{"title":"Nicholas Rhabdas给哈齐克斯的信的来源:一篇匿名的Vat算术论文。倒钩。gr。4","authors":"F. Acerbi, D. Manolova, Inmaculada Pérez Martín","doi":"10.1553/joeb68s1","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The article presents the edition and a detailed discussion of an anonymous treatise of elementary arithmetic that served as the source of the so-called Letter to Khatzykes authored by the Byzantine scholar Nicholas Artabasdos Rhabdas. An updated survey of the extant evidence about the logistic treatises composed in the Nicaean period and in the early Palaiologan era, and a discussion of the prima facie surprisingly widespread phenomenon of appropriation of scientific treatises written by other contemporaries in late Byzantine times will also be provided. This article presents the edition of an anonymous treatise of elementary arithmetic (henceforth called “Anonymus B”) contained, in slightly incomplete form, in ff. 171r–186v of the manuscript Città del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, Barberinianus gr. 4 (Diktyon 64552), to be dated to the beginning of the 14th century. The most important point of our study, however, does not lie in assessing Anonymus B in its own terms, but in showing that it served as the source of the so-called Letter to Khatzykes1 authored by the Byzantine scholar Nicholas Artabasdos Rhabdas2. That the First Letter and the anonymous treatise are very closely connected is obvious from their verbatim agreeing over large stretches of text; two series of facts decisively support our stronger claim about their filiation. First, the Barberini codex, produced within the circle of Maximos Planudes’ (d. ca. 1305) pupils, dates at the latest to the period of Rhabdas’ early activity. Second—and crucially, on account of the fact that the paleographical record does not completely settle the issue of priority—the involved variant readings, starting from the very titles of the two texts, strongly corroborate the hypothesis that Anonymus B is the source of Rhabdas’ First Letter, and not the inverse. As it also happens that an anonymous arithmetical treatise dated 1252 (henceforth “Anonymus 1252”) underwent a similar treatment in the hands of Planudes himself, resulting in his celebrated Great Calculation According to the Indians, we shall provide a revised outline of the extant evidence about the logistic treatises redacted in the Nicaean period (1204–61) and in the early Palaiologan era; we shall also argue, on grounds of style and contents, that Anonymus B and Anonymus 1252 were not composed by the same author. Consequently, we shall discuss the prima facie surprisingly widespread phenomenon, in late Byzantine times, of appropriation of scientific treatises written by other Byzantine scholars. The structure of the article is as follows. We first survey the evidence about Rhabdas’ scientific career; we then briefly describe Barb. gr. 4. The edition of Anonymus B, including the accompanying tables, is followed by an analysis of the textual differences with respect to Rhabdas’ First Letter, and by an assessment of the flourishing of logistic treatises in the middle of the 13th century. In the last * We are grateful to F. Valerio for a preliminary check of Vat. gr. 1481, to O. Delouis for pointing out a relevant text to us. This manuscript, Barb. gr. 4, and Chis. R.IV.20 have been collated at the Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana on June 6–8 and July 10–12, 2018. FA and IPM have been supported by the Research project “The Byzantine Author (II)” (MICINN, FFI201565118-C2-2-P). DM’s contribution was written as part of the project UMO-2015/19/P/HS2/02739, supported by the National Science Centre, Poland; this project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie grant agreement no. 665778. 1 Henceforth called First Letter. We shall see that there are two “letters” of arithmetical content authored by Rhabdas. 2 Rhabdas was born in Smyrna and was active in Constantinople about 1320–40; see PLP, no. 1437; ODB, 1786–1787; and the discussion in the next section. F. Acerbi – D. Manolova – I. Pérez Martín 2 section, we present factual evidence and some considerations on the issue of “scientific plagiarism” in Palaiologan Byzantium. NICHOLAS RHABDAS, LIFE AND WORKS Enough of Nicholas Rhabdas’ scholarly production has been preserved for us to acknowledge his expertise in the mathematical sciences and especially his significant contribution to the domain of Byzantine logistic3. This is a branch of arithmetic in which a unit can be divided and that deals with counting numbers and with calculations on them4. Logistic developed greatly in Late Antiquity as a support to mathematical astronomy, and retained this role in Byzantine times5. As we shall see, Rhabdas was also engaged in astronomical matters and, in addition, composed a grammatical treatise for his son Paul Artabasdos6. 3 His production, however, was assessed in a way that is paradigmatic of a generalized dismissive attitude to Byzantine science; P. Tannery, Manuel Moschopoulos et Nicolas Rhabdas. Bulletin des Sciences mathématiques, 2e série, 8 (1884) 263–277, repr. Id., Mémoires Scientifiques IV. Toulouse–Paris 1920, 1–19: 15, in fact, passed the following judgment on Rhabdas’ writings, whose edition he nevertheless published two years later: “L’intérêt de ses écrits est surtout de montrer jusqu’où étaient tombés les héritiers dégénérés du nom hellène, ceux-là même qui avaient alors Diophante entre leurs mains”. 4 According to the 6th-century Neoplatonic commentator Eutocius, dividing the unit does not pertain to arithmetic but to logistic (J. L. Heiberg (ed.), Archimedis opera omnia cum commentariis Eutocii. I–III. Lipsiae 1910–15, III 120.28–30: ὥστ’ ἐπ’ ἐκείνων [scil. superparticular and superpartient ratios] διαιρετέον τὴν μονάδα, ὃ εἰ καὶ μὴ κατὰ τὸ προσῆκον τῇ ἀριθμητικῇ ἀλλὰ τῇ λογιστικῇ τυγχάνει “so that, for them one has to divide the unit, even if this does not happen to fit to arithmetic, but to logistic”). An earlier definition of logistic—which can almost certainly be ascribed to Geminus (a 1st-century BCE mathematically-minded philosopher, maybe a pupil of Posidonius)—does not allow dividing the unit. This definition can be found in pseudo-Hero, Def. 135.5–6 (J. L. Heiberg – L. Nix – W. Schmidt – H. Schöne (eds.), Heronis Alexandrini opera quae supersunt omnia. I–V. Lipsiae 1899–1914, IV 98.12–100.3), and is also preserved, through a different line of tradition, as a scholium to Plato, Chrm. 165e6 (Scholium 27 in D. Cufalo, Scholia Graeca in Platonem. I. Scholia ad dialogos tetralogiarum I–VII continens [Pleiadi 5.1]. Roma 2007, 173). It is possible that the domain of logistic was expanded to include fractional parts as a consequence of the adoption of the sexagesimal system in Greek mathematical astronomy. In fact, logistic developed greatly in Late Antiquity as a support to mathematical astronomy, and also played this same role in the Byzantine period. The first known treatise of this kind is included in the Prolegomena to the Almagest, and amounts to the (non-redacted) lecture notes of a course held in the circle of the Neoplatonic philosopher Ammonios. This treatise is a computational primer to the Almagest: a tightly organized “handbook of logistic” featuring as its main themes an introduction to the sexagesimal system, a description of computational algorithms for multiplication, division, and extraction of an approximate square root, a presentation of interpolation techniques, and an exposition about compounded ratios and removal of a ratio from a ratio. According to the anonymous author, no comprehensive previous exposition of this kind existed— and in fact no such one has been transmitted to us. See also note 125 below. The best introduction to Greek logistic is still K. Vogel, Beiträge zur griechischen Logistik. Erster Teil (Sitzungsberichte der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Mathematisch-naturwissenschaftliche Abteilung). Munich 1936, 357–472. 5 Cf. the explicit statement opening Anonymus 1252: A. Allard, Le premier traité byzantin de calcul indien: classement des manuscrits et édition critique du texte. Revue d’Histoire des Textes 7 (1977) 57–107: 80.2–4, and, in a smoother formulation, Planudes’ Great Calculation: A. Allard (ed.), Maxime Planude, Le grand calcul selon les Indiens. Louvain-la-Neuve 1981, 27.1–5. Despite its title (and the author’s statement similar to that of Planudes: P. Carelos [ed.], Βαρλαὰμ τοῦ Καλαβροῦ, Λογιστική, Barlaam von Seminara, Logistiké [Corpus philosophorum Medii Ævi. Philosophi byzantini 8]. Athens–Paris– Brussels 1996: 1.10–26), Barlaam’ Logistic is not a writing of logistic, but a fully-fledged treatise of theoretical arithmetic formulated in an impeccable demonstrative style. Barlaam (PLP, no. 2284), undisputably the Byzantine scholar best versed in mathematical matters and a major actor in the hesychastic controversy, died in 1348. 6 See PLP, no. 1438. The unpublished grammatical synopsis addressed to Paul is preserved in the miscellaneous ms. Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, gr. 2650 (Diktyon 52285), ff. 147r–150v. The copying is dated December 6, a.m. 6836 [= 1427] (f. 204v), certainly referring to ff. 201r–204v and possibly also to ff. 153r–167v and 168v–198v, penned by the same hand. However, the script of Rhabdas’ synopsis (located in quire no. ιθʹ, a ternion closed by the blank ff. 151r–152r) seems earlier, perhaps dating back to the middle – third quarter of the 14th century. The synopsis is presented as a grammatical compendium whose aim is expounding the appropriate use of words, in order to avoid barbarisms and solecisms. The exposition is based on analytical divisions of the main grammatical issues, treated by means of μικρούς τινας ὑπομνηματισμούς “some short notes”. It starts from letters (γράμματα and στοιχεῖα) and goes on dealing with syllables and words insofar as they are 3 The Source of Nicholas Rhabdas’ Letter to Khatzykes Much less is known about Rhabdas’ life, education, personal and professional networks. Until recently, the only temporal clue was provided by the fact that, i","PeriodicalId":194077,"journal":{"name":"Jahrbuch der Österreichischen Byzantinistik","volume":"451 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The Source of Nicholas Rhabdas’ Letter to Khatzykes: An Anonymous Arithmetical Treatise in Vat. Barb. gr. 4\",\"authors\":\"F. Acerbi, D. Manolova, Inmaculada Pérez Martín\",\"doi\":\"10.1553/joeb68s1\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"The article presents the edition and a detailed discussion of an anonymous treatise of elementary arithmetic that served as the source of the so-called Letter to Khatzykes authored by the Byzantine scholar Nicholas Artabasdos Rhabdas. An updated survey of the extant evidence about the logistic treatises composed in the Nicaean period and in the early Palaiologan era, and a discussion of the prima facie surprisingly widespread phenomenon of appropriation of scientific treatises written by other contemporaries in late Byzantine times will also be provided. This article presents the edition of an anonymous treatise of elementary arithmetic (henceforth called “Anonymus B”) contained, in slightly incomplete form, in ff. 171r–186v of the manuscript Città del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, Barberinianus gr. 4 (Diktyon 64552), to be dated to the beginning of the 14th century. The most important point of our study, however, does not lie in assessing Anonymus B in its own terms, but in showing that it served as the source of the so-called Letter to Khatzykes1 authored by the Byzantine scholar Nicholas Artabasdos Rhabdas2. That the First Letter and the anonymous treatise are very closely connected is obvious from their verbatim agreeing over large stretches of text; two series of facts decisively support our stronger claim about their filiation. First, the Barberini codex, produced within the circle of Maximos Planudes’ (d. ca. 1305) pupils, dates at the latest to the period of Rhabdas’ early activity. Second—and crucially, on account of the fact that the paleographical record does not completely settle the issue of priority—the involved variant readings, starting from the very titles of the two texts, strongly corroborate the hypothesis that Anonymus B is the source of Rhabdas’ First Letter, and not the inverse. As it also happens that an anonymous arithmetical treatise dated 1252 (henceforth “Anonymus 1252”) underwent a similar treatment in the hands of Planudes himself, resulting in his celebrated Great Calculation According to the Indians, we shall provide a revised outline of the extant evidence about the logistic treatises redacted in the Nicaean period (1204–61) and in the early Palaiologan era; we shall also argue, on grounds of style and contents, that Anonymus B and Anonymus 1252 were not composed by the same author. Consequently, we shall discuss the prima facie surprisingly widespread phenomenon, in late Byzantine times, of appropriation of scientific treatises written by other Byzantine scholars. The structure of the article is as follows. We first survey the evidence about Rhabdas’ scientific career; we then briefly describe Barb. gr. 4. The edition of Anonymus B, including the accompanying tables, is followed by an analysis of the textual differences with respect to Rhabdas’ First Letter, and by an assessment of the flourishing of logistic treatises in the middle of the 13th century. In the last * We are grateful to F. Valerio for a preliminary check of Vat. gr. 1481, to O. Delouis for pointing out a relevant text to us. This manuscript, Barb. gr. 4, and Chis. R.IV.20 have been collated at the Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana on June 6–8 and July 10–12, 2018. FA and IPM have been supported by the Research project “The Byzantine Author (II)” (MICINN, FFI201565118-C2-2-P). DM’s contribution was written as part of the project UMO-2015/19/P/HS2/02739, supported by the National Science Centre, Poland; this project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie grant agreement no. 665778. 1 Henceforth called First Letter. We shall see that there are two “letters” of arithmetical content authored by Rhabdas. 2 Rhabdas was born in Smyrna and was active in Constantinople about 1320–40; see PLP, no. 1437; ODB, 1786–1787; and the discussion in the next section. F. Acerbi – D. Manolova – I. Pérez Martín 2 section, we present factual evidence and some considerations on the issue of “scientific plagiarism” in Palaiologan Byzantium. NICHOLAS RHABDAS, LIFE AND WORKS Enough of Nicholas Rhabdas’ scholarly production has been preserved for us to acknowledge his expertise in the mathematical sciences and especially his significant contribution to the domain of Byzantine logistic3. This is a branch of arithmetic in which a unit can be divided and that deals with counting numbers and with calculations on them4. Logistic developed greatly in Late Antiquity as a support to mathematical astronomy, and retained this role in Byzantine times5. As we shall see, Rhabdas was also engaged in astronomical matters and, in addition, composed a grammatical treatise for his son Paul Artabasdos6. 3 His production, however, was assessed in a way that is paradigmatic of a generalized dismissive attitude to Byzantine science; P. Tannery, Manuel Moschopoulos et Nicolas Rhabdas. Bulletin des Sciences mathématiques, 2e série, 8 (1884) 263–277, repr. Id., Mémoires Scientifiques IV. Toulouse–Paris 1920, 1–19: 15, in fact, passed the following judgment on Rhabdas’ writings, whose edition he nevertheless published two years later: “L’intérêt de ses écrits est surtout de montrer jusqu’où étaient tombés les héritiers dégénérés du nom hellène, ceux-là même qui avaient alors Diophante entre leurs mains”. 4 According to the 6th-century Neoplatonic commentator Eutocius, dividing the unit does not pertain to arithmetic but to logistic (J. L. Heiberg (ed.), Archimedis opera omnia cum commentariis Eutocii. I–III. Lipsiae 1910–15, III 120.28–30: ὥστ’ ἐπ’ ἐκείνων [scil. superparticular and superpartient ratios] διαιρετέον τὴν μονάδα, ὃ εἰ καὶ μὴ κατὰ τὸ προσῆκον τῇ ἀριθμητικῇ ἀλλὰ τῇ λογιστικῇ τυγχάνει “so that, for them one has to divide the unit, even if this does not happen to fit to arithmetic, but to logistic”). An earlier definition of logistic—which can almost certainly be ascribed to Geminus (a 1st-century BCE mathematically-minded philosopher, maybe a pupil of Posidonius)—does not allow dividing the unit. This definition can be found in pseudo-Hero, Def. 135.5–6 (J. L. Heiberg – L. Nix – W. Schmidt – H. Schöne (eds.), Heronis Alexandrini opera quae supersunt omnia. I–V. Lipsiae 1899–1914, IV 98.12–100.3), and is also preserved, through a different line of tradition, as a scholium to Plato, Chrm. 165e6 (Scholium 27 in D. Cufalo, Scholia Graeca in Platonem. I. Scholia ad dialogos tetralogiarum I–VII continens [Pleiadi 5.1]. Roma 2007, 173). It is possible that the domain of logistic was expanded to include fractional parts as a consequence of the adoption of the sexagesimal system in Greek mathematical astronomy. In fact, logistic developed greatly in Late Antiquity as a support to mathematical astronomy, and also played this same role in the Byzantine period. The first known treatise of this kind is included in the Prolegomena to the Almagest, and amounts to the (non-redacted) lecture notes of a course held in the circle of the Neoplatonic philosopher Ammonios. This treatise is a computational primer to the Almagest: a tightly organized “handbook of logistic” featuring as its main themes an introduction to the sexagesimal system, a description of computational algorithms for multiplication, division, and extraction of an approximate square root, a presentation of interpolation techniques, and an exposition about compounded ratios and removal of a ratio from a ratio. According to the anonymous author, no comprehensive previous exposition of this kind existed— and in fact no such one has been transmitted to us. See also note 125 below. The best introduction to Greek logistic is still K. Vogel, Beiträge zur griechischen Logistik. Erster Teil (Sitzungsberichte der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Mathematisch-naturwissenschaftliche Abteilung). Munich 1936, 357–472. 5 Cf. the explicit statement opening Anonymus 1252: A. Allard, Le premier traité byzantin de calcul indien: classement des manuscrits et édition critique du texte. Revue d’Histoire des Textes 7 (1977) 57–107: 80.2–4, and, in a smoother formulation, Planudes’ Great Calculation: A. Allard (ed.), Maxime Planude, Le grand calcul selon les Indiens. Louvain-la-Neuve 1981, 27.1–5. Despite its title (and the author’s statement similar to that of Planudes: P. Carelos [ed.], Βαρλαὰμ τοῦ Καλαβροῦ, Λογιστική, Barlaam von Seminara, Logistiké [Corpus philosophorum Medii Ævi. Philosophi byzantini 8]. Athens–Paris– Brussels 1996: 1.10–26), Barlaam’ Logistic is not a writing of logistic, but a fully-fledged treatise of theoretical arithmetic formulated in an impeccable demonstrative style. Barlaam (PLP, no. 2284), undisputably the Byzantine scholar best versed in mathematical matters and a major actor in the hesychastic controversy, died in 1348. 6 See PLP, no. 1438. The unpublished grammatical synopsis addressed to Paul is preserved in the miscellaneous ms. Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, gr. 2650 (Diktyon 52285), ff. 147r–150v. The copying is dated December 6, a.m. 6836 [= 1427] (f. 204v), certainly referring to ff. 201r–204v and possibly also to ff. 153r–167v and 168v–198v, penned by the same hand. However, the script of Rhabdas’ synopsis (located in quire no. ιθʹ, a ternion closed by the blank ff. 151r–152r) seems earlier, perhaps dating back to the middle – third quarter of the 14th century. The synopsis is presented as a grammatical compendium whose aim is expounding the appropriate use of words, in order to avoid barbarisms and solecisms. The exposition is based on analytical divisions of the main grammatical issues, treated by means of μικρούς τινας ὑπομνηματισμούς “some short notes”. It starts from letters (γράμματα and στοιχεῖα) and goes on dealing with syllables and words insofar as they are 3 The Source of Nicholas Rhabdas’ Letter to Khatzykes Much less is known about Rhabdas’ life, education, personal and professional networks. Until recently, the only temporal clue was provided by the fact that, i\",\"PeriodicalId\":194077,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Jahrbuch der Österreichischen Byzantinistik\",\"volume\":\"451 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"1900-01-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"1\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Jahrbuch der Österreichischen Byzantinistik\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1553/joeb68s1\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Jahrbuch der Österreichischen Byzantinistik","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1553/joeb68s1","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
摘要
事实上,《图卢兹-巴黎》1920,1-19:15,对Rhabdas的著作作出了以下判断,尽管他在两年后出版了他的版本:“L 'intérêt de ses samcrits est surtout de montrer jusqu 'où samtaient tom sams les hsamritiers dsamgsamrsams du nom hell<e:1>, ceux- l<s:2> même qui avaient alors Diophante entre leurs mains”。根据6世纪新柏拉图主义评论家Eutocius的说法,划分单位与算术无关,而与逻辑有关(J. L. Heiberg主编,Archimedis opera omnia cum commentariis Eutocii)。》。Lipsiae 1910 - 15,三世120.28 -30:ὥστ的ἐπ的ἐκείνων(scil。superparticular和superpartient比率)διαιρετέοντὴνμονάδα,ὃεἰκαὶμὴκατὰτὸπροσῆκοντῇἀριθμητικῇἀλλὰτῇλογιστικῇτυγχάνει”因此,他们必须划分单元,即使这并不适合算术,但物流”)。早期对物流的定义——几乎可以肯定是由Geminus(公元前1世纪的数学哲学家,可能是Posidonius的学生)提出的——不允许划分单位。这个定义可以在伪英雄,Def. 135.5-6 (J. L. Heiberg - L. Nix - W. Schmidt - H. Schöne(主编),Heronis Alexandrini opera quae supersuperomnia中找到。电流-电压。Lipsiae 1899-1914, IV 98.12-100.3),并且通过不同的传统,也被保存为柏拉图的学堂,Chrm. 165e6(学堂27在D. Cufalo,学堂在Platonem。1 .书香与对话:四合院I-VII大陆[昴宿星录5.1]。罗马2007,173)。有可能,逻辑的领域被扩展到包括分数部分,作为希腊数学天文学中采用六十进制系统的结果。事实上,逻辑学在古代晚期得到了极大的发展,作为对数学天文学的支持,在拜占庭时期也发挥了同样的作用。这类已知的第一篇论文包含在《至大论导论》中,相当于新柏拉图主义哲学家阿蒙尼奥斯(amonios)圈子里的一门课程的讲义(未经编辑)。这篇论文是Almagest的计算入门:一本组织严密的“逻辑手册”,其主要主题是介绍六十进制系统,描述乘法,除法和提取近似平方根的计算算法,介绍插值技术,并阐述复合比率和从比率中去除比率。根据匿名作者的说法,以前没有这种全面的阐述存在-事实上也没有这样的介绍给我们。又见下文附注125。最好的介绍希腊物流仍然是K. Vogel, Beiträge zur griechischen Logistik。巴伐利亚州科学与自然科学研究院,数学与自然科学与自然科学研究院。慕尼黑1936,357-472。5参考《匿名者》第1252篇开头的明确声明:A. Allard, Le premier trait<s:1> byzantin de calculus indien: classement des manuscrits et samdition critique du text。《文字史评论》7(1977)57-107:80.2-4,以及以更流畅的表述,《Planudes’Great Calculation: a . Allard(主编),Maxime Planude, Le grand Calculation selon les Indiens》。Louvain-la-Neuve 1981, 27.5 - 5。尽管它的标题(和作者的声明类似于Planudes: P. Carelos[编辑],Βαρλα ο μ το ο Καλαβρο ο, Λογιστική, Barlaam von Seminara, logistik<e:1>[媒体哲学文集Ævi]。拜占庭哲学[j]。雅典-巴黎-布鲁塞尔1996:1.10-26),巴拉姆的《逻辑》不是一部逻辑著作,而是一部以无可置疑的论证风格阐述的理论算术的成熟论文。巴拉姆(PLP),不。他无疑是拜占庭最精通数学问题的学者,也是这场神秘争议的主要参与者,于1348年去世。6见PLP, no。1438. 写给保罗的未发表的语法摘要保存在杂项的ms. Paris, biblioth<s:1> nationale de France, gr. 2650 (Diktyon 52285), ff。147 r - 150 v。抄写的日期是12月6日上午6836 [= 1427](f. 204v),肯定是指ff。201r-204v,也可能是ff。153r-167v和168v-198v,由同一手书写。然而,Rhabdas的剧本简介(位于quire no。ιθ′,由空白ff闭合的三元数。151r-152r)似乎更早,也许可以追溯到14世纪中叶。摘要是一个语法纲要,其目的是阐明适当的使用词,以避免野蛮和错误。本文的阐述是基于对主要语法问题的分析划分,并用μικ ο νας ομνημα ισμο ς“一些短音符”来处理。它从字母(γρ <s:2> μματα和στοιχε ε α)开始,并继续处理音节和单词,只要它们是3尼古拉斯·Rhabdas给哈齐克斯的信的来源关于Rhabdas的生活,教育,个人和职业网络的了解很少。 直到最近,唯一的时间线索是,我
The Source of Nicholas Rhabdas’ Letter to Khatzykes: An Anonymous Arithmetical Treatise in Vat. Barb. gr. 4
The article presents the edition and a detailed discussion of an anonymous treatise of elementary arithmetic that served as the source of the so-called Letter to Khatzykes authored by the Byzantine scholar Nicholas Artabasdos Rhabdas. An updated survey of the extant evidence about the logistic treatises composed in the Nicaean period and in the early Palaiologan era, and a discussion of the prima facie surprisingly widespread phenomenon of appropriation of scientific treatises written by other contemporaries in late Byzantine times will also be provided. This article presents the edition of an anonymous treatise of elementary arithmetic (henceforth called “Anonymus B”) contained, in slightly incomplete form, in ff. 171r–186v of the manuscript Città del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, Barberinianus gr. 4 (Diktyon 64552), to be dated to the beginning of the 14th century. The most important point of our study, however, does not lie in assessing Anonymus B in its own terms, but in showing that it served as the source of the so-called Letter to Khatzykes1 authored by the Byzantine scholar Nicholas Artabasdos Rhabdas2. That the First Letter and the anonymous treatise are very closely connected is obvious from their verbatim agreeing over large stretches of text; two series of facts decisively support our stronger claim about their filiation. First, the Barberini codex, produced within the circle of Maximos Planudes’ (d. ca. 1305) pupils, dates at the latest to the period of Rhabdas’ early activity. Second—and crucially, on account of the fact that the paleographical record does not completely settle the issue of priority—the involved variant readings, starting from the very titles of the two texts, strongly corroborate the hypothesis that Anonymus B is the source of Rhabdas’ First Letter, and not the inverse. As it also happens that an anonymous arithmetical treatise dated 1252 (henceforth “Anonymus 1252”) underwent a similar treatment in the hands of Planudes himself, resulting in his celebrated Great Calculation According to the Indians, we shall provide a revised outline of the extant evidence about the logistic treatises redacted in the Nicaean period (1204–61) and in the early Palaiologan era; we shall also argue, on grounds of style and contents, that Anonymus B and Anonymus 1252 were not composed by the same author. Consequently, we shall discuss the prima facie surprisingly widespread phenomenon, in late Byzantine times, of appropriation of scientific treatises written by other Byzantine scholars. The structure of the article is as follows. We first survey the evidence about Rhabdas’ scientific career; we then briefly describe Barb. gr. 4. The edition of Anonymus B, including the accompanying tables, is followed by an analysis of the textual differences with respect to Rhabdas’ First Letter, and by an assessment of the flourishing of logistic treatises in the middle of the 13th century. In the last * We are grateful to F. Valerio for a preliminary check of Vat. gr. 1481, to O. Delouis for pointing out a relevant text to us. This manuscript, Barb. gr. 4, and Chis. R.IV.20 have been collated at the Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana on June 6–8 and July 10–12, 2018. FA and IPM have been supported by the Research project “The Byzantine Author (II)” (MICINN, FFI201565118-C2-2-P). DM’s contribution was written as part of the project UMO-2015/19/P/HS2/02739, supported by the National Science Centre, Poland; this project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie grant agreement no. 665778. 1 Henceforth called First Letter. We shall see that there are two “letters” of arithmetical content authored by Rhabdas. 2 Rhabdas was born in Smyrna and was active in Constantinople about 1320–40; see PLP, no. 1437; ODB, 1786–1787; and the discussion in the next section. F. Acerbi – D. Manolova – I. Pérez Martín 2 section, we present factual evidence and some considerations on the issue of “scientific plagiarism” in Palaiologan Byzantium. NICHOLAS RHABDAS, LIFE AND WORKS Enough of Nicholas Rhabdas’ scholarly production has been preserved for us to acknowledge his expertise in the mathematical sciences and especially his significant contribution to the domain of Byzantine logistic3. This is a branch of arithmetic in which a unit can be divided and that deals with counting numbers and with calculations on them4. Logistic developed greatly in Late Antiquity as a support to mathematical astronomy, and retained this role in Byzantine times5. As we shall see, Rhabdas was also engaged in astronomical matters and, in addition, composed a grammatical treatise for his son Paul Artabasdos6. 3 His production, however, was assessed in a way that is paradigmatic of a generalized dismissive attitude to Byzantine science; P. Tannery, Manuel Moschopoulos et Nicolas Rhabdas. Bulletin des Sciences mathématiques, 2e série, 8 (1884) 263–277, repr. Id., Mémoires Scientifiques IV. Toulouse–Paris 1920, 1–19: 15, in fact, passed the following judgment on Rhabdas’ writings, whose edition he nevertheless published two years later: “L’intérêt de ses écrits est surtout de montrer jusqu’où étaient tombés les héritiers dégénérés du nom hellène, ceux-là même qui avaient alors Diophante entre leurs mains”. 4 According to the 6th-century Neoplatonic commentator Eutocius, dividing the unit does not pertain to arithmetic but to logistic (J. L. Heiberg (ed.), Archimedis opera omnia cum commentariis Eutocii. I–III. Lipsiae 1910–15, III 120.28–30: ὥστ’ ἐπ’ ἐκείνων [scil. superparticular and superpartient ratios] διαιρετέον τὴν μονάδα, ὃ εἰ καὶ μὴ κατὰ τὸ προσῆκον τῇ ἀριθμητικῇ ἀλλὰ τῇ λογιστικῇ τυγχάνει “so that, for them one has to divide the unit, even if this does not happen to fit to arithmetic, but to logistic”). An earlier definition of logistic—which can almost certainly be ascribed to Geminus (a 1st-century BCE mathematically-minded philosopher, maybe a pupil of Posidonius)—does not allow dividing the unit. This definition can be found in pseudo-Hero, Def. 135.5–6 (J. L. Heiberg – L. Nix – W. Schmidt – H. Schöne (eds.), Heronis Alexandrini opera quae supersunt omnia. I–V. Lipsiae 1899–1914, IV 98.12–100.3), and is also preserved, through a different line of tradition, as a scholium to Plato, Chrm. 165e6 (Scholium 27 in D. Cufalo, Scholia Graeca in Platonem. I. Scholia ad dialogos tetralogiarum I–VII continens [Pleiadi 5.1]. Roma 2007, 173). It is possible that the domain of logistic was expanded to include fractional parts as a consequence of the adoption of the sexagesimal system in Greek mathematical astronomy. In fact, logistic developed greatly in Late Antiquity as a support to mathematical astronomy, and also played this same role in the Byzantine period. The first known treatise of this kind is included in the Prolegomena to the Almagest, and amounts to the (non-redacted) lecture notes of a course held in the circle of the Neoplatonic philosopher Ammonios. This treatise is a computational primer to the Almagest: a tightly organized “handbook of logistic” featuring as its main themes an introduction to the sexagesimal system, a description of computational algorithms for multiplication, division, and extraction of an approximate square root, a presentation of interpolation techniques, and an exposition about compounded ratios and removal of a ratio from a ratio. According to the anonymous author, no comprehensive previous exposition of this kind existed— and in fact no such one has been transmitted to us. See also note 125 below. The best introduction to Greek logistic is still K. Vogel, Beiträge zur griechischen Logistik. Erster Teil (Sitzungsberichte der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Mathematisch-naturwissenschaftliche Abteilung). Munich 1936, 357–472. 5 Cf. the explicit statement opening Anonymus 1252: A. Allard, Le premier traité byzantin de calcul indien: classement des manuscrits et édition critique du texte. Revue d’Histoire des Textes 7 (1977) 57–107: 80.2–4, and, in a smoother formulation, Planudes’ Great Calculation: A. Allard (ed.), Maxime Planude, Le grand calcul selon les Indiens. Louvain-la-Neuve 1981, 27.1–5. Despite its title (and the author’s statement similar to that of Planudes: P. Carelos [ed.], Βαρλαὰμ τοῦ Καλαβροῦ, Λογιστική, Barlaam von Seminara, Logistiké [Corpus philosophorum Medii Ævi. Philosophi byzantini 8]. Athens–Paris– Brussels 1996: 1.10–26), Barlaam’ Logistic is not a writing of logistic, but a fully-fledged treatise of theoretical arithmetic formulated in an impeccable demonstrative style. Barlaam (PLP, no. 2284), undisputably the Byzantine scholar best versed in mathematical matters and a major actor in the hesychastic controversy, died in 1348. 6 See PLP, no. 1438. The unpublished grammatical synopsis addressed to Paul is preserved in the miscellaneous ms. Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, gr. 2650 (Diktyon 52285), ff. 147r–150v. The copying is dated December 6, a.m. 6836 [= 1427] (f. 204v), certainly referring to ff. 201r–204v and possibly also to ff. 153r–167v and 168v–198v, penned by the same hand. However, the script of Rhabdas’ synopsis (located in quire no. ιθʹ, a ternion closed by the blank ff. 151r–152r) seems earlier, perhaps dating back to the middle – third quarter of the 14th century. The synopsis is presented as a grammatical compendium whose aim is expounding the appropriate use of words, in order to avoid barbarisms and solecisms. The exposition is based on analytical divisions of the main grammatical issues, treated by means of μικρούς τινας ὑπομνηματισμούς “some short notes”. It starts from letters (γράμματα and στοιχεῖα) and goes on dealing with syllables and words insofar as they are 3 The Source of Nicholas Rhabdas’ Letter to Khatzykes Much less is known about Rhabdas’ life, education, personal and professional networks. Until recently, the only temporal clue was provided by the fact that, i