在1938-1940年凯恩斯-丁伯根交换的《概率论》中,对凯恩斯的不精确、近似测量方法的无知所起的作用

M. E. Brady
{"title":"在1938-1940年凯恩斯-丁伯根交换的《概率论》中,对凯恩斯的不精确、近似测量方法的无知所起的作用","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3353637","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"There is no evidence that J. Tinbergen ever read the technical analysis provided by J. M. Keynes in Parts II and V of the A Treatise on Probability in the 1938-1940 time period or at any later time in his life. The same conclusion holds for econometricians in general. They simply do not understand what Keynes’s Inexact, Approximation Approach to Measurement in the A Treatise on Probability entails. \n \nTinbergen and Keynes held diametrically opposed positions on measurement. Tinbergen’s approach to measurement was guided by the Limiting Frequency interpretation of probability while Keynes’s approach followed the logical approach of George Boole. Tinbergen’s physics background led him to deploy an exact approach to measurement based on the specification of probability distributions, like the normal and lognormal, with exact and precisely defined measurements. All probabilities were assumed to be well defined, precise, exact, determinate, definite, additive, linear, independent single number of answers. Keynes’s approach was an inexact one to measurement based on his modification of Boole’s original approach in 1854 in The Laws of Thought in chapters 16-21. Probabilities for Keynes were, with a few exceptions, partially defined, imprecise, inexact, indefinite, indeterminate, nonadditive, nonlinear, and dependent. Probability estimates for Keynes required two numbers to specify the probability within a lower and upper bound(limit), and nor one like Tinbergen’s approach. Keynes called this approach Approximation. Keynesian probabilities are interval-valued. There are no more than a single handful of academics, worldwide today, who grasp the fact that Keynes’s approach to measurement in the A Treatise on Probability was an interval-valued approach that was covered by Keynes in chapters III and XV. \n \nThere was no economist alive in the late 1930’s-1940’s who understood Keynes’s approach in the A Treatise on Probability. An example of this ignorance is Lawrence Klein’s review in 1951 of Harrod’s biography of Keynes. \n \nThe assessments of the Keynes –Tinbergen exchanges in 1938-40 were practically identical to the assessment made of the A Treatise on Probability by Ronald Fisher in his 1923 Eugenics Review of the A Treatise on Probability, where Fisher completely overlooked the inexact approach to measurement that Keynes presented in Parts I –V of the A Treatise on Probability. He dismissed the A Treatise on Probability based on his belief that Keynes was arguing that probability could not be applied since it was, at best, ordinal in nature. \n \nOnly one economist in the 20th century understood exactly what it was that Keynes had done in the A Treatise on Probability. That economist was named F. Y. Edgeworth. However, Edgeworth died in 1926. His two 1922 book reviews of the A Treatise on Probability required a great deal of mathematical and statistical competence on the part of a reader. That mathematical competence was missing from the economics profession in the late 1930s and 1940s. The result was that Edgeworth’s two superb reviews were forgotten and never read by economists. \n \nThe problem, from Keynes’s perspective, was that Tinbergen was trying to apply to economic data techniques which were only sound in physics, where laboratory controlled environments with detailed experimental design could generate data and replicate/duplicate the experiments worldwide. Keynes had always argued that economics was not a physical or life science like physics, engineering, biology or chemistry and that it could never be like physics. A great abyss thus separated Tinbergen from Keynes from the very start of the private exchange of letters that began in 1938 to the final exchanges in the 1939-40 time period in the Economic Journal. Tinbergen’s complete and total ignorance of Keynes’s approach to inexact measurement meant that the possibility of some type of intellectual compromise was impossible from the very start. \n \nThe main reason for the completely divergent views expressed by Keynes and Tinbergen in their 1938-40 exchanges in the Economic Journal was due to their completely different technical backgrounds. Keynes’s background was logic, mathematics, and philosophy. Tinbergen’s background was physics. There simply was no common ground between the two academics.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-03-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The Role of Ignorance About Keynes’s Inexact, Approximation Approach to Measurement in the A Treatise on Probability in the Keynes-Tinbergen Exchanges of 1938–1940\",\"authors\":\"M. E. Brady\",\"doi\":\"10.2139/ssrn.3353637\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"There is no evidence that J. Tinbergen ever read the technical analysis provided by J. M. Keynes in Parts II and V of the A Treatise on Probability in the 1938-1940 time period or at any later time in his life. The same conclusion holds for econometricians in general. They simply do not understand what Keynes’s Inexact, Approximation Approach to Measurement in the A Treatise on Probability entails. \\n \\nTinbergen and Keynes held diametrically opposed positions on measurement. Tinbergen’s approach to measurement was guided by the Limiting Frequency interpretation of probability while Keynes’s approach followed the logical approach of George Boole. Tinbergen’s physics background led him to deploy an exact approach to measurement based on the specification of probability distributions, like the normal and lognormal, with exact and precisely defined measurements. All probabilities were assumed to be well defined, precise, exact, determinate, definite, additive, linear, independent single number of answers. Keynes’s approach was an inexact one to measurement based on his modification of Boole’s original approach in 1854 in The Laws of Thought in chapters 16-21. Probabilities for Keynes were, with a few exceptions, partially defined, imprecise, inexact, indefinite, indeterminate, nonadditive, nonlinear, and dependent. Probability estimates for Keynes required two numbers to specify the probability within a lower and upper bound(limit), and nor one like Tinbergen’s approach. Keynes called this approach Approximation. Keynesian probabilities are interval-valued. There are no more than a single handful of academics, worldwide today, who grasp the fact that Keynes’s approach to measurement in the A Treatise on Probability was an interval-valued approach that was covered by Keynes in chapters III and XV. \\n \\nThere was no economist alive in the late 1930’s-1940’s who understood Keynes’s approach in the A Treatise on Probability. An example of this ignorance is Lawrence Klein’s review in 1951 of Harrod’s biography of Keynes. \\n \\nThe assessments of the Keynes –Tinbergen exchanges in 1938-40 were practically identical to the assessment made of the A Treatise on Probability by Ronald Fisher in his 1923 Eugenics Review of the A Treatise on Probability, where Fisher completely overlooked the inexact approach to measurement that Keynes presented in Parts I –V of the A Treatise on Probability. He dismissed the A Treatise on Probability based on his belief that Keynes was arguing that probability could not be applied since it was, at best, ordinal in nature. \\n \\nOnly one economist in the 20th century understood exactly what it was that Keynes had done in the A Treatise on Probability. That economist was named F. Y. Edgeworth. However, Edgeworth died in 1926. His two 1922 book reviews of the A Treatise on Probability required a great deal of mathematical and statistical competence on the part of a reader. That mathematical competence was missing from the economics profession in the late 1930s and 1940s. The result was that Edgeworth’s two superb reviews were forgotten and never read by economists. \\n \\nThe problem, from Keynes’s perspective, was that Tinbergen was trying to apply to economic data techniques which were only sound in physics, where laboratory controlled environments with detailed experimental design could generate data and replicate/duplicate the experiments worldwide. Keynes had always argued that economics was not a physical or life science like physics, engineering, biology or chemistry and that it could never be like physics. A great abyss thus separated Tinbergen from Keynes from the very start of the private exchange of letters that began in 1938 to the final exchanges in the 1939-40 time period in the Economic Journal. Tinbergen’s complete and total ignorance of Keynes’s approach to inexact measurement meant that the possibility of some type of intellectual compromise was impossible from the very start. \\n \\nThe main reason for the completely divergent views expressed by Keynes and Tinbergen in their 1938-40 exchanges in the Economic Journal was due to their completely different technical backgrounds. Keynes’s background was logic, mathematics, and philosophy. Tinbergen’s background was physics. There simply was no common ground between the two academics.\",\"PeriodicalId\":226815,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2019-03-16\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"1\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3353637\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3353637","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

摘要

没有证据表明丁伯根曾在1938-1940年期间或在他生命的任何后期阅读过凯恩斯在《概率论》(A Treatise on Probability)第二部分和第五部分中提供的技术分析。同样的结论也适用于一般的计量经济学家。他们根本不理解凯恩斯在《概率论》中提出的不精确、近似的测量方法意味着什么。丁伯根和凯恩斯在测量上持截然相反的立场。丁伯根的测量方法以概率的极限频率解释为指导,而凯恩斯的方法遵循乔治·布尔的逻辑方法。Tinbergen的物理学背景使他采用了一种精确的测量方法,该方法基于概率分布的规范,如正态和对数正态,具有精确和精确定义的测量。所有的概率都被假定为定义良好的、精确的、精确的、确定的、确定的、可加的、线性的、独立的单一个数的答案。1854年,凯恩斯在《思想法则》第16-21章对布尔的原始方法进行了修改,他的方法是一种不精确的测量方法。除了少数例外,凯恩斯的概率是部分定义的、不精确的、不精确的、不确定的、不确定的、非加性的、非线性的和依赖的。凯恩斯的概率估计需要两个数字来指定在下限和上限(极限)内的概率,而不是像Tinbergen的方法那样一个数字。凯恩斯称这种方法为近似。凯恩斯概率是区间值的。今天,全世界只有少数学者认识到,凯恩斯在《概率论》中的测量方法是凯恩斯在第三章和第十五章中所涵盖的区间值方法。在20世纪30年代末到40年代,没有一个经济学家能理解凯恩斯在《概率论》(A Treatise on Probability)中的方法。这种无知的一个例子是劳伦斯·克莱因1951年对哈罗德的凯恩斯传记的评论。1938-40年凯恩斯-丁伯根交换的评估实际上与罗纳德·费雪在1923年对《概率论》的优生学评论中对《概率论》所做的评估相同,费雪完全忽略了凯恩斯在《概率论》第1 - 5部分中提出的不精确的测量方法。他驳回了《概率论》,因为他相信凯恩斯认为概率不能应用,因为它充其量是序数性质的。在20世纪,只有一位经济学家能够准确理解凯恩斯在《概率论》(A Treatise on Probability)中所做的事情。这位经济学家名叫f·y·埃奇沃斯。然而,埃奇沃斯于1926年去世。1922年,他对《概率论》(A Treatise on Probability)的两篇书评要求读者具备很强的数学和统计能力。这种数学能力在20世纪30年代末和40年代的经济学专业中是缺失的。其结果是,埃奇沃斯的两篇极好的评论被遗忘了,经济学家从未读过。从凯恩斯的角度来看,问题在于丁伯根试图应用于经济数据技术,而这些技术只适用于物理学,在物理学中,具有详细实验设计的实验室控制环境可以生成数据并在全球范围内复制实验。凯恩斯一直认为,经济学不像物理学、工程学、生物学或化学那样是一门物理或生命科学,也永远不可能像物理学那样。从1938年开始的私人书信往来,到1939年至1940年在《经济杂志》(Economic Journal)上的最后书信往来,丁伯根和凯恩斯之间存在着巨大的鸿沟。丁伯根对凯恩斯的不精确测量方法完全无知,这意味着某种智力妥协的可能性从一开始就是不可能的。凯恩斯和丁伯根1938- 1940年在《经济杂志》上的交流中表达了完全不同的观点,主要原因是他们的技术背景完全不同。凯恩斯的背景是逻辑学、数学和哲学。丁伯根的背景是物理学。这两位学者之间根本没有共同点。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The Role of Ignorance About Keynes’s Inexact, Approximation Approach to Measurement in the A Treatise on Probability in the Keynes-Tinbergen Exchanges of 1938–1940
There is no evidence that J. Tinbergen ever read the technical analysis provided by J. M. Keynes in Parts II and V of the A Treatise on Probability in the 1938-1940 time period or at any later time in his life. The same conclusion holds for econometricians in general. They simply do not understand what Keynes’s Inexact, Approximation Approach to Measurement in the A Treatise on Probability entails. Tinbergen and Keynes held diametrically opposed positions on measurement. Tinbergen’s approach to measurement was guided by the Limiting Frequency interpretation of probability while Keynes’s approach followed the logical approach of George Boole. Tinbergen’s physics background led him to deploy an exact approach to measurement based on the specification of probability distributions, like the normal and lognormal, with exact and precisely defined measurements. All probabilities were assumed to be well defined, precise, exact, determinate, definite, additive, linear, independent single number of answers. Keynes’s approach was an inexact one to measurement based on his modification of Boole’s original approach in 1854 in The Laws of Thought in chapters 16-21. Probabilities for Keynes were, with a few exceptions, partially defined, imprecise, inexact, indefinite, indeterminate, nonadditive, nonlinear, and dependent. Probability estimates for Keynes required two numbers to specify the probability within a lower and upper bound(limit), and nor one like Tinbergen’s approach. Keynes called this approach Approximation. Keynesian probabilities are interval-valued. There are no more than a single handful of academics, worldwide today, who grasp the fact that Keynes’s approach to measurement in the A Treatise on Probability was an interval-valued approach that was covered by Keynes in chapters III and XV. There was no economist alive in the late 1930’s-1940’s who understood Keynes’s approach in the A Treatise on Probability. An example of this ignorance is Lawrence Klein’s review in 1951 of Harrod’s biography of Keynes. The assessments of the Keynes –Tinbergen exchanges in 1938-40 were practically identical to the assessment made of the A Treatise on Probability by Ronald Fisher in his 1923 Eugenics Review of the A Treatise on Probability, where Fisher completely overlooked the inexact approach to measurement that Keynes presented in Parts I –V of the A Treatise on Probability. He dismissed the A Treatise on Probability based on his belief that Keynes was arguing that probability could not be applied since it was, at best, ordinal in nature. Only one economist in the 20th century understood exactly what it was that Keynes had done in the A Treatise on Probability. That economist was named F. Y. Edgeworth. However, Edgeworth died in 1926. His two 1922 book reviews of the A Treatise on Probability required a great deal of mathematical and statistical competence on the part of a reader. That mathematical competence was missing from the economics profession in the late 1930s and 1940s. The result was that Edgeworth’s two superb reviews were forgotten and never read by economists. The problem, from Keynes’s perspective, was that Tinbergen was trying to apply to economic data techniques which were only sound in physics, where laboratory controlled environments with detailed experimental design could generate data and replicate/duplicate the experiments worldwide. Keynes had always argued that economics was not a physical or life science like physics, engineering, biology or chemistry and that it could never be like physics. A great abyss thus separated Tinbergen from Keynes from the very start of the private exchange of letters that began in 1938 to the final exchanges in the 1939-40 time period in the Economic Journal. Tinbergen’s complete and total ignorance of Keynes’s approach to inexact measurement meant that the possibility of some type of intellectual compromise was impossible from the very start. The main reason for the completely divergent views expressed by Keynes and Tinbergen in their 1938-40 exchanges in the Economic Journal was due to their completely different technical backgrounds. Keynes’s background was logic, mathematics, and philosophy. Tinbergen’s background was physics. There simply was no common ground between the two academics.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信