{"title":"认知分歧、多样性与相对主义","authors":"J. Carter","doi":"10.4324/9781315717937-15","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Diversity abounds, and typically, disagreement is not far behind. Unsurprisingly, when initial starting points are far enough apart (take for example, the famous 17th century dispute between Galileo and Cardinal Bellarmine) the ensuing disagreements can appear rationally irreconcilable. Some philosophers such as Richard Rorty (1979) have taken the presence of such disagreements as evidence for epistemic relativism. The present aim will be to canvass this general argument strategy, which moves from diversity to disagreement to epistemic relativism. In the course of doing so, objections will be raised to various forms that this argument has taken, and, finally, I’ll contrast traditional forms of the diversity-disagreement-relativism sequence with a more contemporary, linguistically driven variant that has been defended in recent work by John MacFarlane (e.g., 2007; 2014). 1. From diversity to disagreement to relativism: ethics and epistemology Diversity often gives rise to disagreement. Consider a straightforward non-epistemic example, described byHerodotus in theHistories, concerning funerary customs1. The custom of the ancient Greeks was always to bury their dead; eating them would have been appalling. The Callatians on the other hand honoured the dead by eating them; burying themwould have been out of the question. AsHerodotus noted, each thought the other custom was not merely different, but obviously wrong. Their differing funerary codes accordingly led to a disagreement, overseen by King Darius of Persia, about the right way to honour the dead. And it’s unclear what, if anything, could have settled such a disagreement. Perhaps, in such circumstances, mutual tolerance is the way forward. Here’s a slogan that is often trotted out: burying the dead is right for the Greeks, eating them is right for Callatians. And there’s no ‘culture-independent’ sense in which either is 1This example, reported in the Histories (c. 440 BCE), is often used to introduce the idea of moral relativism. See, for example, Rachels (2003, Ch. 2), who takes this case as a starting point for discussion in the widely used textbook The Elements of Moral Philosophy.","PeriodicalId":438715,"journal":{"name":"The Routledge Handbook of Social Epistemology","volume":"100 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-07-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"4","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Epistemic Disagreement, Diversity and Relativism\",\"authors\":\"J. Carter\",\"doi\":\"10.4324/9781315717937-15\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Diversity abounds, and typically, disagreement is not far behind. Unsurprisingly, when initial starting points are far enough apart (take for example, the famous 17th century dispute between Galileo and Cardinal Bellarmine) the ensuing disagreements can appear rationally irreconcilable. Some philosophers such as Richard Rorty (1979) have taken the presence of such disagreements as evidence for epistemic relativism. The present aim will be to canvass this general argument strategy, which moves from diversity to disagreement to epistemic relativism. In the course of doing so, objections will be raised to various forms that this argument has taken, and, finally, I’ll contrast traditional forms of the diversity-disagreement-relativism sequence with a more contemporary, linguistically driven variant that has been defended in recent work by John MacFarlane (e.g., 2007; 2014). 1. From diversity to disagreement to relativism: ethics and epistemology Diversity often gives rise to disagreement. Consider a straightforward non-epistemic example, described byHerodotus in theHistories, concerning funerary customs1. The custom of the ancient Greeks was always to bury their dead; eating them would have been appalling. The Callatians on the other hand honoured the dead by eating them; burying themwould have been out of the question. AsHerodotus noted, each thought the other custom was not merely different, but obviously wrong. Their differing funerary codes accordingly led to a disagreement, overseen by King Darius of Persia, about the right way to honour the dead. And it’s unclear what, if anything, could have settled such a disagreement. Perhaps, in such circumstances, mutual tolerance is the way forward. Here’s a slogan that is often trotted out: burying the dead is right for the Greeks, eating them is right for Callatians. And there’s no ‘culture-independent’ sense in which either is 1This example, reported in the Histories (c. 440 BCE), is often used to introduce the idea of moral relativism. See, for example, Rachels (2003, Ch. 2), who takes this case as a starting point for discussion in the widely used textbook The Elements of Moral Philosophy.\",\"PeriodicalId\":438715,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"The Routledge Handbook of Social Epistemology\",\"volume\":\"100 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2019-07-19\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"4\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"The Routledge Handbook of Social Epistemology\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315717937-15\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The Routledge Handbook of Social Epistemology","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315717937-15","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
摘要
多样性是丰富的,通常,分歧也不甘落后。不出所料,当最初的出发点相距甚远时(例如,17世纪伽利略和红衣主教贝拉明之间著名的争论),随后的分歧在理性上似乎是不可调和的。一些哲学家,如理查德·罗蒂(Richard Rorty, 1979),将这种分歧的存在作为认识论相对主义的证据。目前的目的是探讨这种从多样性到分歧再到认识论相对主义的一般论证策略。在此过程中,对这一论点所采取的各种形式将提出反对意见,最后,我将把多样性-分歧-相对主义序列的传统形式与约翰·麦克法兰(John MacFarlane)最近的作品中捍卫的更现代、语言驱动的变体进行对比(例如,2007;2014)。1. 从多样性到分歧再到相对主义:伦理学与认识论多样性往往引起分歧。考虑一个简单的非认识论的例子,由希罗多德在《历史》中描述,关于丧葬习俗。古希腊人的习俗总是埋葬他们的死者;吃了它们会很可怕。另一方面,卡拉蒂亚人以吃死人来纪念他们;埋葬他们是不可能的。正如希罗多德所指出的,双方都认为对方的习俗不仅不同,而且显然是错误的。在波斯国王大流士(King Darius of Persia)的监督下,他们不同的丧葬规范导致了对死者的正确方式的分歧。目前还不清楚是什么(如果有的话)解决了这样的分歧。也许,在这种情况下,相互容忍才是前进的方向。这是一个经常被提起的口号:埋葬死者是希腊人的权利,吃他们是卡拉蒂亚人的权利。而且也没有“文化独立”的意义。这个例子记载在《历史》(公元前440年)中,经常被用来介绍道德相对主义的概念。例如,请看rachel(2003,第2章),她在广泛使用的教科书《道德哲学的要素》中把这个案例作为讨论的起点。
Diversity abounds, and typically, disagreement is not far behind. Unsurprisingly, when initial starting points are far enough apart (take for example, the famous 17th century dispute between Galileo and Cardinal Bellarmine) the ensuing disagreements can appear rationally irreconcilable. Some philosophers such as Richard Rorty (1979) have taken the presence of such disagreements as evidence for epistemic relativism. The present aim will be to canvass this general argument strategy, which moves from diversity to disagreement to epistemic relativism. In the course of doing so, objections will be raised to various forms that this argument has taken, and, finally, I’ll contrast traditional forms of the diversity-disagreement-relativism sequence with a more contemporary, linguistically driven variant that has been defended in recent work by John MacFarlane (e.g., 2007; 2014). 1. From diversity to disagreement to relativism: ethics and epistemology Diversity often gives rise to disagreement. Consider a straightforward non-epistemic example, described byHerodotus in theHistories, concerning funerary customs1. The custom of the ancient Greeks was always to bury their dead; eating them would have been appalling. The Callatians on the other hand honoured the dead by eating them; burying themwould have been out of the question. AsHerodotus noted, each thought the other custom was not merely different, but obviously wrong. Their differing funerary codes accordingly led to a disagreement, overseen by King Darius of Persia, about the right way to honour the dead. And it’s unclear what, if anything, could have settled such a disagreement. Perhaps, in such circumstances, mutual tolerance is the way forward. Here’s a slogan that is often trotted out: burying the dead is right for the Greeks, eating them is right for Callatians. And there’s no ‘culture-independent’ sense in which either is 1This example, reported in the Histories (c. 440 BCE), is often used to introduce the idea of moral relativism. See, for example, Rachels (2003, Ch. 2), who takes this case as a starting point for discussion in the widely used textbook The Elements of Moral Philosophy.