洛克式的对无证移民道德地位的描述

Pub Date : 2023-11-09 DOI:10.1080/13698230.2023.2280878
J.K. Numao
{"title":"洛克式的对无证移民道德地位的描述","authors":"J.K. Numao","doi":"10.1080/13698230.2023.2280878","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTThis article aims to show that Locke’s discussion of tacit consent and the right to punish aliens in the Second Treatise of Government has important bearings on the moral status of undocumented immigrants. It argues that Locke conceptualized both friendly and hostile aliens, counting the former as tacit consenters to whom host states owed rights and protection. Moreover, it highlights how his approach, unlike theorists before and after him, was one that saw individuals as capable of shaping their own relationship with the host. The article also examines Locke’s discussion of the federative power of the state, which includes the power to vet aliens within the country. Seen through this Lockean lens, the article argues that the vast majority of undocumented immigrants can be understood as tacit consenters or potential citizens who should be judged by how they choose to relate to the host, and not by their country of origin. While noting that the Lockean approach is not incompatible with border control, the article also shows how it puts the onus on the host to justify the power it exercises and to engage in dialogue with undocumented immigrants about what their status should be in the country.KEYWORDS: Lockeirregular migrationundocumented immigrantstacit consentpunishment AcknowledgmentsI would like to thank everyone who attended the online Locke working group workshop on June 25th, 2021. I have benefited greatly from their questions and comments. I would especially like to thank Douglas Casson who was the commentator for my session on this occasion. I would also like to thank Takuya Furuta and Brian Smith for reading an earlier version of this paper. Finally, I would like to thank the editor and the anonymous reviewers for their invaluable feedback.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. By this, I mean irregular migration as it tends to be understood today. For example, the International Organization for Migration (IOM) defines this type of migration as the ‘Movement of persons that takes place outside the laws, regulations, or international agreements governing the entry into or exit from the State of origin, transit or destination’. https://www.iom.int/key-migration-terms (Accessed on September 9, 2021). However, what may be considered ‘irregular’ by today’s standards may not have been irregular, but quite ‘regular’, in seventeenth-century England. What I am doing therefore is to consider the implications of Locke’s comments for the debate over irregular immigration today. I am grateful to Brian Smith for his suggestion to clarify this point.2. References to Locke (Citation1988) will be by book (Roman numeral) and paragraph number (Arabic numeral).3. The irrevocability of citizenship may be puzzling to some and may make Locke’s theory less appealing. I make no effort in this article to explain or defend it, simply regarding it as a part of Locke’s argument. At the same time, I do not think it seriously undercuts the relevance of Locke’s discussion for undocumented immigrants.4. In seventeenth-century England, denizenship was a legal status granted by the King. Denizens enjoyed certain rights such as the right to purchase land or send their children to English schools. However, it was a status short of full citizenship, and so they did not enjoy political rights nor the right to bequeath their land to their children (Casalini, Citation2008; Matar, Citation2008).5. That is 21 years or older (II.59). According to the ‘Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina’, adulthood starts at 17 (Locke, Citation1997b, p. 179, 181). I am grateful to Brian Smith for pointing this out to me.6. So, while the state of nature is a ‘State of perfect Freedom’ (II.3), unless you were living outside an existing political society, you would quickly become a tacit consenter, agreeing to subject yourself to some kind of rule without leaving your natural state.7. Pinheiro (Citation2020, p. 14) suggests that Locke was not interested in naturalizing unskilled agrarian workers. Locke (Citation1997a, pp. 324–25), however, plays down the fear that the labourers would be ‘idle’ or that ‘too many’ would come in.8. I am grateful to Johan Olsthoorn for pointing this out to me. A brief survey of how Locke uses the term ‘in effect’ in the Two Treatises of Government and other works such as the Letter Concerning Toleration shows that the reading is consistent with his use.9. Perhaps Simmons (Citation1992, p. 86) implies this when he refers to the alien tacit consenters ‘with whom the state is at peace’. See also Simmons (Citation2001, p. 169). My point here is that this point needs to be emphasized much more.10. Both Waldron (Citation2002, p. 125) and Ward (Citation2010, p. 82) note the complementary nature of the two arguments while offering no explanation as to why this is so.11. Perhaps there is an interesting question about punishing crimes committed by an alien tacit consenter against another alien tacit consenter from a different country.12. Other interesting cases might include bluffers and deniers of hostile intent. Also, in the aforementioned case of the fleeing former tacit consenter, should the state decide to punish this individual, the state would use its federative power.13. ‘Offences for which aliens, within the jurisdiction of a country are punishable, are – first, offences committed by the nation of which they make a part, and in whose offences they are involved; secondly, offences committed by themselves alone, without any charge against the nation to which they belong. The first is the case of alien enemies; the second, the case of alien friends’ (Madison, Citation1900, p. 364).14. See also Madison (Citation1900, p. 366): ‘that the removal of alien enemies is an incident to the power of war; that the removal of alien friends is not an incident to the power of war’.15. I have benefited from an exchange with Douglas Casson on this point. His comments have helped me clarify the point I wanted to make.Additional informationFundingKeio Gijuku Academic Development FundsNotes on contributorsJ.K. NumaoJ.K. Numao is an Associate Professor of Foreign Languages and Liberal Arts in the Faculty of Science and Technology at Keio University. His research interests are in political theory and the history of political thought, especially the ideas of the seventeenth-century English thinker John Locke. He has written on topics ranging from toleration to emigration.","PeriodicalId":0,"journal":{"name":"","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"A Lockean account of the moral status of undocumented immigrants\",\"authors\":\"J.K. Numao\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/13698230.2023.2280878\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"ABSTRACTThis article aims to show that Locke’s discussion of tacit consent and the right to punish aliens in the Second Treatise of Government has important bearings on the moral status of undocumented immigrants. It argues that Locke conceptualized both friendly and hostile aliens, counting the former as tacit consenters to whom host states owed rights and protection. Moreover, it highlights how his approach, unlike theorists before and after him, was one that saw individuals as capable of shaping their own relationship with the host. The article also examines Locke’s discussion of the federative power of the state, which includes the power to vet aliens within the country. Seen through this Lockean lens, the article argues that the vast majority of undocumented immigrants can be understood as tacit consenters or potential citizens who should be judged by how they choose to relate to the host, and not by their country of origin. While noting that the Lockean approach is not incompatible with border control, the article also shows how it puts the onus on the host to justify the power it exercises and to engage in dialogue with undocumented immigrants about what their status should be in the country.KEYWORDS: Lockeirregular migrationundocumented immigrantstacit consentpunishment AcknowledgmentsI would like to thank everyone who attended the online Locke working group workshop on June 25th, 2021. I have benefited greatly from their questions and comments. I would especially like to thank Douglas Casson who was the commentator for my session on this occasion. I would also like to thank Takuya Furuta and Brian Smith for reading an earlier version of this paper. Finally, I would like to thank the editor and the anonymous reviewers for their invaluable feedback.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. By this, I mean irregular migration as it tends to be understood today. For example, the International Organization for Migration (IOM) defines this type of migration as the ‘Movement of persons that takes place outside the laws, regulations, or international agreements governing the entry into or exit from the State of origin, transit or destination’. https://www.iom.int/key-migration-terms (Accessed on September 9, 2021). However, what may be considered ‘irregular’ by today’s standards may not have been irregular, but quite ‘regular’, in seventeenth-century England. What I am doing therefore is to consider the implications of Locke’s comments for the debate over irregular immigration today. I am grateful to Brian Smith for his suggestion to clarify this point.2. References to Locke (Citation1988) will be by book (Roman numeral) and paragraph number (Arabic numeral).3. The irrevocability of citizenship may be puzzling to some and may make Locke’s theory less appealing. I make no effort in this article to explain or defend it, simply regarding it as a part of Locke’s argument. At the same time, I do not think it seriously undercuts the relevance of Locke’s discussion for undocumented immigrants.4. In seventeenth-century England, denizenship was a legal status granted by the King. Denizens enjoyed certain rights such as the right to purchase land or send their children to English schools. However, it was a status short of full citizenship, and so they did not enjoy political rights nor the right to bequeath their land to their children (Casalini, Citation2008; Matar, Citation2008).5. That is 21 years or older (II.59). According to the ‘Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina’, adulthood starts at 17 (Locke, Citation1997b, p. 179, 181). I am grateful to Brian Smith for pointing this out to me.6. So, while the state of nature is a ‘State of perfect Freedom’ (II.3), unless you were living outside an existing political society, you would quickly become a tacit consenter, agreeing to subject yourself to some kind of rule without leaving your natural state.7. Pinheiro (Citation2020, p. 14) suggests that Locke was not interested in naturalizing unskilled agrarian workers. Locke (Citation1997a, pp. 324–25), however, plays down the fear that the labourers would be ‘idle’ or that ‘too many’ would come in.8. I am grateful to Johan Olsthoorn for pointing this out to me. A brief survey of how Locke uses the term ‘in effect’ in the Two Treatises of Government and other works such as the Letter Concerning Toleration shows that the reading is consistent with his use.9. Perhaps Simmons (Citation1992, p. 86) implies this when he refers to the alien tacit consenters ‘with whom the state is at peace’. See also Simmons (Citation2001, p. 169). My point here is that this point needs to be emphasized much more.10. Both Waldron (Citation2002, p. 125) and Ward (Citation2010, p. 82) note the complementary nature of the two arguments while offering no explanation as to why this is so.11. Perhaps there is an interesting question about punishing crimes committed by an alien tacit consenter against another alien tacit consenter from a different country.12. Other interesting cases might include bluffers and deniers of hostile intent. Also, in the aforementioned case of the fleeing former tacit consenter, should the state decide to punish this individual, the state would use its federative power.13. ‘Offences for which aliens, within the jurisdiction of a country are punishable, are – first, offences committed by the nation of which they make a part, and in whose offences they are involved; secondly, offences committed by themselves alone, without any charge against the nation to which they belong. The first is the case of alien enemies; the second, the case of alien friends’ (Madison, Citation1900, p. 364).14. See also Madison (Citation1900, p. 366): ‘that the removal of alien enemies is an incident to the power of war; that the removal of alien friends is not an incident to the power of war’.15. I have benefited from an exchange with Douglas Casson on this point. His comments have helped me clarify the point I wanted to make.Additional informationFundingKeio Gijuku Academic Development FundsNotes on contributorsJ.K. NumaoJ.K. Numao is an Associate Professor of Foreign Languages and Liberal Arts in the Faculty of Science and Technology at Keio University. His research interests are in political theory and the history of political thought, especially the ideas of the seventeenth-century English thinker John Locke. He has written on topics ranging from toleration to emigration.\",\"PeriodicalId\":0,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-11-09\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2023.2280878\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2023.2280878","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

也许有一个有趣的问题是关于惩罚一个外籍默许者对另一个来自不同国家的外籍默许者所犯的罪行。其他有趣的案例可能包括虚张声势和否认敌对意图。此外,在上述逃亡的前默许者的案件中,如果国家决定惩罚这个人,国家将使用其联邦权力。“外国人在一国管辖范围内应受惩处的罪行,首先是他们所属的国家所犯的罪行,并且他们参与了该国家的罪行;第二,他们自己单独犯下的罪行,对他们所属的国家没有任何指控。第一种情况是外来敌人;第二,外星人朋友的案例”(麦迪逊,引文1900,第364页)。另见麦迪逊(引文1900,第366页):“清除外来敌人是战争力量的一个事件;驱逐异族朋友并不是战争力量的偶然事件。在这一点上,我与道格拉斯·卡森(Douglas Casson)的交流让我受益匪浅。他的评论帮助我澄清了我想表达的观点。其他信息资助keio Gijuku学术发展基金捐助者说明。NumaoJ.K。Numao是日本庆应义塾大学科学技术学院外语文学系副教授。他的研究兴趣是政治理论和政治思想史,尤其是17世纪英国思想家约翰·洛克的思想。他写过的话题从宽容到移民都有。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
分享
查看原文
A Lockean account of the moral status of undocumented immigrants
ABSTRACTThis article aims to show that Locke’s discussion of tacit consent and the right to punish aliens in the Second Treatise of Government has important bearings on the moral status of undocumented immigrants. It argues that Locke conceptualized both friendly and hostile aliens, counting the former as tacit consenters to whom host states owed rights and protection. Moreover, it highlights how his approach, unlike theorists before and after him, was one that saw individuals as capable of shaping their own relationship with the host. The article also examines Locke’s discussion of the federative power of the state, which includes the power to vet aliens within the country. Seen through this Lockean lens, the article argues that the vast majority of undocumented immigrants can be understood as tacit consenters or potential citizens who should be judged by how they choose to relate to the host, and not by their country of origin. While noting that the Lockean approach is not incompatible with border control, the article also shows how it puts the onus on the host to justify the power it exercises and to engage in dialogue with undocumented immigrants about what their status should be in the country.KEYWORDS: Lockeirregular migrationundocumented immigrantstacit consentpunishment AcknowledgmentsI would like to thank everyone who attended the online Locke working group workshop on June 25th, 2021. I have benefited greatly from their questions and comments. I would especially like to thank Douglas Casson who was the commentator for my session on this occasion. I would also like to thank Takuya Furuta and Brian Smith for reading an earlier version of this paper. Finally, I would like to thank the editor and the anonymous reviewers for their invaluable feedback.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. By this, I mean irregular migration as it tends to be understood today. For example, the International Organization for Migration (IOM) defines this type of migration as the ‘Movement of persons that takes place outside the laws, regulations, or international agreements governing the entry into or exit from the State of origin, transit or destination’. https://www.iom.int/key-migration-terms (Accessed on September 9, 2021). However, what may be considered ‘irregular’ by today’s standards may not have been irregular, but quite ‘regular’, in seventeenth-century England. What I am doing therefore is to consider the implications of Locke’s comments for the debate over irregular immigration today. I am grateful to Brian Smith for his suggestion to clarify this point.2. References to Locke (Citation1988) will be by book (Roman numeral) and paragraph number (Arabic numeral).3. The irrevocability of citizenship may be puzzling to some and may make Locke’s theory less appealing. I make no effort in this article to explain or defend it, simply regarding it as a part of Locke’s argument. At the same time, I do not think it seriously undercuts the relevance of Locke’s discussion for undocumented immigrants.4. In seventeenth-century England, denizenship was a legal status granted by the King. Denizens enjoyed certain rights such as the right to purchase land or send their children to English schools. However, it was a status short of full citizenship, and so they did not enjoy political rights nor the right to bequeath their land to their children (Casalini, Citation2008; Matar, Citation2008).5. That is 21 years or older (II.59). According to the ‘Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina’, adulthood starts at 17 (Locke, Citation1997b, p. 179, 181). I am grateful to Brian Smith for pointing this out to me.6. So, while the state of nature is a ‘State of perfect Freedom’ (II.3), unless you were living outside an existing political society, you would quickly become a tacit consenter, agreeing to subject yourself to some kind of rule without leaving your natural state.7. Pinheiro (Citation2020, p. 14) suggests that Locke was not interested in naturalizing unskilled agrarian workers. Locke (Citation1997a, pp. 324–25), however, plays down the fear that the labourers would be ‘idle’ or that ‘too many’ would come in.8. I am grateful to Johan Olsthoorn for pointing this out to me. A brief survey of how Locke uses the term ‘in effect’ in the Two Treatises of Government and other works such as the Letter Concerning Toleration shows that the reading is consistent with his use.9. Perhaps Simmons (Citation1992, p. 86) implies this when he refers to the alien tacit consenters ‘with whom the state is at peace’. See also Simmons (Citation2001, p. 169). My point here is that this point needs to be emphasized much more.10. Both Waldron (Citation2002, p. 125) and Ward (Citation2010, p. 82) note the complementary nature of the two arguments while offering no explanation as to why this is so.11. Perhaps there is an interesting question about punishing crimes committed by an alien tacit consenter against another alien tacit consenter from a different country.12. Other interesting cases might include bluffers and deniers of hostile intent. Also, in the aforementioned case of the fleeing former tacit consenter, should the state decide to punish this individual, the state would use its federative power.13. ‘Offences for which aliens, within the jurisdiction of a country are punishable, are – first, offences committed by the nation of which they make a part, and in whose offences they are involved; secondly, offences committed by themselves alone, without any charge against the nation to which they belong. The first is the case of alien enemies; the second, the case of alien friends’ (Madison, Citation1900, p. 364).14. See also Madison (Citation1900, p. 366): ‘that the removal of alien enemies is an incident to the power of war; that the removal of alien friends is not an incident to the power of war’.15. I have benefited from an exchange with Douglas Casson on this point. His comments have helped me clarify the point I wanted to make.Additional informationFundingKeio Gijuku Academic Development FundsNotes on contributorsJ.K. NumaoJ.K. Numao is an Associate Professor of Foreign Languages and Liberal Arts in the Faculty of Science and Technology at Keio University. His research interests are in political theory and the history of political thought, especially the ideas of the seventeenth-century English thinker John Locke. He has written on topics ranging from toleration to emigration.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信