人类学的社会认识论:来自判断聚合的见解

Dagan Douglas
{"title":"人类学的社会认识论:来自判断聚合的见解","authors":"Dagan Douglas","doi":"10.7710/2155-4838.1177","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Anthropological writings have, at times, been vague in the approach used to gather evidence of cultural and social beliefs of the peoples studied, and the method of representing the data to the reading public. This paper employs the theory of judgment aggregation in critiquing anthropological theory and practice. It will be structured in three parts: first, I will present the theory of judgment aggregation as constructed by Christian List and Philip Pettit; second, I will sketch some epistemological methods used by anthropologists, and assess their attitude toward the notions of judgment aggregation and group agency; and finally, I will apply List and Pettit’s arguments about effective group organization to anthropological practice of representing its studied peoples’ beliefs and judgments by proposing three possible changes in method that will allow for more accurate and faithful interpretations and descriptions. Dagan Douglas Reed College douglasd@reed.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1177 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1177 Res Cogitans Judgment Aggregation An emerging subfield of epistemology, social epistemology has sought to uncover the social element inherent in certain forms of knowledge.1 It expands from epistemology’s exclusive focus on individuals into “investigating the epistemic effects of social interactions and social systems.” The field of judgment aggregation2 investigates “the epistemic quality of group doxastic attitudes (whatever their provenance may be),” and “the epistemic consequences of adopting certain institutional arrangements or systemic relations as opposed to alternatives” as well.3 List called this the “radical form” of social epistemology, wherein “certain multi-member groups themselves are taken to be epistemic agents capable of acquiring beliefs and knowledge.”4 Judgment aggregation, where judgments are binary expressions of attitudes,5 is concerned with the establishment of group doxastic attitudes (judgments and beliefs) out of individual doxastic attitudes.6 Juries determining defendants’ guilt or innocence, expert panels of scientists recommending policy, and bank committees forecasting future opportunities are just the sort of groups List and Pettit want to explore.7 Much of their work on judgment aggregation since their famous 2002 article “Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result” has been clarification of the aggregation procedure, defense of the existence of group agents, and suggestion for certain configurations of groups using certain aggregation procedures to produce certain results. I will now briefly sketch their views on each of these first two matters, 1 Alvin I. Goldman and Thomas Blanchard, “Social Epistemology,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), section 1, https://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/win2016/entries/epistemology-social. The authors place its formal beginnings in the 1970s and 1980s. 2 One of the many types of social epistemology to have developed since its inception. Alvin I. Goldman, “A Guide to Social Epistemology,” in Social Epistemology: Essential Readings, ed. by Alvin I. Goldman and Dennis Whitcomb (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 11. 3 Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, “Social Epistemology,” section 2 and 4.1-4.2. 4 Christian List, “Group Knowledge and Group Rationality: A Judgment Aggregation Perspective,” in Social Epistemology: Essential Readings, ed. by Alvin I. Goldman and Dennis Whitcomb (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 223. 5 Christian List and Philip Pettit, Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 37-38. 6 “A Guide to Social Epistemology,” 17. 7 “Group Knowledge,” 223. Douglas | The Social Epistemology of Anthropology commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans eP1177 | 3 and return to the third in my conclusion. Aggregation procedures “are mechanisms a multi-member group can use to combine (‘aggregate’) the individual beliefs or judgments held by the group members into collective beliefs or judgments endorsed by the group as a whole.”8 Groups like juries and federal agencies seek to make decisive judgments on important propositions whilst adhering to the dual constraints of responsiveness to the judgments of their composing individual members, and collective rationality across their judgments and over time.9 One example of many different possible procedures that such groups may implement is systematic majority voting on each proposition in question: the proposition is considered by itself by each member of the group, who give a binary affirmation or denial of its veracity; then, the ‘majority’ judgment on that proposition becomes the group’s judgment on it. In addition to responsiveness and rationality, the procedure, or “aggregation function” (“a mapping that assigns to each profile of individual attitudes towards the propositions on the agenda the collective attitudes towards these propositions”10), must also meet three more minimal conditions that List and Pettit claim we would expect “of plausible group attitude formation”: universal domain, anonymity, and systematicity.11 Universal domain is when “any possible profile of individual attitudes towards the propositions on the agenda” may be input to the function. Anonymity is when “all individuals’ attitudes are given equal weight in determining the group attitudes,” as in a secret ballot. And systematicity is when “the group attitude on each proposition depends only on the individuals’ attitudes towards it, not on their attitudes towards other propositions, and the pattern of dependence between individual and collective attitudes is the same for all propositions.” List and Pettit show that any organization attempting to meet all of these standards at once will fail to do so, an issue they dubbed the discursive paradox.12 To avoid it, they suggest ignoring at least one of these conditions, so that groups can still function while not being perfect. I return to this idea in the conclusion. 8 “Group Knowledge and Group Rationality: A Judgment Aggregation Perspective,” 222. 9 Christian List and Philip Pettit, “Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result,” Economics and Philosophy 18 (1) (2002): 91, 96. Rationality itself is bound by three of its own constraints, which are completeness, consistency, and deductive closure. See pages 97-98 for definition. 10 Group agency, 48. 11 Group agency, 49. 12 “Aggregating sets of judgments,” 95-96, 100. Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 4 | eP1177 Res Cogitans Judgment aggregation depends heavily on the notion of group agency, which might not be readily accepted as existing. List and Pettit claim that in everyday speech, we regularly ascribe to groups’ and organizations’ motivations and actions, such as the FBI investigating such and such suspects, or Goodwill wanting to hire this or that many employees. Not only do we find it acceptable to speak in this manner despite knowing that these groups exist only as collections of their members under certain organizing principles, but also, List and Pettit claim, we could not make sense of these groups as merely collections of individuals. They argue that these groups have agency apart from though arising from the agency of the individual members. List states that thinkers [M]ay be prepared to treat certain groups as agents, provided some stringent conditions are met.... In particular, to be an agent, a group must exhibit patterns of behaviour vis-a-vis the outside world that robustly satisfy certain rationality conditions... In short, a necessary condition for epistemic agency in a group is an institutional structure (formal or informal) that allows the group to endorse certain beliefs or judgments as collective ones; and the group’s performance as an epistemic agent [i.e. how they perform at acquiring beliefs or knowledge] depends on the details of that institutional structure.13 This definition allows groups, from corporations to tribes, to be considered group agents.","PeriodicalId":167127,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","volume":"42 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2018-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The Social Epistemology of Anthropology: Insights from Judgment Aggregation\",\"authors\":\"Dagan Douglas\",\"doi\":\"10.7710/2155-4838.1177\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Anthropological writings have, at times, been vague in the approach used to gather evidence of cultural and social beliefs of the peoples studied, and the method of representing the data to the reading public. This paper employs the theory of judgment aggregation in critiquing anthropological theory and practice. It will be structured in three parts: first, I will present the theory of judgment aggregation as constructed by Christian List and Philip Pettit; second, I will sketch some epistemological methods used by anthropologists, and assess their attitude toward the notions of judgment aggregation and group agency; and finally, I will apply List and Pettit’s arguments about effective group organization to anthropological practice of representing its studied peoples’ beliefs and judgments by proposing three possible changes in method that will allow for more accurate and faithful interpretations and descriptions. Dagan Douglas Reed College douglasd@reed.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1177 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1177 Res Cogitans Judgment Aggregation An emerging subfield of epistemology, social epistemology has sought to uncover the social element inherent in certain forms of knowledge.1 It expands from epistemology’s exclusive focus on individuals into “investigating the epistemic effects of social interactions and social systems.” The field of judgment aggregation2 investigates “the epistemic quality of group doxastic attitudes (whatever their provenance may be),” and “the epistemic consequences of adopting certain institutional arrangements or systemic relations as opposed to alternatives” as well.3 List called this the “radical form” of social epistemology, wherein “certain multi-member groups themselves are taken to be epistemic agents capable of acquiring beliefs and knowledge.”4 Judgment aggregation, where judgments are binary expressions of attitudes,5 is concerned with the establishment of group doxastic attitudes (judgments and beliefs) out of individual doxastic attitudes.6 Juries determining defendants’ guilt or innocence, expert panels of scientists recommending policy, and bank committees forecasting future opportunities are just the sort of groups List and Pettit want to explore.7 Much of their work on judgment aggregation since their famous 2002 article “Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result” has been clarification of the aggregation procedure, defense of the existence of group agents, and suggestion for certain configurations of groups using certain aggregation procedures to produce certain results. I will now briefly sketch their views on each of these first two matters, 1 Alvin I. Goldman and Thomas Blanchard, “Social Epistemology,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), section 1, https://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/win2016/entries/epistemology-social. The authors place its formal beginnings in the 1970s and 1980s. 2 One of the many types of social epistemology to have developed since its inception. Alvin I. Goldman, “A Guide to Social Epistemology,” in Social Epistemology: Essential Readings, ed. by Alvin I. Goldman and Dennis Whitcomb (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 11. 3 Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, “Social Epistemology,” section 2 and 4.1-4.2. 4 Christian List, “Group Knowledge and Group Rationality: A Judgment Aggregation Perspective,” in Social Epistemology: Essential Readings, ed. by Alvin I. Goldman and Dennis Whitcomb (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 223. 5 Christian List and Philip Pettit, Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 37-38. 6 “A Guide to Social Epistemology,” 17. 7 “Group Knowledge,” 223. Douglas | The Social Epistemology of Anthropology commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans eP1177 | 3 and return to the third in my conclusion. Aggregation procedures “are mechanisms a multi-member group can use to combine (‘aggregate’) the individual beliefs or judgments held by the group members into collective beliefs or judgments endorsed by the group as a whole.”8 Groups like juries and federal agencies seek to make decisive judgments on important propositions whilst adhering to the dual constraints of responsiveness to the judgments of their composing individual members, and collective rationality across their judgments and over time.9 One example of many different possible procedures that such groups may implement is systematic majority voting on each proposition in question: the proposition is considered by itself by each member of the group, who give a binary affirmation or denial of its veracity; then, the ‘majority’ judgment on that proposition becomes the group’s judgment on it. In addition to responsiveness and rationality, the procedure, or “aggregation function” (“a mapping that assigns to each profile of individual attitudes towards the propositions on the agenda the collective attitudes towards these propositions”10), must also meet three more minimal conditions that List and Pettit claim we would expect “of plausible group attitude formation”: universal domain, anonymity, and systematicity.11 Universal domain is when “any possible profile of individual attitudes towards the propositions on the agenda” may be input to the function. Anonymity is when “all individuals’ attitudes are given equal weight in determining the group attitudes,” as in a secret ballot. And systematicity is when “the group attitude on each proposition depends only on the individuals’ attitudes towards it, not on their attitudes towards other propositions, and the pattern of dependence between individual and collective attitudes is the same for all propositions.” List and Pettit show that any organization attempting to meet all of these standards at once will fail to do so, an issue they dubbed the discursive paradox.12 To avoid it, they suggest ignoring at least one of these conditions, so that groups can still function while not being perfect. I return to this idea in the conclusion. 8 “Group Knowledge and Group Rationality: A Judgment Aggregation Perspective,” 222. 9 Christian List and Philip Pettit, “Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result,” Economics and Philosophy 18 (1) (2002): 91, 96. Rationality itself is bound by three of its own constraints, which are completeness, consistency, and deductive closure. See pages 97-98 for definition. 10 Group agency, 48. 11 Group agency, 49. 12 “Aggregating sets of judgments,” 95-96, 100. Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 4 | eP1177 Res Cogitans Judgment aggregation depends heavily on the notion of group agency, which might not be readily accepted as existing. List and Pettit claim that in everyday speech, we regularly ascribe to groups’ and organizations’ motivations and actions, such as the FBI investigating such and such suspects, or Goodwill wanting to hire this or that many employees. Not only do we find it acceptable to speak in this manner despite knowing that these groups exist only as collections of their members under certain organizing principles, but also, List and Pettit claim, we could not make sense of these groups as merely collections of individuals. They argue that these groups have agency apart from though arising from the agency of the individual members. List states that thinkers [M]ay be prepared to treat certain groups as agents, provided some stringent conditions are met.... In particular, to be an agent, a group must exhibit patterns of behaviour vis-a-vis the outside world that robustly satisfy certain rationality conditions... In short, a necessary condition for epistemic agency in a group is an institutional structure (formal or informal) that allows the group to endorse certain beliefs or judgments as collective ones; and the group’s performance as an epistemic agent [i.e. how they perform at acquiring beliefs or knowledge] depends on the details of that institutional structure.13 This definition allows groups, from corporations to tribes, to be considered group agents.\",\"PeriodicalId\":167127,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities\",\"volume\":\"42 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2018-06-07\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1177\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1177","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

除了反应性和合理性之外,这个过程,或“聚合函数”(“将个人对议程上的命题的态度映射到集体对这些命题的态度”10),还必须满足三个更小的条件,即List和Pettit声称我们期望“合理的群体态度形成”的条件:普遍领域、匿名性和系统性普遍领域是指“个人对议程上的命题的态度的任何可能的轮廓”可以输入该函数。匿名是指“在决定群体态度时,所有个人的态度都得到同等的重视”,就像无记名投票一样。系统性是指"群体对每个命题的态度只取决于个体对这个命题的态度,而不取决于个体对其他命题的态度,个人态度和集体态度之间的依赖模式对所有命题都是一样的"李斯特和佩蒂特表明,任何试图同时满足所有这些标准的组织都将失败,他们将这个问题称为话语悖论为了避免这种情况,他们建议至少忽略这些条件中的一个,这样团队就可以在不完美的情况下继续运作。我在结论部分回到这个观点上来。8 .《群体知识与群体理性:一个判断聚合的视角》,第2期。9 Christian List和Philip Pettit,“集合判断集:一个不可能的结果”,《经济学与哲学》18(1)(2002):91,96。理性本身受三个自身约束的约束,即完备性、一致性和演绎封闭性。定义见第97-98页。10 .集团代理,48。11集团代理,49。12“判断的集合”,95-96,100。第9卷,第1期Res Cogitans 4 | Res Cogitans判断聚合在很大程度上依赖于群体代理的概念,这可能不容易被接受为存在。List和Pettit声称,在日常用语中,我们经常将其归因于团体和组织的动机和行为,例如FBI调查这样或那样的嫌疑人,或者Goodwill想要雇用这样或那样的员工。尽管我们知道这些群体只是在一定的组织原则下作为其成员的集合而存在,但我们不仅发现以这种方式说话是可以接受的,而且,List和Pettit声称,我们不能把这些群体仅仅理解为个人的集合。他们认为,这些群体除了产生于个体成员的能动性之外,还具有能动性。列表表明,思想家[M]可能准备将某些群体视为代理人,只要满足一些严格的条件....特别是,要成为一个主体,一个群体面对外部世界必须表现出强烈满足某些理性条件的行为模式……简而言之,群体中认知代理的必要条件是一个制度结构(正式的或非正式的),它允许群体认可某些信念或判断作为集体的;而群体作为认知主体的表现(即他们在获取信念或知识方面的表现)取决于该制度结构的细节这个定义允许从公司到部落的群体被视为群体代理。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The Social Epistemology of Anthropology: Insights from Judgment Aggregation
Anthropological writings have, at times, been vague in the approach used to gather evidence of cultural and social beliefs of the peoples studied, and the method of representing the data to the reading public. This paper employs the theory of judgment aggregation in critiquing anthropological theory and practice. It will be structured in three parts: first, I will present the theory of judgment aggregation as constructed by Christian List and Philip Pettit; second, I will sketch some epistemological methods used by anthropologists, and assess their attitude toward the notions of judgment aggregation and group agency; and finally, I will apply List and Pettit’s arguments about effective group organization to anthropological practice of representing its studied peoples’ beliefs and judgments by proposing three possible changes in method that will allow for more accurate and faithful interpretations and descriptions. Dagan Douglas Reed College douglasd@reed.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1177 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1177 Res Cogitans Judgment Aggregation An emerging subfield of epistemology, social epistemology has sought to uncover the social element inherent in certain forms of knowledge.1 It expands from epistemology’s exclusive focus on individuals into “investigating the epistemic effects of social interactions and social systems.” The field of judgment aggregation2 investigates “the epistemic quality of group doxastic attitudes (whatever their provenance may be),” and “the epistemic consequences of adopting certain institutional arrangements or systemic relations as opposed to alternatives” as well.3 List called this the “radical form” of social epistemology, wherein “certain multi-member groups themselves are taken to be epistemic agents capable of acquiring beliefs and knowledge.”4 Judgment aggregation, where judgments are binary expressions of attitudes,5 is concerned with the establishment of group doxastic attitudes (judgments and beliefs) out of individual doxastic attitudes.6 Juries determining defendants’ guilt or innocence, expert panels of scientists recommending policy, and bank committees forecasting future opportunities are just the sort of groups List and Pettit want to explore.7 Much of their work on judgment aggregation since their famous 2002 article “Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result” has been clarification of the aggregation procedure, defense of the existence of group agents, and suggestion for certain configurations of groups using certain aggregation procedures to produce certain results. I will now briefly sketch their views on each of these first two matters, 1 Alvin I. Goldman and Thomas Blanchard, “Social Epistemology,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), section 1, https://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/win2016/entries/epistemology-social. The authors place its formal beginnings in the 1970s and 1980s. 2 One of the many types of social epistemology to have developed since its inception. Alvin I. Goldman, “A Guide to Social Epistemology,” in Social Epistemology: Essential Readings, ed. by Alvin I. Goldman and Dennis Whitcomb (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 11. 3 Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, “Social Epistemology,” section 2 and 4.1-4.2. 4 Christian List, “Group Knowledge and Group Rationality: A Judgment Aggregation Perspective,” in Social Epistemology: Essential Readings, ed. by Alvin I. Goldman and Dennis Whitcomb (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 223. 5 Christian List and Philip Pettit, Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 37-38. 6 “A Guide to Social Epistemology,” 17. 7 “Group Knowledge,” 223. Douglas | The Social Epistemology of Anthropology commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans eP1177 | 3 and return to the third in my conclusion. Aggregation procedures “are mechanisms a multi-member group can use to combine (‘aggregate’) the individual beliefs or judgments held by the group members into collective beliefs or judgments endorsed by the group as a whole.”8 Groups like juries and federal agencies seek to make decisive judgments on important propositions whilst adhering to the dual constraints of responsiveness to the judgments of their composing individual members, and collective rationality across their judgments and over time.9 One example of many different possible procedures that such groups may implement is systematic majority voting on each proposition in question: the proposition is considered by itself by each member of the group, who give a binary affirmation or denial of its veracity; then, the ‘majority’ judgment on that proposition becomes the group’s judgment on it. In addition to responsiveness and rationality, the procedure, or “aggregation function” (“a mapping that assigns to each profile of individual attitudes towards the propositions on the agenda the collective attitudes towards these propositions”10), must also meet three more minimal conditions that List and Pettit claim we would expect “of plausible group attitude formation”: universal domain, anonymity, and systematicity.11 Universal domain is when “any possible profile of individual attitudes towards the propositions on the agenda” may be input to the function. Anonymity is when “all individuals’ attitudes are given equal weight in determining the group attitudes,” as in a secret ballot. And systematicity is when “the group attitude on each proposition depends only on the individuals’ attitudes towards it, not on their attitudes towards other propositions, and the pattern of dependence between individual and collective attitudes is the same for all propositions.” List and Pettit show that any organization attempting to meet all of these standards at once will fail to do so, an issue they dubbed the discursive paradox.12 To avoid it, they suggest ignoring at least one of these conditions, so that groups can still function while not being perfect. I return to this idea in the conclusion. 8 “Group Knowledge and Group Rationality: A Judgment Aggregation Perspective,” 222. 9 Christian List and Philip Pettit, “Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result,” Economics and Philosophy 18 (1) (2002): 91, 96. Rationality itself is bound by three of its own constraints, which are completeness, consistency, and deductive closure. See pages 97-98 for definition. 10 Group agency, 48. 11 Group agency, 49. 12 “Aggregating sets of judgments,” 95-96, 100. Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 4 | eP1177 Res Cogitans Judgment aggregation depends heavily on the notion of group agency, which might not be readily accepted as existing. List and Pettit claim that in everyday speech, we regularly ascribe to groups’ and organizations’ motivations and actions, such as the FBI investigating such and such suspects, or Goodwill wanting to hire this or that many employees. Not only do we find it acceptable to speak in this manner despite knowing that these groups exist only as collections of their members under certain organizing principles, but also, List and Pettit claim, we could not make sense of these groups as merely collections of individuals. They argue that these groups have agency apart from though arising from the agency of the individual members. List states that thinkers [M]ay be prepared to treat certain groups as agents, provided some stringent conditions are met.... In particular, to be an agent, a group must exhibit patterns of behaviour vis-a-vis the outside world that robustly satisfy certain rationality conditions... In short, a necessary condition for epistemic agency in a group is an institutional structure (formal or informal) that allows the group to endorse certain beliefs or judgments as collective ones; and the group’s performance as an epistemic agent [i.e. how they perform at acquiring beliefs or knowledge] depends on the details of that institutional structure.13 This definition allows groups, from corporations to tribes, to be considered group agents.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信