{"title":"风险偏好类型、有限考虑和福利","authors":"Levon Barseghyan, Francesca Molinari","doi":"10.1080/07350015.2023.2239949","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"AbstractWe provide sufficient conditions for semi-nonparametric point identification of a mixture model of decision making under risk, when agents make choices in multiple lines of insurance coverage (contexts) by purchasing a bundle. As a first departure from the related literature, the model allows for two preference types. In the first one, agents behave according to standard expected utility theory with CARA Bernoulli utility function, with an agent-specific coefficient of absolute risk aversion whose distribution is left completely unspecified. In the other, agents behave according to the dual theory of choice under risk combined with a one-parameter family distortion function, where the parameter is agent-specific and is drawn from a distribution that is left completely unspecified. Within each preference type, the model allows for unobserved heterogeneity in consideration sets, where the latter form at the bundle level—a second departure from the related literature. Our point identification result rests on observing sufficient variation in covariates across contexts, without requiring any independent variation across alternatives within a single context. We estimate the model on data on households’ deductible choices in two lines of property insurance, and use the results to assess the welfare implications of a hypothetical market intervention where the two lines of insurance are combined into a single one. We study the role of limited consideration in mediating the welfare effects of such intervention.KEYWORDS: (Non-)expected utilityRisk preferencesSemi-nonparametric identificationUnobserved consideration sets AcknowledgmentsWe thank the editor, Ivan Canay, two anonymous reviewers, Matias Cattaneo, Cristina Gualdani, Elisabeth Honka, Xinwei Ma, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Julie Mortimer, Deborah Doukas, Roberta Olivieri, and conference participants at FUR22 and at the JBES session at the ESWM23 for helpful comments.Disclosure StatementThe authors report there are no competing interests to declare.Notes1 This assumption is sometimes viewed as an aspect of rationality (e.g., Kahneman Citation2003), and is credible in our empirical study of demand in very similar contexts (collision and comprehensive deductible insurance).2 Within a single insurance company, typically in a given context if an agent faces a larger price than another agent for one alternative, the first agent faces a (proportionally) larger price for all other alternatives.3 See Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b) for a formal discussion and Section 4.3 for further details.4 See Section 4.2 for additional information on the data.5 The multiplicative factors {glj:l∈Dj} are known as the deductible factors and δj is a small markup known as the expense fee.6 Multiple preference types are a focus of the literature that estimates risk preferences using experimental data (e.g., Bruhin, Fehr-Duda, and Epper Citation2010; Harrison, Humphrey, and Verschoor Citation2010; Conte, Hey, and Moffatt Citation2011), although preferences are homogeneous within each type, at most conditioning on some observed demographic characteristics.7 Other preferences that are characterized by a scalar parameter include ones exhibiting constant relative risk aversion (CRRA), or negligible third derivative (NTD; see, e.g., Cohen and Einav Citation2007; Barseghyan et al. Citation2013). Under CRRA, it is required that agents’ initial wealth is known to the researcher.8 Recall that our analysis conditions on μij, hence, the distribution of preferences may depend on it.9 All papers that estimate risk preferences in the field as reviewed in Barseghyan et al. (Citation2018) impose it.10 The SCP is satisfied in many contexts, ranging from single agent models with goods that can be unambiguously ordered based on quality, to multiple agents models (e.g., Athey Citation2001).11 We assume that while ν and ω have bounded support, the utility functions in U1 and U0 are well defined for any real valued ν and ω, respectively.12 For a discussion of possible failures of SCP, see Apesteguia and Ballester (Citation2018).13 Recall that our analysis conditions on μij, hence, the distribution of consideration sets may depend on it.14 For example, a $500 deductible at price xI in collision insurance and a $500 deductible at price xII in comprehensive insurance would enter the consideration set independently.15 The results extend easily to more than two contexts, at the cost of heavier notation.16 See Figure 3.1 and its discussion below.17 In our empirical model described in Section 4, this intersection point corresponds to ν = 0 and ω = 1, that is, respectively, no risk aversion and no probability distortions.18 Recall that these assumptions, jointly, imply that any agent who draws ν<V2,11,1(xI′)<V1,21,1(xII′) unambiguously prefers alternative l1I to all other alternatives in DI, unambiguously prefers alternative l1II to all other alternatives in DII, and therefore unambiguously prefers bundle I1,1 to any other bundle in D.19 Equivalently, bundle Il,q is chosen if and only if it is the first best among the ones considered:Pr(I*=Il,q|x)=α∑Il,q∈KQ1(K)∫1(CEν(Ik,r,x)≤CEν(Il,q,x) ∀Ik,r∈K|x;ν)dF+(1−α)∑Il,q∈KQ0(K)∫1(CEω(Ik,r,x)≤CEω(Il,q,x) ∀Ik,r∈K|x;ω)dG.20 For ∂Pr(I*=I1,1|x)∂xII, the right-hand side of (3.9) remains as is, with ∂xII replacing ∂xI.21 Alternatively, O1({I1,1,I1,2};∅)=O1({I1,1,I1,2};{I2,2,I2,1}) can replace the last condition in Assumption 3.5-(II). In our application this alternative restriction is satisfied because bundle I1,2 (which is the deductible bundle {$1000,$500} ) is chosen with probability zero, and hence both probabilities are zero.22 These conditions are available from the authors upon request, and require that ∂V1,21,1(x)/∂xII does not equal a specific linear function of ∂V2,11,1(x)/∂xI.23 If one had variation in xj across alternatives and unbounded support, letting the observed covariate (say, price) for a given alternative go to infinity would be akin to assuming that one observes agents repeated choices in context j while facing feasible sets that include/exclude each single alternative.24 For example, if for type ti = 1 alternative Il,k dominates alternative Iq,r, Q1({Il,k,Iq,r}) cannot be separately identified from Q1({Il,k}).25 For example, Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b) require that whenever l1I is considered, l2I is also considered. They do so because there is not a one-to-one mapping between ∂Pr(I*=I1|x)/∂xI and the (up-to-scale) density function evaluated at a single point. Rather, ∂Pr(I*=I1|x)/∂xI maps into a linear combination of the density function evaluated at cutoffs Vk1(xI),k>1. In contrast, here by properly using variation in xII we are able to create such a mapping even though there can be multiple preference types.26 Probability distortions are featured also in, for example, prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky Citation1979; Tversky and Kahneman Citation1992), rank-dependent expected utility theory (Quiggin Citation1982), Gul (Citation1991) disappointment aversion theory, and Kőszegi and Rabin (Citation2006, Citation2007) reference-dependent utility theory.27 Vuong tests comparing the various models confirm the good fit of our preferred specification.28 Except when both degenerate into net present value calculations with νi=0 and ωi=1.29 Independence results from the assumption that claims follow a Poisson distribution, which is imposed in estimating the probability of a claim (see Barseghyan et al. Citation2013; Barseghyan, Teitelbaum, and Xu Citation2018).30 Inspection of (A.2)–(A.4) in the Appendix shows that under Assumption 4.4, f(·) and g(·) are identified, provided the intervals [ν*,ν**] and [ω*,ω**] in Assumption 3.4 are not singletons.31 Alternatively, we could assume that if the realized consideration set is empty, agents choose one of the alternatives in D uniformly at random. Our estimation results are robust to this modeling assumption.32 As explained in Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b), the dataset is an updated version of the one used in Barseghyan et al. (Citation2013). It contains information for an additional year of data and puts stricter restrictions on the timing of purchases across different lines. These restrictions are meant to minimize potential biases stemming from nonactive choices, such as policy renewals, and temporal changes in socioeconomic conditions.33 An analogous fact can be established even if an iid, type-specific, noise term were added to the utility function in (4.3) at the coverage level or, more broadly, for any model that abides a notion of generalized dominance formally defined in Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b).34 We use subsampling because the parameter vector is on the boundary of the parameter space.35 Given the choice patterns in the data discussed in Section 4.3, this is not surprising, as MLE sets the consideration probability of never-chosen bundles to zero.36 Recall that we assume that ($1000,$1000) is considered with probability one.37 Under full consideration, the likelihood of observing nonzero shares of never-the-first-best alternatives is zero. Due to this, in estimation we set the consideration probability of each bundle to 0.99 instead of 1.00.38 These results are sensitive to the choice of the simple lottery to benchmark willingness to pay. Changing the stakes will induce a nonlinear response by the EU types but a linear one by the DT types. Changing the loss probability will induce a nonlinear response by the DT types but a linear one by the EU types.39 The narrow consideration model implies a rank correlation of 0.42 while in the data and under the broad consideration model this coefficient equals 0.61 and 0.62, respectively. In comparison, in the Mixed Logit model with full consideration this correlation is 0.45, while with lower triangular consideration it is 0.65.40 See, for example, the model with imperfect information in (Gualdani and Sinha Citation2023, Example 2).41 As we allow for multiple preference types, our analysis extends that of Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b) even in the simplified framework where consideration is independent across contexts.42 Many important papers in the theory literature—including papers on revealed preference analysis under limited attention, limited consideration, rational inattention, and other forms of bounded rationality that manifest in unobserved heterogeneity in consideration sets—also grapple with the identification problem (e.g., Masatlioglu, Nakajima, and Ozbay Citation2012; Manzini and Mariotti Citation2014; Caplin and Dean Citation2015; Lleras et al. Citation2017; Cattaneo et al. Citation2020). However, these papers generally assume rich datasets—for example, observed choices from every possible subset of the feasible set—that often are not available in applied work, especially outside of the laboratory.43 Examples for the first approach include De los Santos, Hortaçsu, and Wildenbeest (Citation2012), Conlon and Mortimer (Citation2013), Honka, Hortaçsu, and Vitorino (Citation2017), Honka and Chintagunta (Citation2017); for the second, Goeree (Citation2008), van Nierop et al. (Citation2010), Gaynor, Propper, and Seiler (Citation2016); Heiss et al. (Citation2021). Recent examples for the third approach include Abaluck and Adams (Citation2020), Crawford, Griffith, and Iaria (Citation2021), Lu (Citation2022).44 These derivations are based on repeated use of facts such asO1({I1,1,I2,2};∅)=O1({I1,1,I2,2,I2,1};∅)+O1({I1,1,I2,2};{I2,1})=O1({I1,1,I2,2,I1,2};∅)+O1({I1,1,I2,2};{I1,2})Additional informationFundingFinancial support from NSF grants SES-1824448 and SES-2149374 is gratefully acknowledged.","PeriodicalId":2,"journal":{"name":"ACS Applied Bio Materials","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":4.6000,"publicationDate":"2023-09-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"4","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Risk Preference Types, Limited Consideration, and Welfare\",\"authors\":\"Levon Barseghyan, Francesca Molinari\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/07350015.2023.2239949\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"AbstractWe provide sufficient conditions for semi-nonparametric point identification of a mixture model of decision making under risk, when agents make choices in multiple lines of insurance coverage (contexts) by purchasing a bundle. As a first departure from the related literature, the model allows for two preference types. In the first one, agents behave according to standard expected utility theory with CARA Bernoulli utility function, with an agent-specific coefficient of absolute risk aversion whose distribution is left completely unspecified. In the other, agents behave according to the dual theory of choice under risk combined with a one-parameter family distortion function, where the parameter is agent-specific and is drawn from a distribution that is left completely unspecified. Within each preference type, the model allows for unobserved heterogeneity in consideration sets, where the latter form at the bundle level—a second departure from the related literature. Our point identification result rests on observing sufficient variation in covariates across contexts, without requiring any independent variation across alternatives within a single context. We estimate the model on data on households’ deductible choices in two lines of property insurance, and use the results to assess the welfare implications of a hypothetical market intervention where the two lines of insurance are combined into a single one. We study the role of limited consideration in mediating the welfare effects of such intervention.KEYWORDS: (Non-)expected utilityRisk preferencesSemi-nonparametric identificationUnobserved consideration sets AcknowledgmentsWe thank the editor, Ivan Canay, two anonymous reviewers, Matias Cattaneo, Cristina Gualdani, Elisabeth Honka, Xinwei Ma, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Julie Mortimer, Deborah Doukas, Roberta Olivieri, and conference participants at FUR22 and at the JBES session at the ESWM23 for helpful comments.Disclosure StatementThe authors report there are no competing interests to declare.Notes1 This assumption is sometimes viewed as an aspect of rationality (e.g., Kahneman Citation2003), and is credible in our empirical study of demand in very similar contexts (collision and comprehensive deductible insurance).2 Within a single insurance company, typically in a given context if an agent faces a larger price than another agent for one alternative, the first agent faces a (proportionally) larger price for all other alternatives.3 See Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b) for a formal discussion and Section 4.3 for further details.4 See Section 4.2 for additional information on the data.5 The multiplicative factors {glj:l∈Dj} are known as the deductible factors and δj is a small markup known as the expense fee.6 Multiple preference types are a focus of the literature that estimates risk preferences using experimental data (e.g., Bruhin, Fehr-Duda, and Epper Citation2010; Harrison, Humphrey, and Verschoor Citation2010; Conte, Hey, and Moffatt Citation2011), although preferences are homogeneous within each type, at most conditioning on some observed demographic characteristics.7 Other preferences that are characterized by a scalar parameter include ones exhibiting constant relative risk aversion (CRRA), or negligible third derivative (NTD; see, e.g., Cohen and Einav Citation2007; Barseghyan et al. Citation2013). Under CRRA, it is required that agents’ initial wealth is known to the researcher.8 Recall that our analysis conditions on μij, hence, the distribution of preferences may depend on it.9 All papers that estimate risk preferences in the field as reviewed in Barseghyan et al. (Citation2018) impose it.10 The SCP is satisfied in many contexts, ranging from single agent models with goods that can be unambiguously ordered based on quality, to multiple agents models (e.g., Athey Citation2001).11 We assume that while ν and ω have bounded support, the utility functions in U1 and U0 are well defined for any real valued ν and ω, respectively.12 For a discussion of possible failures of SCP, see Apesteguia and Ballester (Citation2018).13 Recall that our analysis conditions on μij, hence, the distribution of consideration sets may depend on it.14 For example, a $500 deductible at price xI in collision insurance and a $500 deductible at price xII in comprehensive insurance would enter the consideration set independently.15 The results extend easily to more than two contexts, at the cost of heavier notation.16 See Figure 3.1 and its discussion below.17 In our empirical model described in Section 4, this intersection point corresponds to ν = 0 and ω = 1, that is, respectively, no risk aversion and no probability distortions.18 Recall that these assumptions, jointly, imply that any agent who draws ν<V2,11,1(xI′)<V1,21,1(xII′) unambiguously prefers alternative l1I to all other alternatives in DI, unambiguously prefers alternative l1II to all other alternatives in DII, and therefore unambiguously prefers bundle I1,1 to any other bundle in D.19 Equivalently, bundle Il,q is chosen if and only if it is the first best among the ones considered:Pr(I*=Il,q|x)=α∑Il,q∈KQ1(K)∫1(CEν(Ik,r,x)≤CEν(Il,q,x) ∀Ik,r∈K|x;ν)dF+(1−α)∑Il,q∈KQ0(K)∫1(CEω(Ik,r,x)≤CEω(Il,q,x) ∀Ik,r∈K|x;ω)dG.20 For ∂Pr(I*=I1,1|x)∂xII, the right-hand side of (3.9) remains as is, with ∂xII replacing ∂xI.21 Alternatively, O1({I1,1,I1,2};∅)=O1({I1,1,I1,2};{I2,2,I2,1}) can replace the last condition in Assumption 3.5-(II). In our application this alternative restriction is satisfied because bundle I1,2 (which is the deductible bundle {$1000,$500} ) is chosen with probability zero, and hence both probabilities are zero.22 These conditions are available from the authors upon request, and require that ∂V1,21,1(x)/∂xII does not equal a specific linear function of ∂V2,11,1(x)/∂xI.23 If one had variation in xj across alternatives and unbounded support, letting the observed covariate (say, price) for a given alternative go to infinity would be akin to assuming that one observes agents repeated choices in context j while facing feasible sets that include/exclude each single alternative.24 For example, if for type ti = 1 alternative Il,k dominates alternative Iq,r, Q1({Il,k,Iq,r}) cannot be separately identified from Q1({Il,k}).25 For example, Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b) require that whenever l1I is considered, l2I is also considered. They do so because there is not a one-to-one mapping between ∂Pr(I*=I1|x)/∂xI and the (up-to-scale) density function evaluated at a single point. Rather, ∂Pr(I*=I1|x)/∂xI maps into a linear combination of the density function evaluated at cutoffs Vk1(xI),k>1. In contrast, here by properly using variation in xII we are able to create such a mapping even though there can be multiple preference types.26 Probability distortions are featured also in, for example, prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky Citation1979; Tversky and Kahneman Citation1992), rank-dependent expected utility theory (Quiggin Citation1982), Gul (Citation1991) disappointment aversion theory, and Kőszegi and Rabin (Citation2006, Citation2007) reference-dependent utility theory.27 Vuong tests comparing the various models confirm the good fit of our preferred specification.28 Except when both degenerate into net present value calculations with νi=0 and ωi=1.29 Independence results from the assumption that claims follow a Poisson distribution, which is imposed in estimating the probability of a claim (see Barseghyan et al. Citation2013; Barseghyan, Teitelbaum, and Xu Citation2018).30 Inspection of (A.2)–(A.4) in the Appendix shows that under Assumption 4.4, f(·) and g(·) are identified, provided the intervals [ν*,ν**] and [ω*,ω**] in Assumption 3.4 are not singletons.31 Alternatively, we could assume that if the realized consideration set is empty, agents choose one of the alternatives in D uniformly at random. Our estimation results are robust to this modeling assumption.32 As explained in Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b), the dataset is an updated version of the one used in Barseghyan et al. (Citation2013). It contains information for an additional year of data and puts stricter restrictions on the timing of purchases across different lines. These restrictions are meant to minimize potential biases stemming from nonactive choices, such as policy renewals, and temporal changes in socioeconomic conditions.33 An analogous fact can be established even if an iid, type-specific, noise term were added to the utility function in (4.3) at the coverage level or, more broadly, for any model that abides a notion of generalized dominance formally defined in Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b).34 We use subsampling because the parameter vector is on the boundary of the parameter space.35 Given the choice patterns in the data discussed in Section 4.3, this is not surprising, as MLE sets the consideration probability of never-chosen bundles to zero.36 Recall that we assume that ($1000,$1000) is considered with probability one.37 Under full consideration, the likelihood of observing nonzero shares of never-the-first-best alternatives is zero. Due to this, in estimation we set the consideration probability of each bundle to 0.99 instead of 1.00.38 These results are sensitive to the choice of the simple lottery to benchmark willingness to pay. Changing the stakes will induce a nonlinear response by the EU types but a linear one by the DT types. Changing the loss probability will induce a nonlinear response by the DT types but a linear one by the EU types.39 The narrow consideration model implies a rank correlation of 0.42 while in the data and under the broad consideration model this coefficient equals 0.61 and 0.62, respectively. In comparison, in the Mixed Logit model with full consideration this correlation is 0.45, while with lower triangular consideration it is 0.65.40 See, for example, the model with imperfect information in (Gualdani and Sinha Citation2023, Example 2).41 As we allow for multiple preference types, our analysis extends that of Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b) even in the simplified framework where consideration is independent across contexts.42 Many important papers in the theory literature—including papers on revealed preference analysis under limited attention, limited consideration, rational inattention, and other forms of bounded rationality that manifest in unobserved heterogeneity in consideration sets—also grapple with the identification problem (e.g., Masatlioglu, Nakajima, and Ozbay Citation2012; Manzini and Mariotti Citation2014; Caplin and Dean Citation2015; Lleras et al. Citation2017; Cattaneo et al. Citation2020). However, these papers generally assume rich datasets—for example, observed choices from every possible subset of the feasible set—that often are not available in applied work, especially outside of the laboratory.43 Examples for the first approach include De los Santos, Hortaçsu, and Wildenbeest (Citation2012), Conlon and Mortimer (Citation2013), Honka, Hortaçsu, and Vitorino (Citation2017), Honka and Chintagunta (Citation2017); for the second, Goeree (Citation2008), van Nierop et al. (Citation2010), Gaynor, Propper, and Seiler (Citation2016); Heiss et al. (Citation2021). Recent examples for the third approach include Abaluck and Adams (Citation2020), Crawford, Griffith, and Iaria (Citation2021), Lu (Citation2022).44 These derivations are based on repeated use of facts such asO1({I1,1,I2,2};∅)=O1({I1,1,I2,2,I2,1};∅)+O1({I1,1,I2,2};{I2,1})=O1({I1,1,I2,2,I1,2};∅)+O1({I1,1,I2,2};{I1,2})Additional informationFundingFinancial support from NSF grants SES-1824448 and SES-2149374 is gratefully acknowledged.\",\"PeriodicalId\":2,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"ACS Applied Bio Materials\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":4.6000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-09-18\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"4\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"ACS Applied Bio Materials\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/07350015.2023.2239949\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q2\",\"JCRName\":\"MATERIALS SCIENCE, BIOMATERIALS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"ACS Applied Bio Materials","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/07350015.2023.2239949","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"MATERIALS SCIENCE, BIOMATERIALS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
摘要
摘要我们提供了风险下决策混合模型的半非参数点识别的充分条件,当代理人通过购买捆绑包在多个保险范围(上下文)中进行选择时。作为与相关文献的第一个区别,该模型允许两种偏好类型。在第一种模型中,agent的行为遵循标准期望效用理论,具有CARA Bernoulli效用函数,具有特定于agent的绝对风险厌恶系数,其分布完全不确定。在另一种情况下,智能体根据风险下的二元选择理论和单参数族扭曲函数进行行为,其中参数是特定于智能体的,并且是从完全未指定的分布中提取的。在每种偏好类型中,该模型允许考虑集中存在未观察到的异质性,后者在bundle级别形成——这是与相关文献的第二个不同之处。我们的点识别结果依赖于观察跨上下文的协变量的足够变化,而不需要在单个上下文中跨备选项的任何独立变化。我们根据家庭在两种财产保险中免赔额选择的数据估计模型,并使用结果来评估假设的市场干预对福利的影响,其中两种保险合并为一种。我们研究了有限考虑在调解这种干预的福利效应中的作用。我们感谢编辑Ivan Canay、两位匿名审稿人Matias Cattaneo、Cristina Gualdani、Elisabeth Honka、Xinwei Ma、Yusufcan Masatlioglu、Julie Mortimer、Deborah Doukas、Roberta Olivieri以及FUR22和ESWM23 JBES会议的与会者提供的宝贵意见。声明作者报告无竞争利益需要申报。注1:这一假设有时被视为理性的一个方面(例如,Kahneman Citation2003),并且在我们对非常相似背景(碰撞和全面免赔保险)的需求的实证研究中是可信的在单个保险公司中,通常在给定的环境中,如果一个代理人在一个选择上面临比另一个代理人更高的价格,那么第一个代理人在所有其他选择上面临(按比例)更高的价格参见Barseghyan, Molinari和Thirkettle (Citation2021b)的正式讨论和4.3节的进一步细节有关数据的更多信息,请参见4.2节乘法因子{glj:l∈Dj}被称为免赔因子,δj是一个小的加价,被称为费用费用多重偏好类型是使用实验数据估计风险偏好的文献的焦点(例如,Bruhin, Fehr-Duda和Epper Citation2010;Harrison, Humphrey, and Verschoor citation; 2010;Conte, Hey, and Moffatt Citation2011),尽管每种类型的偏好都是同质的,但最多是受一些观察到的人口特征的影响其他以标量参数为特征的偏好包括表现出恒定相对风险厌恶(CRRA)或可忽略的三阶导数(NTD;参见,例如,Cohen和Einav Citation2007;Barseghyan等人。Citation2013)。根据CRRA,代理人的初始财富必须为研究人员所知回想一下,我们的分析条件是μij,因此,偏好的分布可能取决于它Barseghyan等人(Citation2018)审查的所有估计该领域风险偏好的论文都强加了它SCP在许多情况下都是可以满足的,从具有商品的单代理模型(可以根据质量明确订购)到多代理模型(例如,Athey Citation2001)我们假设,当ν和ω具有有界支持时,U1和U0中的效用函数分别对任何实值ν和ω都是定义好的关于SCP可能失败的讨论,请参见Apesteguia和Ballester (Citation2018)回想一下,我们的分析条件是μij,因此,考虑集的分布可能依赖于它结果很容易扩展到两种以上的上下文中,但代价是更沉重的符号参见图3.1及其下面的讨论在我们第4节描述的经验模型中,这个交点对应于ν = 0和ω = 1,即分别没有风险规避和概率扭曲回想一下,这些假设合在一起,意味着任何抽到ν1的代理。相比之下,在这里,通过适当地使用xII中的变化,我们能够创建这样的映射,即使可以有多个首选项类型。 26概率扭曲也有特点,例如,前景理论(卡尼曼和特沃斯基引文,1979;27 . Tversky and Kahneman Citation1992), Quiggin Citation1982), Gul (Citation1991)失望厌恶理论,Kőszegi and Rabin (Citation2006, Citation2007)参考依赖效用理论比较各种模型的Vuong试验证实了我们的首选规格的良好拟合除非两者都退化为νi=0和ωi=1.29的净现值计算,否则独立性源于索赔遵循泊松分布的假设,这是在估计索赔概率时强加的(见Barseghyan等人)。Citation2013;Barseghyan, Teitelbaum, and Xu Citation2018).30对附录(A.2) - (A.4)的检验表明,在假设4.4下,假设3.4中的区间[ν*,ν**]和[ω*,ω**]不是单例,则f(·)和g(·)是可识别的或者,我们可以假设,如果实现的考虑集是空的,代理均匀随机地选择D中的一个选项。我们的估计结果对这个建模假设是稳健的正如Barseghyan、Molinari和Thirkettle (Citation2021b)所解释的那样,该数据集是Barseghyan等人(Citation2013)使用的数据集的更新版本。它包含了额外一年的数据信息,并对不同行业的购买时间进行了更严格的限制。这些限制是为了尽量减少由非主动选择引起的潜在偏差,如政策更新和社会经济条件的时间变化类似的事实可以建立,即使在覆盖水平(4.3)的效用函数中添加一个特定类型的噪声项,或者更广泛地说,对于任何遵循Barseghyan, Molinari和Thirkettle (Citation2021b)中正式定义的广义优势概念的模型我们使用子采样是因为参数向量在参数空间的边界上考虑到第4.3节中讨论的数据中的选择模式,这并不奇怪,因为MLE将从未选择的束的考虑概率设置为零回想一下,我们假设($1000,$1000)被考虑的概率是1在充分考虑的情况下,观察到非最佳选择的非零股票的可能性为零。因此,在估计中,我们将每个捆绑包的考虑概率设置为0.99而不是1.00.38。这些结果对选择简单的摇号来衡量支付意愿很敏感。改变赌注将引起欧盟类型的非线性响应,而DT类型的线性响应。39 .改变损失概率会引起DT型的非线性响应,而EU型的线性响应狭义考虑模型的秩相关系数为0.42,而在数据和广义考虑模型下,该系数分别为0.61和0.62。相比之下,在充分考虑的混合Logit模型中,这一相关性为0.45,而在低三角考虑下,这一相关性为0.65.40,参见(Gualdani and Sinha Citation2023, example 2) 41中具有不完全信息的模型由于我们允许多种偏好类型,我们的分析扩展了Barseghyan, Molinari和Thirkettle (Citation2021b)的分析,甚至在考虑跨上下文独立的简化框架中也是如此理论文献中的许多重要论文——包括关于有限注意、有限考虑、理性不注意和其他形式的有限理性下的揭示偏好分析的论文,这些论文在考虑集中表现为未观察到的异质性——也在努力解决识别问题(例如,Masatlioglu、Nakajima和Ozbay Citation2012;Manzini and Mariotti citation; 2014;Caplin and Dean Citation2015;勒勒斯等人。Citation2017;cataneo等人。Citation2020)。然而,这些论文通常假设了丰富的数据集——例如,从可行集的每个可能子集中观察到的选择——这些数据集在应用工作中通常是不可用的,特别是在实验室之外第一种方法的例子包括De los Santos、hortasu和Wildenbeest (Citation2012)、Conlon和Mortimer (Citation2013)、Honka、hortasu和Vitorino (Citation2017)、Honka和Chintagunta (Citation2017);第二,Goeree (Citation2008), van Nierop等人(Citation2010), Gaynor, Propper, and Seiler (Citation2016);Heiss等人(Citation2021)。第三种方法最近的例子包括Abaluck和Adams (Citation2020), Crawford, Griffith和Iaria (Citation2021), Lu (Citation2022)这些推导基于以下事实的重复使用:O1({i1,1,i2,2};∅)=O1({i1,1,i2,2, i2,1};∅)+O1({i1,1, i2,2};{i2,1})=O1({i1,1,1, i2,2, i1,2};∅)+O1({i1,1, i2,2};{i1,2})附加信息感谢NSF拨款SES-1824448和SES-2149374的财政支持。
Risk Preference Types, Limited Consideration, and Welfare
AbstractWe provide sufficient conditions for semi-nonparametric point identification of a mixture model of decision making under risk, when agents make choices in multiple lines of insurance coverage (contexts) by purchasing a bundle. As a first departure from the related literature, the model allows for two preference types. In the first one, agents behave according to standard expected utility theory with CARA Bernoulli utility function, with an agent-specific coefficient of absolute risk aversion whose distribution is left completely unspecified. In the other, agents behave according to the dual theory of choice under risk combined with a one-parameter family distortion function, where the parameter is agent-specific and is drawn from a distribution that is left completely unspecified. Within each preference type, the model allows for unobserved heterogeneity in consideration sets, where the latter form at the bundle level—a second departure from the related literature. Our point identification result rests on observing sufficient variation in covariates across contexts, without requiring any independent variation across alternatives within a single context. We estimate the model on data on households’ deductible choices in two lines of property insurance, and use the results to assess the welfare implications of a hypothetical market intervention where the two lines of insurance are combined into a single one. We study the role of limited consideration in mediating the welfare effects of such intervention.KEYWORDS: (Non-)expected utilityRisk preferencesSemi-nonparametric identificationUnobserved consideration sets AcknowledgmentsWe thank the editor, Ivan Canay, two anonymous reviewers, Matias Cattaneo, Cristina Gualdani, Elisabeth Honka, Xinwei Ma, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Julie Mortimer, Deborah Doukas, Roberta Olivieri, and conference participants at FUR22 and at the JBES session at the ESWM23 for helpful comments.Disclosure StatementThe authors report there are no competing interests to declare.Notes1 This assumption is sometimes viewed as an aspect of rationality (e.g., Kahneman Citation2003), and is credible in our empirical study of demand in very similar contexts (collision and comprehensive deductible insurance).2 Within a single insurance company, typically in a given context if an agent faces a larger price than another agent for one alternative, the first agent faces a (proportionally) larger price for all other alternatives.3 See Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b) for a formal discussion and Section 4.3 for further details.4 See Section 4.2 for additional information on the data.5 The multiplicative factors {glj:l∈Dj} are known as the deductible factors and δj is a small markup known as the expense fee.6 Multiple preference types are a focus of the literature that estimates risk preferences using experimental data (e.g., Bruhin, Fehr-Duda, and Epper Citation2010; Harrison, Humphrey, and Verschoor Citation2010; Conte, Hey, and Moffatt Citation2011), although preferences are homogeneous within each type, at most conditioning on some observed demographic characteristics.7 Other preferences that are characterized by a scalar parameter include ones exhibiting constant relative risk aversion (CRRA), or negligible third derivative (NTD; see, e.g., Cohen and Einav Citation2007; Barseghyan et al. Citation2013). Under CRRA, it is required that agents’ initial wealth is known to the researcher.8 Recall that our analysis conditions on μij, hence, the distribution of preferences may depend on it.9 All papers that estimate risk preferences in the field as reviewed in Barseghyan et al. (Citation2018) impose it.10 The SCP is satisfied in many contexts, ranging from single agent models with goods that can be unambiguously ordered based on quality, to multiple agents models (e.g., Athey Citation2001).11 We assume that while ν and ω have bounded support, the utility functions in U1 and U0 are well defined for any real valued ν and ω, respectively.12 For a discussion of possible failures of SCP, see Apesteguia and Ballester (Citation2018).13 Recall that our analysis conditions on μij, hence, the distribution of consideration sets may depend on it.14 For example, a $500 deductible at price xI in collision insurance and a $500 deductible at price xII in comprehensive insurance would enter the consideration set independently.15 The results extend easily to more than two contexts, at the cost of heavier notation.16 See Figure 3.1 and its discussion below.17 In our empirical model described in Section 4, this intersection point corresponds to ν = 0 and ω = 1, that is, respectively, no risk aversion and no probability distortions.18 Recall that these assumptions, jointly, imply that any agent who draws ν1. In contrast, here by properly using variation in xII we are able to create such a mapping even though there can be multiple preference types.26 Probability distortions are featured also in, for example, prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky Citation1979; Tversky and Kahneman Citation1992), rank-dependent expected utility theory (Quiggin Citation1982), Gul (Citation1991) disappointment aversion theory, and Kőszegi and Rabin (Citation2006, Citation2007) reference-dependent utility theory.27 Vuong tests comparing the various models confirm the good fit of our preferred specification.28 Except when both degenerate into net present value calculations with νi=0 and ωi=1.29 Independence results from the assumption that claims follow a Poisson distribution, which is imposed in estimating the probability of a claim (see Barseghyan et al. Citation2013; Barseghyan, Teitelbaum, and Xu Citation2018).30 Inspection of (A.2)–(A.4) in the Appendix shows that under Assumption 4.4, f(·) and g(·) are identified, provided the intervals [ν*,ν**] and [ω*,ω**] in Assumption 3.4 are not singletons.31 Alternatively, we could assume that if the realized consideration set is empty, agents choose one of the alternatives in D uniformly at random. Our estimation results are robust to this modeling assumption.32 As explained in Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b), the dataset is an updated version of the one used in Barseghyan et al. (Citation2013). It contains information for an additional year of data and puts stricter restrictions on the timing of purchases across different lines. These restrictions are meant to minimize potential biases stemming from nonactive choices, such as policy renewals, and temporal changes in socioeconomic conditions.33 An analogous fact can be established even if an iid, type-specific, noise term were added to the utility function in (4.3) at the coverage level or, more broadly, for any model that abides a notion of generalized dominance formally defined in Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b).34 We use subsampling because the parameter vector is on the boundary of the parameter space.35 Given the choice patterns in the data discussed in Section 4.3, this is not surprising, as MLE sets the consideration probability of never-chosen bundles to zero.36 Recall that we assume that ($1000,$1000) is considered with probability one.37 Under full consideration, the likelihood of observing nonzero shares of never-the-first-best alternatives is zero. Due to this, in estimation we set the consideration probability of each bundle to 0.99 instead of 1.00.38 These results are sensitive to the choice of the simple lottery to benchmark willingness to pay. Changing the stakes will induce a nonlinear response by the EU types but a linear one by the DT types. Changing the loss probability will induce a nonlinear response by the DT types but a linear one by the EU types.39 The narrow consideration model implies a rank correlation of 0.42 while in the data and under the broad consideration model this coefficient equals 0.61 and 0.62, respectively. In comparison, in the Mixed Logit model with full consideration this correlation is 0.45, while with lower triangular consideration it is 0.65.40 See, for example, the model with imperfect information in (Gualdani and Sinha Citation2023, Example 2).41 As we allow for multiple preference types, our analysis extends that of Barseghyan, Molinari, and Thirkettle (Citation2021b) even in the simplified framework where consideration is independent across contexts.42 Many important papers in the theory literature—including papers on revealed preference analysis under limited attention, limited consideration, rational inattention, and other forms of bounded rationality that manifest in unobserved heterogeneity in consideration sets—also grapple with the identification problem (e.g., Masatlioglu, Nakajima, and Ozbay Citation2012; Manzini and Mariotti Citation2014; Caplin and Dean Citation2015; Lleras et al. Citation2017; Cattaneo et al. Citation2020). However, these papers generally assume rich datasets—for example, observed choices from every possible subset of the feasible set—that often are not available in applied work, especially outside of the laboratory.43 Examples for the first approach include De los Santos, Hortaçsu, and Wildenbeest (Citation2012), Conlon and Mortimer (Citation2013), Honka, Hortaçsu, and Vitorino (Citation2017), Honka and Chintagunta (Citation2017); for the second, Goeree (Citation2008), van Nierop et al. (Citation2010), Gaynor, Propper, and Seiler (Citation2016); Heiss et al. (Citation2021). Recent examples for the third approach include Abaluck and Adams (Citation2020), Crawford, Griffith, and Iaria (Citation2021), Lu (Citation2022).44 These derivations are based on repeated use of facts such asO1({I1,1,I2,2};∅)=O1({I1,1,I2,2,I2,1};∅)+O1({I1,1,I2,2};{I2,1})=O1({I1,1,I2,2,I1,2};∅)+O1({I1,1,I2,2};{I1,2})Additional informationFundingFinancial support from NSF grants SES-1824448 and SES-2149374 is gratefully acknowledged.