“宪法问题”、“条约和国际协定”、“主权、民族自决和权力下放”以及“公共政策问题”)。虽然对政治学家有用,但它们涉及的重叠部分太多,不能绝对有用里克·哈森《没有法律的投票?》(1996) 144宾夕法尼亚大学法律评论2135,2135.11当然,在某些制度下,公民可以发起宪法公投,如在意大利和一些较小的欧洲民主国家:Alan Renwick和Jess Sergeant,《公民投票的规则》,史密斯,第6页以上,71.12“代表的概念简单得令人误解;每个人似乎都知道它是什么,但很少有人能就这个难以捉摸的概念的任何特定定义达成一致”:Suzanne Dovi,“政治代表”,斯坦福哲学百科全书(斯坦福大学,2018年修订版)。汉娜·菲尼切尔·皮特金的《表象的概念》(加州大学出版社,1967)指出了它的悖论格雷姆奥尔,“选举民主的法律:理论和目的”在艾伦博格等人(编),社会民主的宪法(哈特,2020)173-75。这些都是建设性的或局内人的观点;第四个是愤世嫉俗或局外人的观点,认为选举民主只是一种掩盖根深蒂固的不平等或压迫的游戏我在这里使用“终极”一词,并不是指“必要(如果不是充分的话)”:一种可感知的、真实的合法性,对任何政治秩序中的信任和稳定都至关重要参见Graeme Orr,选举制度中的仪式和节奏:一个比较的法律解释(Routledge, 2015).1617 . Justin Buchler,《雇佣和解雇官员:重新思考选举的目的》(牛津大学出版社,2011)国际理念目前估计,在203个国家中,有27个国家采用了某种形式的强制投票率;40个国家曾经使用过这个词(其中只有3个国家在地方选举中使用过:奥地利、瑞士和美国)。参见“强制投票”。18 2006年的一项调查确定了23个国家,当时立法规定了选举强制(包括两个仅在次国家一级)。其中16个是“自由的”,6个是“部分自由的”,只有一个(埃及)被列为“不自由的”:选举事务联合常设委员会,《2004年联邦选举:2004年联邦选举行为及其相关事项调查报告》(澳大利亚联邦议会,2006年)附录G.19参见澳大利亚高等法院在Faderson v Bridger (1971) 126 CLR 271中的讨论。 更实际的问题是,投票指示是否意味着选民必须正式在选票上做标记,或者是否注意到破坏选票的能力:格雷姆·奥尔,“不选择的选择:联邦法和保留偏好”(1997)23莫纳什大学法律评论285.20丽莎·希尔,“使用强制投票增加投票率”(2011)31政治27,33。这是为了确保短期内的选举不会受到影响,例如,政党竞选活动的重点是压低对手支持者的投票率;从长远来看,整个选民阶层不会被疏远到他们的声音被忽视的程度查普曼,在第8页,104.22国际IDEA,在第17页。这就排除了仅仅强制选民登记的国家,比如新西兰。“一些”强制包括那些非常年轻、非常年老或海外选民不被强制的国家例如,澳大利亚宪法第128条规定全民公决。但是在1984年之前,每次公民投票都采用一次性立法:Graeme Orr,“澳大利亚公民投票和公民投票的行为:法律视角”(2000)11《公法评论》117。相反,在澳大利亚,公民投票在次国家层面上大多是自由裁量的,然而除了一个州之外,所有州现在都有关于公民投票的立法:Paul Kildea,“州和地区公民投票的法律和历史”(2022)44悉尼法律评论31,49 n 111.24选举观察和能力建设意味着选举法现在被广泛公布例如,《1961年新加坡全民公决条例》第21条(常设全民公决法)和2005年《关于全民公决法》(卢森堡)第37条(一次性全民公决法)例如,Regulación全民公决(ley8492, 2006年4月4日,哥斯达黎加)第5条(常设全民公决法)巴西联邦共和国宪法(1988年)第14条。虽然在全民投票和公民投票的一般程序中没有重申这一点(1998年11月18日第9 709号法令),但在特殊事件的条例中有明确规定(例如1993年7月4日第8 624号法令,第3条)Bechtel等人在上文第4条中描述了一个罕见的例外:瑞士沃州强制参与联邦公民投票——通常是立法而不是宪法——同时不强制参加选举Alvaro Marques和Thomas B Smith,“第三世界的公民投票”(1984)3选举研究85,10130同上,91.31同上,100.32 Duncan McCargo等人,“秩序和平:泰国2016年宪法公投”(2017)65当代东南亚65.33 Oran Doyle,“混乱中的秩序?宪法变迁的类型学和模式”在孔蒂亚德和佛蒂亚杜(编),上面第6、182、182页。关于公民投票问题的另一种类型,请见LeDuc在第9.34条以上所述。关于法治主要是实体价值还是程序价值的辩论反映出的二分法2018年,另一场公投废除了这一禁令。这次公投是准机构性的,因为这个问题并没有保证堕胎的权利,而不是允许立法机构进行监管。但是,鉴于大力推动立法以使法律自由化的背景,它仍然侧重于社会价值当亚里士多德认为人类是动物政治时,他说的是一般的,而不是具体的Graeme Orr,《审议与选举法》(2013)12《选举法》杂志421.38 LeDuc,以上n . 9, 72.39台湾甚至有两种情况:立法机关绝对多数提出全民公决,然后获得所有合格选民的50%批准Regulación重新登记(ley8492, 2006年4月4日,哥斯达黎加)第4.41条辛格,上文第2条24-25款。巧合的是,这次公民投票涉及是否保留选举强制例如,英国脱欧公投获得了登记选民37.5%的投票(投票率为72%)。根据40%的法定人数规则,该法案将无法通过,但如果投票率达到78%,该法案将获得通过。几乎没有评论人士认为投票率扭曲了英国退欧的结果Ron Levy,《宪法公投的审议案例》(2017)16选举法杂志213.44,即使是审议民主派也对选举曾经是审议事件感到绝望:Dennis Thompson,《关于选举的审议,而不是在选举中》(2013)选举法杂志372(认为审议民主派应该把重点放在改革选举规则的公众审议上,而不是竞选活动本身)。关于选举是最适合聚集已有党派观点的纯粹审议荒地的论点,请参见詹姆斯·A·加德纳的《竞选是为了什么?》《说服在选举法和政治中的作用》(牛津大学出版社,2009).45Neil Gow,“在澳大利亚联邦引入强制投票”(1971)6 Politics 201。今天,平等主义者比自由主义者更看重强制。 46 .但是在澳大利亚引入强制投票制度的是中右翼政党,他们担心劳工运动在选出工人阶级选民方面具有优势参见Paul Strangio和Matteo Bonotti的《澳大利亚强制投票的一个世纪:起源、影响和未来》(Palgrave Macmillan, 2021)中的各个章节Graeme Orr,“你将死的方式的选择”:澳大利亚法院对强制投票”,Strangio和Bonotti(编),同上,141.48 Sarah Cameron和Ian MacAllister,澳大利亚公众舆论趋势:1987-2022年澳大利亚选举研究的结果,75(包括1967年的数据)。20世纪80年代的一次轻微下降恰逢一个主要政党质疑强制的时期(主要是在南澳大利亚自由党的自由派内部)有关统计数据,请参见格伦·罗兹,《为澳大利亚投票:殖民地居民在1899-1900年联邦公民投票中如何投票》(澳大利亚公共部门管理中心,格里菲斯大学,2002年)16-17。结果的(不可)预测性不是一个因素:投票率只比投票接近的两个殖民地的平均水平高1-4%乔治·威廉姆斯和大卫·休谟,《人民的力量:澳大利亚公民投票的历史和未来》(新南威尔士大学出版社,2010年),52页在1977年、1984年、1988年和1999年的最后四个全民公决日,投票率超过92%。在上一次这样的事件中,也就是1999年的共和国公投中,支持率达到了95%。这四件事中只有一件与选举同时发生。即使在提案范围狭窄和纯粹是制度主义的时候(如1977年),投票率仍然很高Elisa Arcioni和Adrienne Stone在Xenophon Contiades和Alkmene Fotiadou(编辑)的“澳大利亚的宪法变革:冰冻大陆的悖论”,《劳特利奇比较宪法变革手册》(劳特利奇,2022)388认为,这种单薄一直是一种救赎之恩。54 .非正式的宪法修改由于没有限定太多内容,就能够弥补明确修正案的失败在鸟类的比喻中,它是一只“棕色的小鸟”,与美国宪法中的“鹰”相比:帕特里克·基恩法官,“庆祝宪法”(宪法创始人讲座,2008年6月12日)。55进一步参见Graeme Orr,“澳大利亚公民投票的自愿投票:旧酒,新瓶子”,Ron Levy等人(编),澳大利亚法律的新方向:当代法律改革论文(澳大利亚国立大学出版社,2017)359.56威廉姆斯和休谟,上面第51,205页。我并不是说所有的制度问题都是晦涩难懂的。有时它们与关键的民主结构有关:里克·拉鲁(Rick LaRue)的《我们爱权利法案》(We Love the Bill of Rights)。我们能喜欢一个结构法案吗?(2022)21选举法杂志308.57澳大利亚联邦,是/否-公投' 99 -你的官方公投小册子(澳大利亚选举委员会,1999)17.58正如在“如果它没有坏,不要修理它”的口号下明确指出的那样:同上,15.59克拉斯·沃尔德林,《全民公决中自愿投票的案例》(1976)11政治学209.60威廉姆斯和休谟,见上文第51页,第4章和附录2.61。澳大利亚最后一次成功的全民公决日是在1977年:三个相对较小的修正案获得通过,一个更重要的修正案失败了在过去十年中,尽管各方都同意有必要进行宪法改革,但仍未达成全民公决的例子包括:对过时的限制议员和候选人资格的规则进行现代化改革,以及对联邦资助地方政府的重要做法进行规范化以众议院法律和宪法事务常务委员会为例,是时候改变了:是/否?《公民投票机制调查》(澳大利亚联邦议会,2009年)第4-5章。另见威廉姆斯和休谟,见上文第51页,第7.64章。官方结果显示,67%的人投了赞成票,这一结果一直受到怀疑。从技术上讲,那次投票是一次不具约束力的公民投票。但是,正如导言中所指出的,这与我们无关。在宪法过渡的关键时刻,可能没有预先存在的宪法秩序“强制”进行改革公投。此外,虽然专制政权可以无视其提案被拒绝的事实,但它更有可能改变天平,以确保有利的结果,并在必要时修改提案和投票比例,然后再次尝试早在1925年,自愿登记就已经成为智利的宪法规定。Tiffany D Barnes和Gabriela Rangel,“智利的选举法改革:自动登记和自愿投票的实施”(2014),《选举法杂志》第13期,第570,571页。皮诺切特lost.67帕梅拉·菲格罗亚,新冠肺炎大流行期间的宪法公投:智利的案例(国际思想,案例研究,2021年8月27日)6.70同上,7.71同上,14。 72认识到这一点,澳大利亚在其共和党制宪会议选举中采用了自愿投票:Graeme Orr,“修改公约:澳大利亚1997年制宪会议选举中的自愿投票”(1998)17选举研究575.73 16-17岁的自愿投票:Propuesta Constitución Política de la República de Chile 2022, art 160.1.74 Bechtel等人,上文第4条。这项研究是在瑞士沃州废除强制公民投票之后进行的。尽管在实施时投票率大幅上升(30-36%,取决于提案的显著性),而且对其他自愿联邦选举投票率的明显“溢出”效应较少(12%的额外投票率,如果公投与选举日一致,则上升到24%),但这些影响在沃州废除强制后迅速消退美国则采取相反的方法,把各种各样的选票,地方的、州的、联邦的,都扔到一个普通的日子里实际上,1982年《<s:1>基耶共和国宪法》临时第16条本身就规定,在公民投票中未能投票的人在其后五年内被剥夺选举权和候选人资格埃尔根Özbudun和Ömer法鲁克·根帕拉卡亚:《土耳其的民主化与制宪政治》(中欧大学出版社,2009年)。《人民政府理论与实践的比较研究》(曼彻斯特,2015年)147.79正如常设和相当稳定的选举法是“重复发挥”的一个方面(产生对选举的持续承诺,作为更新代议制授权的手段),这是民主的关键要素:塞缪尔·伊萨查罗夫,《民主的游离:民粹主义和人民主权的腐败》(牛津大学出版社,2023年)第4章。
Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Notes1 ‘Back’ implies that sovereignty derives from the people. ‘Referring’ reminds that a process of choosing which issues to send to a vote – and how to frame them – is involved.2 Eg, Jason Brennan and Lisa Hill, Compulsory Voting: For and Against (Cambridge University Press, 2014), Sarah Birch, Full Participation: a Comparative Study of Compulsory Voting (United Nations University Press, 2009) and Shane P Singh, Beyond Turnout: How Compulsory Voting Shapes Citizens and Political Parties (Oxford University Press, 2021).3 Eg, Costas Panagopoulos, ‘The Calculus of Voting in Compulsory Voting Systems’ (2008) 30 Political Behavior 455 cf Alberto Chong and Mauricio Olivera, ‘On Compulsory Voting and Income Equality’ (Inter-American Development Bank, Working Paper #33, 5/2005).4 Eg, Loren E Lomasky and Geoffrey Brennan, ‘Is There a Duty to Vote?’ (2000) 17 Social Philosophy and Policy 62 cf Michael M Bechtel et al, ‘Compulsory Voting, Habit Formation, and Political Participation’ (2018) 100 The Review of Economics and Statistics 467.5 Eg, Bart Engelen, ‘Why Compulsory Voting Can Enhance Democracy’ (2007) 42 Acta Politica 23. Conversely, it has been argued that compulsion could be used to accentuate a slippage into anti-democratic populism: Pete Crabb, ‘Compulsory Voting and Populism’ (SSRN, doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3662725, 5/9/2020).6 Eg, Xenophon Contiades and Alkmene Fotiadou, Participatory Constitutional Change: The People as Amenders of the Constitution (Routledge, 2016) and Julie Smith, The Palgrave Handbook of European Referendums (Palgrave Macmillan, 2021).7 Respectively: Karin Gilland Lutz and Simon Hug (eds), Financing Referendum Campaigns (Palgrave Macmillan, 2009), Sandrine Baume et al (eds); Misinformation in Referenda (Routledge, 2020); and Ron Levy et al, Deliberative Peace Referendums (Oxford University Press, 2021).8 Eg, Emilee Booth Chapman, ‘The Distinctive Value of Elections and the Case of Compulsory Voting’ (2019) 63 American Journal of Political Science 101, 102 (parenthetically suggesting that the case for compulsion in large-scale elections ‘potentially’ applies to referendums).9 See distinctions in Larry LeDuc, The Politics of Direct Democracy: Referendums in Global Perspective (University of Toronto Press, 2003) 39. I do not otherwise adopt LeDuc’s four-part typology of referendum topics (‘constitutional issues’, ‘treaties and international agreements’, ‘sovereignty, national self-determination and devolution’, and ‘public policy issues’). Whilst useful for a political scientist, they involve too much overlap to be categorically useful.10 Rick Hasen, ‘Voting Without Law?’ (1996) 144 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 2135, 2135.11 In some systems of course, citizens can initiate constitutional referendums, as in Italy and some smaller European democracies: Alan Renwick and Jess Sergeant, ‘The Rules of Referendums’ in Smith, above n 6, 71.12 ‘The concept of representation is misleadingly simple; everyone seems to know what it is, yet few can agree on any particular definition … of this elusive concept’: Suzanne Dovi, ‘Political Representation’, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (Stanford University, 2018 revision). Its paradoxes were identified in Hannah Fenichel Pitkin’s The Concept of Representation (University of California Press, 1967).13 Graeme Orr, ‘The Law of Electoral Democracy: Theory and Purpose’ in Alan Bogg et al (eds), The Constitution of Social Democracy (Hart, 2020)173–75. These are constructive or insider perspectives; a fourth is the cynical or outsider perspective, where electoral democracy is just a game masking entrenched inequities or oppression.14 I use ‘ultimate’ here not in the of ‘necessary if not sufficient’: a sense of legitimacy, perceived and real, being essential to trust and stability within any political order.15 See further Graeme Orr, Ritual and Rhythm in Electoral Systems: A Comparative Legal Account (Routledge, 2015).16 Justin Buchler, Hiring and Firing Officials: Rethinking the Purpose of Elections (Oxford University Press, 2011).17 International IDEA currently reckons that 27 countries (out of 203) employ some form of compulsion in turnout; and that 40 have ever used it (including three only ever at some sub-national elections: Austria, Switzerland and the US). See ‘Compulsory Voting’ .18 A 2006 survey identified 23 countries where electoral compulsion was then legislated for (including two only at sub-national level). Of these 16 were ‘free’, six ‘partly free’ and only one (Egypt) classed as ‘not free’: Joint Standing Committee on Electoral Matters, The 2004 Federal Election: Report of the Inquiry into the Conduct of the 2004 Federal Election and Matters Related Thereto (Parliament of the Commonwealth of Australia, 2006) Appendix G.19 See discussion in the Australian High Court in Faderson v Bridger (1971) 126 CLR 271. The more pragmatic question is whether ballot instructions imply that the voter must mark the ballot formally or whether the ability to spoil the ballot is noted: Graeme Orr, ‘The Choice Not to Choose: Commonwealth Law and the Withholding of Preferences’ (1997) 23 Monash University Law Review 285.20 Lisa Hill, ‘Increasing Turnout Using Compulsory Voting’ (2011) 31 Politics 27, 33. This is to ensure that elections in the short term are not skewed, eg, by party campaigns focusing on depressing the turnout of their rivals’ supporters; and in the longer term that whole classes of the electorate are not alienated such that their voices are unheeded.21 Chapman, above n 8, 104.22 International IDEA, above n 17. This excludes countries that merely compel voter registration, such as New Zealand. ‘Some’ compulsion includes countries where very young, very old or overseas electors are not compelled.23 Eg, s 128 of the Australian Constitution mandates referendums. But one-off legislation was used to run every referendum until 1984: Graeme Orr, ‘The Conduct of Referenda and Plebiscites in Australia: a Legal Perspective’ (2000) 11 Public Law Review 117. Conversely, referendums are mostly discretionary at the sub-national level in Australia, yet all bar one State now has standing legislation for them: Paul Kildea, ‘The Law and History of State and Territory Referendums' (2022) 44 Sydney Law Review 31, 49 n 111.24 Election observation and capacity-building means that electoral acts are now widely published.25 Eg, Singapore National Referendum Ordinance 1961, s 21 (standing referendum law) and Loi du 4 février 2005 relative au référendum au niveau national (Luxembourg) art 37 (one-off referendum law).26 Eg, Regulación del Referéndum (Ley 8492, 4/4/2006, Costa Rica) art 5 (standing referendum law).27 Constitution of the Federal Republic of Brazil (1988) art 14. Whilst this is not restated in the general procedures for plebiscites and referendums (Lei 9,709 de 18 de Novembro 1998) it is explicit in regulations for particular events (eg Lei 8,624 de 4 de Fevereiro 1993, art 3).28 A rare exception is described in Bechtel et al, above n 4: the Swiss canton of Vaud compelled participation in federal referendums – typically legislative rather than constitutional – whilst not mandating turnout for elections.29 Alvaro Marques and Thomas B Smith, ‘Referendums in the Third World’ (1984) 3 Electoral Studies 85, 10130 Ibid, 91.31 Ibid, 100.32 Duncan McCargo et al, ‘Ordering Peace: Thailand’s 2016 Constitutional Referendum’ (2017) 65 Contemporary Southeast Asia 65.33 Oran Doyle, ‘Order from Chaos? Typologies and Models of Constitutional Change’ in Contiades and Fotiadou (eds), above n 6, 182, 182. For a different typology of referendum issues to mine, see LeDuc, above n 9.34 A dichotomy mirrored in debates about whether the rule of law is primarily a substantive or procedural value.35 In 2018, another referendum repealed the prohibition. This referendum was quasi-institutional, since the question did not guarantee abortion rights as opposed to permitting the legislature to regulate. But it remained focused on social values, given the context was a strong push for legislation to liberalise the law.36 When Aristotle held that humans are zoon politikon, he was talking generally not specifically.37 Graeme Orr, ‘Deliberation and Electoral Law’ (2013) 12 Election Law Journal 421.38 LeDuc, above n 9, 72.39 Taiwan even has both: legislative supermajority to propose a referendum, then approval by 50% of all eligible voters.40 Regulación del Referéndum (Ley 8492, 4/4/2006, Costa Rica) art 4.41 Singh, above n 2, 24–25. Co-incidentally, that referendum concerned whether to retain electoral compulsion.42 For instance, the Brexit referendum achieved a vote of 37.5% of the enrolled electorate (on a turnout of 72%). It would have failed under a 40% quorum rule, but passed if turnout were 78%. Few commentators believe turnout skewed the Brexit result.43 Ron Levy, ‘Deliberative Case for Constitutional Referenda’ (2017) 16 Election Law Journal 213.44 Even deliberative democrats despair at elections ever being deliberative events: Dennis Thompson, ‘Deliberate About, Not In, Elections’ (2013) Election Law Journal 372 (arguing that deliberative democrats should focus on popular deliberation in reforming the rules of elections, rather than election campaigns themselves). For an argument that elections are flat-out deliberative wastelands best suited to the aggregation of pre-existing partisan views, see James A Gardner, What are Campaigns For? The Role of Persuasion in Electoral Law and Politics (Oxford University Press, 2009).45 Neil Gow, ‘The Introduction of Compulsory Voting in the Australian Commonwealth’ (1971) 6 Politics 201. Today, egalitarians value compulsion more than libertarians. But it was the centre-right parties who introduced compulsory voting in Australia, fearing that the labour movement had an advantage in turning out working class electors.46 See various chapters in Paul Strangio and Matteo Bonotti, A Century of Compulsory Voting in Australia: Genesis, Impact and Future (Palgrave Macmillan, 2021).47 Graeme Orr, ‘Choice of the Manner in Which Thou Wilt Die’: The Australian Courts on Compulsory Voting’ in Strangio and Bonotti (eds), ibid, 141.48 Sarah Cameron and Ian MacAllister, Trends in Australian Public Opinion: Results from the Australian Election Study 1987–2022, 75 (including data back to 1967). A shallow dip in the 1980s coincided with the one period when a major party has questioned compulsion (primarily within the liberal wing of the South Australian Liberal Party).49 For statistics see Glenn Rhodes, Votes for Australia: How Colonials Voted at the 1899–1900 Federation Referendums (Centre for Australian Public Sector Management, Griffith University, 2002) 16–17. The (un)predictability of outcomes was not a factor: turnout was only 1–4% higher than average in the two colonies where the vote was close.50 Australian Constitution, s 128.51 George Williams and David Hume, People Power: the History and Future of the Referendum in Australia (UNSW Press, 2010).52 At the last four national referendum days, in 1977, 1984, 1988 and 1999, turnout has been over 92%. It peaked at 95% for the last such event, the 1999 Republic referendum. Only one of those four events coincided with an election. Turnout remained high even when the proposals were narrow and purely institutionalist (as in 1977).53 Elisa Arcioni and Adrienne Stone, ‘Constitutional Change in Australia: The Paradox of the Frozen Continent’ in Xenophon Contiades and Alkmene Fotiadou (eds), Routledge Handbook on Comparative Constitutional Change (Routledge, 2022) 388 argue that this thinness has been a saving grace. By not locking-in too much, informal constitutional change has been able to compensate for the failure of explicit amendments.54 In an avian metaphor, it is a ‘small brown bird’ compared to the US constitutional ‘eagle’: Justice Patrick Keane, ‘In Celebration of the Constitution’ (Constitution Founders Lecture, 12/6/2008).55 See further, Graeme Orr, ‘Voluntary Voting for Referendums in Australia: Old Wine, New Bottle’ in Ron Levy et al (eds), New Directions for Law in Australian: Essays in Contemporary Law Reform (ANU Press, 2017) 359.56 Williams and Hume, above n 51, 205. I am not saying that all institutional questions are arcane. Sometimes they relate to key democratic structures: Rick LaRue, ‘We Love the Bill of Rights. Can We Like a Bill of Structures’ (2022) 21 Election Law Journal 308.57 Commonwealth of Australia, Yes/No – Referendum ’99 – Your Official Referendum Pamphlet (Australian Electoral Commission, 1999) 17.58 As distinctly argued under the slogan ‘If it ain’t broke, don’t fix it’: ibid, 15.59 Klaas Woldring, ‘The Case for Voluntary Voting in Referendums’ (1976) 11 Politics 209.60 Williams and Hume, above n 51, ch 4 and appendix 2.61 The last successful national referendum day in Australia was in 1977: three relatively minor amendments were approved, one more substantial one failed.62 Examples in the past decade that have not reached a referendum despite all sides agreeing constitutional reform is necessary include modernising dated rules limiting qualifications of MPs and candidates, and regularising the vital practice of Commonwealth funding of local governments.63 Exemplified in House of Representatives Standing Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs, A Time for Change: Yes/No? Inquiry into the Machinery of Referendums (Parliament of the Commonwealth of Australia, 2009) chs 4–5. See also Williams and Hume, above n 51, ch 7.64 The official result, of a 67% ‘yes’ vote, has been the subject of suspicion. Technically that vote was a non-binding plebiscite. But, as noted in the introduction, that does not concern us. In liminal moments, of constitutional transition, there may be no pre-existing constitutional order ‘mandating’ a referendum for reform. Further, whilst an authoritarian regime could ignore the rejection of one of its proposals, it is more likely to tilt the scales to try to ensure a favourable outcome and, if necessary, modify the proposal and the voting scales and try again.65 Voluntary registration had until then been a constitutional rule in Chile as far back as 1925.66 Tiffany D Barnes and Gabriela Rangel, ‘Election Law Reform in Chile: the Implementation of Automatic Registration and Voluntary Voting’ (2014) 13 Election Law Journal 570, 571. Pinochet lost.67 Ibid, 572–73.68 Ibid, 573–76.69 Pamela Figueroa, Constitutional Referendum During the Covid-19 Pandemic: the Case of Chile (International IDEA, Case Study, 27/8/2021) 6.70 Ibid, 7.71 Ibid, 14.72 Recognising this, Australia employed voluntary voting for its Republican Constitutional Convention election: Graeme Orr, ‘Tinkering with Convention: Voluntary Voting at Australia's 1997 Constitutional Convention Election’ (1998) 17 Electoral Studies 575.73 With voluntary voting for 16–17 year olds: Propuesta Constitución Política de la República de Chile 2022, art 160.1.74 Bechtel et al, above n 4. The study followed the repeal of referendum compulsion in the Vaud canton of Switzerland. Despite a strong turnout boost whilst it was in place (30–36%, depending on the proposal’s salience) and a clear ‘spillover’ effect on turnout at otherwise voluntary federal elections was less (12% extra turnout, rising to 24% if a referendum coincided with an election day) these effects quickly subsided after Vaud repealed compulsion.75 The US takes the opposite approach, throwing all manner of ballots, local/state/federal, onto a common day.76 Indeed provisional article 16 of the Constitution of the Republic of Türkiye (1982) itself included deprivation of electoral and candidacy rights, for five years following, for those who failed to vote at that referendum.77 Ergun Özbudun and Ömer Faruk Gençkaya, Democratization and the Politics of Constitution-Making in Turkey (Central European University Press, 2009) 20.78 Mads Qvortup, Direct Democracy: A Comparative Study of the Theory and Practice of Government by the People (Manchester UP, 2015) 147.79 Just as standing and fairly stable electoral laws are an aspect of the ‘repeat play’ (generating ongoing commitment to elections as a means of renewing representative mandates) that is a key element of democracy: Samuel Issacharoff, Democracy Unmoored: Populism and the Corruption of Popular Sovereignty (Oxford University Press, 2023) ch 4.