塔木德注释和规范自我批判的问题

M. Fisch
{"title":"塔木德注释和规范自我批判的问题","authors":"M. Fisch","doi":"10.5771/9783835345195-27","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Aristotle famously defined humans as rational animals, as creatures whose exclusive defining property is their ability to be moved by reasons. Interestingly, within Jewish tradition one finds a seemingly different human property displayed as exclusive and defining: our capacity for speech. The eleventh-century poet and philosopher Judah Halevy famously distinguished humankind from the inanimate, vegetative, and organic world by its power of speech.1 A millennium earlier, Onkelos, the Aramaic translator of the Hebrew Bible, rendered the famous description of God breathing »the breath of life« into Adam’s nostrils (Gen 2:7) as breathing into them »the spirit of speech«. The two human qualities – rationality and speech – would seem not only to be different, but to pertain to very different realms of human activity: rationality, to the inner realm of mind and self, the essentially intra-subjective sphere of thinking and pondering; and speech, to the essentially outer, dialogical inter-personal, social space of questioning and answering, addressing and responding, agreeing and disagreeing. The two are obviously connected. Both require language, for example, without which options cannot be rationally weighed or even thought about. Thinking is, in an important sense, a form of inner speech. And by the same token, one cannot engage meaningfully in conversation with others without exercising one’s rational capacities. The question of the relative primacy of thinking and speaking has a history of its own. Until recently, most philosophers followed Descartes in maintaining that thinking is primary, and that to speak is merely to convey one’s thoughts to others by means of a shared vocabulary. More recently there has been a resolute tendency to reverse the arrow of explanation, and view speaking as primary and thinking as internalized speech. Michael Dummett and Robert Brandom stand out in this regard.2 The main claim of this paper is different, and has received scarce attention in the philosophical literature to date. It is that one can get only so far by thinking alone; that to act and live rationally requires talking to others. Stronger still : that we can live up to our full rational capacity only by engaging in dialogue with others. And the emphasis will be first on dialogue, namely, on real, non-Socratic, discursive exchange, and second, on others, namely, on doing so with people genuinely committed differently. The following pages first make the case for this twofold claim by defining rationality as I employ the term, exposing its central relation to critique, pointing to the","PeriodicalId":259032,"journal":{"name":"Geschichte der Philologien","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Talmudic Commentary and the Problem of Normative Self-Critique\",\"authors\":\"M. Fisch\",\"doi\":\"10.5771/9783835345195-27\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Aristotle famously defined humans as rational animals, as creatures whose exclusive defining property is their ability to be moved by reasons. Interestingly, within Jewish tradition one finds a seemingly different human property displayed as exclusive and defining: our capacity for speech. The eleventh-century poet and philosopher Judah Halevy famously distinguished humankind from the inanimate, vegetative, and organic world by its power of speech.1 A millennium earlier, Onkelos, the Aramaic translator of the Hebrew Bible, rendered the famous description of God breathing »the breath of life« into Adam’s nostrils (Gen 2:7) as breathing into them »the spirit of speech«. The two human qualities – rationality and speech – would seem not only to be different, but to pertain to very different realms of human activity: rationality, to the inner realm of mind and self, the essentially intra-subjective sphere of thinking and pondering; and speech, to the essentially outer, dialogical inter-personal, social space of questioning and answering, addressing and responding, agreeing and disagreeing. The two are obviously connected. Both require language, for example, without which options cannot be rationally weighed or even thought about. Thinking is, in an important sense, a form of inner speech. And by the same token, one cannot engage meaningfully in conversation with others without exercising one’s rational capacities. The question of the relative primacy of thinking and speaking has a history of its own. Until recently, most philosophers followed Descartes in maintaining that thinking is primary, and that to speak is merely to convey one’s thoughts to others by means of a shared vocabulary. More recently there has been a resolute tendency to reverse the arrow of explanation, and view speaking as primary and thinking as internalized speech. Michael Dummett and Robert Brandom stand out in this regard.2 The main claim of this paper is different, and has received scarce attention in the philosophical literature to date. It is that one can get only so far by thinking alone; that to act and live rationally requires talking to others. Stronger still : that we can live up to our full rational capacity only by engaging in dialogue with others. And the emphasis will be first on dialogue, namely, on real, non-Socratic, discursive exchange, and second, on others, namely, on doing so with people genuinely committed differently. The following pages first make the case for this twofold claim by defining rationality as I employ the term, exposing its central relation to critique, pointing to the\",\"PeriodicalId\":259032,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Geschichte der Philologien\",\"volume\":\"1 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"1900-01-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Geschichte der Philologien\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.5771/9783835345195-27\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Geschichte der Philologien","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5771/9783835345195-27","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

亚里士多德著名地将人类定义为理性动物,作为一种生物,其唯一的定义属性是他们能够被理性所感动。有趣的是,在犹太人的传统中,人们发现一种看似不同的人类属性被显示为排他性和决定性的:我们的语言能力。11世纪的诗人和哲学家犹大·哈勒维以其说话的能力将人类与无生命、植物和有机世界区分开来一千年前,希伯来圣经的阿拉姆语翻译家昂基罗斯(Onkelos)将上帝将“生命的气息”吹进亚当的鼻孔(创世记2:7)的著名描述翻译为“说话的灵”。人类的两种品质——理性和言语——似乎不仅是不同的,而且属于非常不同的人类活动领域:理性,属于心灵和自我的内在领域,本质上是思维和思考的内在主体领域;演讲,本质上是外部的,对话的人际关系,提问和回答,称呼和回应,同意和不同意的社会空间。这两者显然是有联系的。例如,两者都需要语言,没有语言,人们就无法理性地权衡甚至思考各种选择。在一个重要的意义上,思维是一种内心的话语。出于同样的原因,一个人如果不运用自己的理性能力,就无法与他人进行有意义的对话。思考和说话相对首要的问题有它自己的历史。直到最近,大多数哲学家都遵循笛卡尔的观点,认为思考是首要的,说话只不过是通过共同的词汇将自己的思想传达给他人。最近出现了一种坚决的倾向,把解释的箭头颠倒过来,把说话看作是原始的,把思考看作是内化的说话。迈克尔·达米特和罗伯特·布兰顿在这方面表现突出这篇论文的主要主张是不同的,并且在迄今为止的哲学文献中很少受到关注。那就是一个人只能靠自己的思考走到这一步;理性地行动和生活需要与他人交谈。更重要的是:只有与他人对话,我们才能充分发挥自己的理性能力。重点将首先放在对话上,即真实的,非苏格拉底式的,话语性的交流,其次放在他人上,即与真正有不同承诺的人进行对话。下面的章节首先通过定义我所使用的“理性”一词,揭示其与批判的中心关系,来论证这一双重主张
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Talmudic Commentary and the Problem of Normative Self-Critique
Aristotle famously defined humans as rational animals, as creatures whose exclusive defining property is their ability to be moved by reasons. Interestingly, within Jewish tradition one finds a seemingly different human property displayed as exclusive and defining: our capacity for speech. The eleventh-century poet and philosopher Judah Halevy famously distinguished humankind from the inanimate, vegetative, and organic world by its power of speech.1 A millennium earlier, Onkelos, the Aramaic translator of the Hebrew Bible, rendered the famous description of God breathing »the breath of life« into Adam’s nostrils (Gen 2:7) as breathing into them »the spirit of speech«. The two human qualities – rationality and speech – would seem not only to be different, but to pertain to very different realms of human activity: rationality, to the inner realm of mind and self, the essentially intra-subjective sphere of thinking and pondering; and speech, to the essentially outer, dialogical inter-personal, social space of questioning and answering, addressing and responding, agreeing and disagreeing. The two are obviously connected. Both require language, for example, without which options cannot be rationally weighed or even thought about. Thinking is, in an important sense, a form of inner speech. And by the same token, one cannot engage meaningfully in conversation with others without exercising one’s rational capacities. The question of the relative primacy of thinking and speaking has a history of its own. Until recently, most philosophers followed Descartes in maintaining that thinking is primary, and that to speak is merely to convey one’s thoughts to others by means of a shared vocabulary. More recently there has been a resolute tendency to reverse the arrow of explanation, and view speaking as primary and thinking as internalized speech. Michael Dummett and Robert Brandom stand out in this regard.2 The main claim of this paper is different, and has received scarce attention in the philosophical literature to date. It is that one can get only so far by thinking alone; that to act and live rationally requires talking to others. Stronger still : that we can live up to our full rational capacity only by engaging in dialogue with others. And the emphasis will be first on dialogue, namely, on real, non-Socratic, discursive exchange, and second, on others, namely, on doing so with people genuinely committed differently. The following pages first make the case for this twofold claim by defining rationality as I employ the term, exposing its central relation to critique, pointing to the
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信