《怪诞的情感哲学

L. Currie
{"title":"《怪诞的情感哲学","authors":"L. Currie","doi":"10.5399/UO/OURJ.14.1.2","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Through an analysis of Søren Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata from the first volume of Either/Or, a work which exhibits strikingly contemporary ways of thinking, this paper seeks to uncover the complex and paradoxical ways in which emotions inhabit a person. The urge to explicate the complexity of emotions arose from the author’s dissatisfaction with the rudimentary schematic used in daily life wherein emotions are categorized and hastily rationalized, misconstruing their greater complexity. Emotions are often irrational, contradictory, etc., and must be considered on those terms. Thus, concession of paradox is vital in order to think through contradictory states of emotions. An aphorism from Pascal states that we are nothing but “lies, duplicity, and contradiction.” With this idea in mind, the essay proceeds to argue that the use of pseudonyms to create contradictions within Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata show the Diapsalmata functioning as a “monstrous” philosophy of emotions. What is meant by “monstrous” differs from the colloquial use of the term and the essay’s particular usage is discussed with reference to Socrates and Typhon in Plato’s Phaedrus. The paper claims that Kierkegaard's thought as a whole is “monstrous” in the dissonance of the religious, comedic, ethical, ironic, and aesthetic stages he constructs in his broader philosophy. The monstrous philosophy of emotions developed from the Diapsalmata is argued to have a “prefatory weight” on the question of Being, i.e. “why are there beings instead of nothing?” The way in which different emotions preface this question is briefly discussed. The conclusion emphasizes the importance of understanding the complexity of emotions philosophically. “Talk about humility gives occasion for pride to the proud and humility to the humble. Similarly, skeptical arguments allow the positive to be positive. Few speak humbly of humility, chastely of chastity, dubiously of skepticism. We are nothing but lies, duplicity, contradiction, and we hide and disguise ourselves from ourselves” (Pascal, 240). Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal Currie Volume 14 Issue 1 Winter 2019 2 Despite the radical tone of Pascal’s claim that we solely consist of “lies, duplicity, and contradiction,” his hyperbolic insistence that we are nothing but is a poetic device indicating his claim should not be taken literally. One might then dismiss this as one of Pascal’s characteristically gloomy formulations and deem it unworthy of being taken seriously. Yet to do this would evade the very real force of his claim: to what degree do I disguise myself from myself? Am I merely a sum of contradictions masquerading as a quasi-coherent self? Is not the self which I present to the world ever-changing, duplicitous, multiplicitous? Is not this self, too, a fiction? One created out of an inability to account for my contradictions? The range of questions which erupt from Pascal’s aphorism must be circumscribed if one wishes to attain anything like an answer to them. One way in which we most overtly contradict ourselves is in and through our emotions. Such contradictions are monstrous insofar as the self which experiences these contradictory emotions is a whole self-made of discordant parts, namely differing emotional states, rather than a whole comprised of harmonious, non-contradictory parts. Pascal addresses the issue of a contradictory self succinctly in his aphorism while Søren Kierkegaard “performs” it in his Diapsalmata and in his works in general. This preliminary reflection inspired by Pascal’s aphorism leads me to consider Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata as a monstrous philosophy of emotions. Before addressing the relationship between the different moods which appear in the Diapsalmata, I shall provide some context for that work. The authorship of Kierkegaard's Either/Or is obfuscated by pseudonyms. Either/Or is, as discussed in its preface by Victor Eremita, Kierkegaard’s first pseudonym, a collection of essays, letters, and fragments from two authors whom Eremita discovered. He names them A and B, respectively. Author A’s writings are inclined toward the “aesthetic” while Author B is inclined toward the “ethical.” Either/Or is principally a work which attempts to put these two authors and the aesthetic and ethical they represent in dialectical tension. Along with these three pseudonyms, Author A discovers a diary of a man named Johannes, giving us a fourth pseudonym. Eremita embeds this diary within A’s own works, seeing that Johannes’ diary shares a similar aesthetic comportment to A’s own writings and believing Author A and Johannes to be the same person. Yet, of course, all of these authors are just Kierkegaard playing different roles. Through the power of the pseudonym and the obfuscation of authorship, Kierkegaard takes on the roles of a discoverer and editor of unknown works, an aesthetic writer of melancholic poetry and philosophy, a judge who rebuts the aesthetic writer’s stance in favor of the ethical, and so on. While Pascal uses poetic hyperbole to confront man’s contradictions, Kierkegaard textually “performs” these contradictions through the writings of the pseudonyms. These contradictions only begin to show when considering Kierkegaard’s pseudonyms in relation to each other––any particular pseudonym’s writing is self-consistent. The internal conflict of Either/Or gives rise to dialogical relationships between its fictional authors. As mentioned above, Author A and Author B represent a tension between the aesthetic and the ethical. Author B is a judge whose writings are largely clinically written moral condemnations of the amoral, existential, and emotional writings of Author A, who claims to be a poet. he two authors’ writings support worldviews which are in tension with one another. Kierkegaard’s different “stages of experience” (namely the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal Currie Volume 14 Issue 1 Winter 2019 3 stages) operate with a similarly crucial tension: the aesthetic is always in conflict with the ethical as the ethical is always in conflict with the religious. The distinctions between these stages, however, are not entirely rigid as they inhere in one another to varying degrees. The tension of the three stages gives rise to two liminal stages: The ironic stage arises between the tension of the aesthetic and the ethical, and the comedic stage arises between the ethical and the religious. One does not solely occupy distinct stages at distinct times but rather bleeds between them and often occupies various stages simultaneously. Thus, like Pascal’s conception of the contradictory, selfdeceiving self, Kierkegaard presents a self in contradiction with itself, a self which can occupy and experience stages of experience which are at odds with one another. Kierkegaard seems to have intended the whole of Either/Or to act as an extensive thought experiment. It places the different authors’ writings in tension with one another and refuses to resolve the tension, inviting engaged readers to reconcile the views in tension and seek their own conclusion. Given the structure of the text, Kierkegaard shows himself as a contradictory self by occupying these different stages through the pseudonyms. This calls into question the degree to which Kierkegaard himself embodies each of the authors of the text and, furthermore, which authors originated from his own genuine experience and which, though still originating from him, are the product of ingenious artifice. Around the time he was writing Either/Or and had a falling out with the love of his life, Regine, he declared that the aesthetic was ultimately his “element.” In a letter to his friend Boesen, he said, “This matter [between Regine and I] ... has two sides, an ethical and an aesthetic... The aesthetic is above all my element. As soon as the ethical asserts itself, it easily gains power over me. I become a quite different person, I know no bounds for what my duties may be, et cetera” (Garff, 205). With this in mind, one approaches Either/Or differently, particularly Author A’s aesthetic writings. Of A’s writings, the Diapsalmata are perhaps the most affecting and devastating. The work is a brief collection of disordered aphorisms, which are pithy statements that exist somewhere between the concision of an axiom or maxim and the evocative immediacy of a poem. Kierkegaard could not have created the aphorisms in the Diapsalmata solely through artifice––these aphorisms must have come from lived experience. With this initial impression of the work and the fact that Kierkegaard himself, at least around the time of Either/Or’s genesis, claimed he favored the aesthetic above all else, one can say with some confidence that the Diapsalmata is more or less directly from Kierkegaard himself, masked by the pseudonym attached to it and a product of the pseudonym which gives way to the very expression of his experiences. A pseudonym both obscures and makes clear. From here it would be best to interrogate the relationship between the aphorisms in the work and begin to develop a philosophy of emotions. The moods of the Diapsalmata oscillate from bored to ecstatic; from melancholic to comedic; from nihilistic to life-affirming. The contradictory nature of the work initially confuses the reader. Author A himself occasionally thematizes contradiction in the Diapsalmata. In one instance, A says, “There are, as is known, insects that die in the moment of fertilization. So, it is with all joy: life’s highest, most splendid moment of enjoyment is accompanied by death” (Kierkegaard, 20). Here the highest experiences in life are met with their contrary, if taken literally. This may also be taken metaphorically. One does not usually die after experiencing the enjoyment A alludes to, but Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal Currie Volume 14 Issue 1 Winter 2019 4 perhaps one feels as though one had died in the fallout of this moment of ","PeriodicalId":338305,"journal":{"name":"Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal","volume":"90 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"A Monstrous Philosophy of Emotions\",\"authors\":\"L. Currie\",\"doi\":\"10.5399/UO/OURJ.14.1.2\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Through an analysis of Søren Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata from the first volume of Either/Or, a work which exhibits strikingly contemporary ways of thinking, this paper seeks to uncover the complex and paradoxical ways in which emotions inhabit a person. The urge to explicate the complexity of emotions arose from the author’s dissatisfaction with the rudimentary schematic used in daily life wherein emotions are categorized and hastily rationalized, misconstruing their greater complexity. Emotions are often irrational, contradictory, etc., and must be considered on those terms. Thus, concession of paradox is vital in order to think through contradictory states of emotions. An aphorism from Pascal states that we are nothing but “lies, duplicity, and contradiction.” With this idea in mind, the essay proceeds to argue that the use of pseudonyms to create contradictions within Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata show the Diapsalmata functioning as a “monstrous” philosophy of emotions. What is meant by “monstrous” differs from the colloquial use of the term and the essay’s particular usage is discussed with reference to Socrates and Typhon in Plato’s Phaedrus. The paper claims that Kierkegaard's thought as a whole is “monstrous” in the dissonance of the religious, comedic, ethical, ironic, and aesthetic stages he constructs in his broader philosophy. The monstrous philosophy of emotions developed from the Diapsalmata is argued to have a “prefatory weight” on the question of Being, i.e. “why are there beings instead of nothing?” The way in which different emotions preface this question is briefly discussed. The conclusion emphasizes the importance of understanding the complexity of emotions philosophically. “Talk about humility gives occasion for pride to the proud and humility to the humble. Similarly, skeptical arguments allow the positive to be positive. Few speak humbly of humility, chastely of chastity, dubiously of skepticism. We are nothing but lies, duplicity, contradiction, and we hide and disguise ourselves from ourselves” (Pascal, 240). Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal Currie Volume 14 Issue 1 Winter 2019 2 Despite the radical tone of Pascal’s claim that we solely consist of “lies, duplicity, and contradiction,” his hyperbolic insistence that we are nothing but is a poetic device indicating his claim should not be taken literally. One might then dismiss this as one of Pascal’s characteristically gloomy formulations and deem it unworthy of being taken seriously. Yet to do this would evade the very real force of his claim: to what degree do I disguise myself from myself? Am I merely a sum of contradictions masquerading as a quasi-coherent self? Is not the self which I present to the world ever-changing, duplicitous, multiplicitous? Is not this self, too, a fiction? One created out of an inability to account for my contradictions? The range of questions which erupt from Pascal’s aphorism must be circumscribed if one wishes to attain anything like an answer to them. One way in which we most overtly contradict ourselves is in and through our emotions. Such contradictions are monstrous insofar as the self which experiences these contradictory emotions is a whole self-made of discordant parts, namely differing emotional states, rather than a whole comprised of harmonious, non-contradictory parts. Pascal addresses the issue of a contradictory self succinctly in his aphorism while Søren Kierkegaard “performs” it in his Diapsalmata and in his works in general. This preliminary reflection inspired by Pascal’s aphorism leads me to consider Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata as a monstrous philosophy of emotions. Before addressing the relationship between the different moods which appear in the Diapsalmata, I shall provide some context for that work. The authorship of Kierkegaard's Either/Or is obfuscated by pseudonyms. Either/Or is, as discussed in its preface by Victor Eremita, Kierkegaard’s first pseudonym, a collection of essays, letters, and fragments from two authors whom Eremita discovered. He names them A and B, respectively. Author A’s writings are inclined toward the “aesthetic” while Author B is inclined toward the “ethical.” Either/Or is principally a work which attempts to put these two authors and the aesthetic and ethical they represent in dialectical tension. Along with these three pseudonyms, Author A discovers a diary of a man named Johannes, giving us a fourth pseudonym. Eremita embeds this diary within A’s own works, seeing that Johannes’ diary shares a similar aesthetic comportment to A’s own writings and believing Author A and Johannes to be the same person. Yet, of course, all of these authors are just Kierkegaard playing different roles. Through the power of the pseudonym and the obfuscation of authorship, Kierkegaard takes on the roles of a discoverer and editor of unknown works, an aesthetic writer of melancholic poetry and philosophy, a judge who rebuts the aesthetic writer’s stance in favor of the ethical, and so on. While Pascal uses poetic hyperbole to confront man’s contradictions, Kierkegaard textually “performs” these contradictions through the writings of the pseudonyms. These contradictions only begin to show when considering Kierkegaard’s pseudonyms in relation to each other––any particular pseudonym’s writing is self-consistent. The internal conflict of Either/Or gives rise to dialogical relationships between its fictional authors. As mentioned above, Author A and Author B represent a tension between the aesthetic and the ethical. Author B is a judge whose writings are largely clinically written moral condemnations of the amoral, existential, and emotional writings of Author A, who claims to be a poet. he two authors’ writings support worldviews which are in tension with one another. Kierkegaard’s different “stages of experience” (namely the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal Currie Volume 14 Issue 1 Winter 2019 3 stages) operate with a similarly crucial tension: the aesthetic is always in conflict with the ethical as the ethical is always in conflict with the religious. The distinctions between these stages, however, are not entirely rigid as they inhere in one another to varying degrees. The tension of the three stages gives rise to two liminal stages: The ironic stage arises between the tension of the aesthetic and the ethical, and the comedic stage arises between the ethical and the religious. One does not solely occupy distinct stages at distinct times but rather bleeds between them and often occupies various stages simultaneously. Thus, like Pascal’s conception of the contradictory, selfdeceiving self, Kierkegaard presents a self in contradiction with itself, a self which can occupy and experience stages of experience which are at odds with one another. Kierkegaard seems to have intended the whole of Either/Or to act as an extensive thought experiment. It places the different authors’ writings in tension with one another and refuses to resolve the tension, inviting engaged readers to reconcile the views in tension and seek their own conclusion. Given the structure of the text, Kierkegaard shows himself as a contradictory self by occupying these different stages through the pseudonyms. This calls into question the degree to which Kierkegaard himself embodies each of the authors of the text and, furthermore, which authors originated from his own genuine experience and which, though still originating from him, are the product of ingenious artifice. Around the time he was writing Either/Or and had a falling out with the love of his life, Regine, he declared that the aesthetic was ultimately his “element.” In a letter to his friend Boesen, he said, “This matter [between Regine and I] ... has two sides, an ethical and an aesthetic... The aesthetic is above all my element. As soon as the ethical asserts itself, it easily gains power over me. I become a quite different person, I know no bounds for what my duties may be, et cetera” (Garff, 205). With this in mind, one approaches Either/Or differently, particularly Author A’s aesthetic writings. Of A’s writings, the Diapsalmata are perhaps the most affecting and devastating. The work is a brief collection of disordered aphorisms, which are pithy statements that exist somewhere between the concision of an axiom or maxim and the evocative immediacy of a poem. Kierkegaard could not have created the aphorisms in the Diapsalmata solely through artifice––these aphorisms must have come from lived experience. With this initial impression of the work and the fact that Kierkegaard himself, at least around the time of Either/Or’s genesis, claimed he favored the aesthetic above all else, one can say with some confidence that the Diapsalmata is more or less directly from Kierkegaard himself, masked by the pseudonym attached to it and a product of the pseudonym which gives way to the very expression of his experiences. A pseudonym both obscures and makes clear. From here it would be best to interrogate the relationship between the aphorisms in the work and begin to develop a philosophy of emotions. The moods of the Diapsalmata oscillate from bored to ecstatic; from melancholic to comedic; from nihilistic to life-affirming. The contradictory nature of the work initially confuses the reader. Author A himself occasionally thematizes contradiction in the Diapsalmata. In one instance, A says, “There are, as is known, insects that die in the moment of fertilization. So, it is with all joy: life’s highest, most splendid moment of enjoyment is accompanied by death” (Kierkegaard, 20). Here the highest experiences in life are met with their contrary, if taken literally. This may also be taken metaphorically. One does not usually die after experiencing the enjoyment A alludes to, but Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal Currie Volume 14 Issue 1 Winter 2019 4 perhaps one feels as though one had died in the fallout of this moment of \",\"PeriodicalId\":338305,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal\",\"volume\":\"90 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"1900-01-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.5399/UO/OURJ.14.1.2\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5399/UO/OURJ.14.1.2","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

通过笔名的力量和作者身份的模糊,克尔凯郭尔扮演了未知作品的发现者和编辑者、忧郁诗歌和哲学的美学作家、反驳美学作家支持伦理立场的法官等角色。当帕斯卡用诗意的夸张来面对人的矛盾时,克尔凯郭尔通过笔名的写作在文本上“表演”了这些矛盾。只有在考虑克尔凯郭尔的笔名之间的关系时,这些矛盾才开始显现出来——任何特定笔名的写作都是自洽的。非此即彼的内在冲突导致了小说作者之间的对话关系。如上所述,作者A和作者B代表了审美和伦理之间的紧张关系。作者B是一名法官,他的作品主要是对自称诗人的作者a的非道德、存在主义和情感作品进行客观的道德谴责。这两位作家的作品所支持的世界观是相互矛盾的。克尔凯郭尔的不同“经验阶段”(即美学、伦理和宗教俄勒冈大学本科生研究杂志Currie第14卷第1期2019年冬季3个阶段)以类似的关键张力运作:美学总是与伦理冲突,因为伦理总是与宗教冲突。然而,这些阶段之间的区别并不是完全严格的,因为它们在不同程度上彼此存在着。这三个阶段的张力产生了两个阈限阶段:反讽阶段出现在审美与伦理的张力之间,喜剧阶段出现在伦理与宗教的张力之间。一个人不只是在不同的时间占据不同的阶段,而是在它们之间流血,经常同时占据不同的阶段。因此,就像帕斯卡关于矛盾的、自欺欺人的自我的概念一样,克尔凯郭尔呈现了一个与自身矛盾的自我,一个可以占据并经历彼此不一致的经验阶段的自我。克尔凯郭尔似乎有意将《非此即彼》作为一个广泛的思想实验。它将不同作者的作品置于彼此之间的紧张关系中,并拒绝解决这种紧张关系,而是邀请读者在紧张关系中调和观点,并寻求自己的结论。鉴于文本的结构,克尔凯郭尔通过笔名占据了这些不同的阶段,显示了自己是一个矛盾的自我。这让人质疑克尔凯郭尔自己在多大程度上体现了文本的每个作者,此外,哪些作者源于他自己的真实经验,哪些作者虽然仍然源于他,但却是巧妙技巧的产物。大约在他写《非此即彼》和他一生的挚爱雷吉娜闹翻的时候,他宣称美学最终是他的“元素”。在给他的朋友Boesen的一封信中,他说:“这件事(雷金和我之间的)……有两个方面,一个是伦理的,一个是审美的……美学是我最喜欢的元素。一旦道德主张自己,它就很容易对我产生影响。我变成了一个完全不同的人,我不知道我的职责是什么,等等”(Garff, 205)。考虑到这一点,人们会以不同的方式对待非此即彼,尤其是作者A的美学作品。在A的作品中,Diapsalmata可能是最感人和最具破坏性的。这部作品是一本杂乱无章的格言的简短合集,这些格言是存在于公理或格言的简洁和诗歌的唤起性的直接之间的精练陈述。克尔凯郭尔不可能仅仅通过技巧创造出《Diapsalmata》中的格言——这些格言一定来自生活经验。有了对这部作品的最初印象以及克尔凯郭尔自己的事实,至少在《非此即彼》的起源时期,声称他更喜欢美学高于一切,人们可以有信心地说,《Diapsalmata》或多或少直接来自克尔凯郭尔自己,被附在它上面的假名所掩盖,假名的产物,让位于他的经历的表达。假名既模糊又清晰。从这里开始,最好是探究作品中警句之间的关系,并开始发展一种情感哲学。迪帕萨玛塔的情绪在无聊和狂喜之间摇摆;从忧郁到喜剧;从虚无主义到肯定生命。这部作品的矛盾性质最初使读者感到困惑。作者A本人偶尔也会把《失联》中的矛盾主题化。在一个例子中,A说:“众所周知,有些昆虫在受精的那一刻就死了。因此,所有的快乐都是如此:生命中最崇高、最辉煌的享受时刻伴随着死亡”(克尔凯郭尔,20)。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
A Monstrous Philosophy of Emotions
Through an analysis of Søren Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata from the first volume of Either/Or, a work which exhibits strikingly contemporary ways of thinking, this paper seeks to uncover the complex and paradoxical ways in which emotions inhabit a person. The urge to explicate the complexity of emotions arose from the author’s dissatisfaction with the rudimentary schematic used in daily life wherein emotions are categorized and hastily rationalized, misconstruing their greater complexity. Emotions are often irrational, contradictory, etc., and must be considered on those terms. Thus, concession of paradox is vital in order to think through contradictory states of emotions. An aphorism from Pascal states that we are nothing but “lies, duplicity, and contradiction.” With this idea in mind, the essay proceeds to argue that the use of pseudonyms to create contradictions within Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata show the Diapsalmata functioning as a “monstrous” philosophy of emotions. What is meant by “monstrous” differs from the colloquial use of the term and the essay’s particular usage is discussed with reference to Socrates and Typhon in Plato’s Phaedrus. The paper claims that Kierkegaard's thought as a whole is “monstrous” in the dissonance of the religious, comedic, ethical, ironic, and aesthetic stages he constructs in his broader philosophy. The monstrous philosophy of emotions developed from the Diapsalmata is argued to have a “prefatory weight” on the question of Being, i.e. “why are there beings instead of nothing?” The way in which different emotions preface this question is briefly discussed. The conclusion emphasizes the importance of understanding the complexity of emotions philosophically. “Talk about humility gives occasion for pride to the proud and humility to the humble. Similarly, skeptical arguments allow the positive to be positive. Few speak humbly of humility, chastely of chastity, dubiously of skepticism. We are nothing but lies, duplicity, contradiction, and we hide and disguise ourselves from ourselves” (Pascal, 240). Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal Currie Volume 14 Issue 1 Winter 2019 2 Despite the radical tone of Pascal’s claim that we solely consist of “lies, duplicity, and contradiction,” his hyperbolic insistence that we are nothing but is a poetic device indicating his claim should not be taken literally. One might then dismiss this as one of Pascal’s characteristically gloomy formulations and deem it unworthy of being taken seriously. Yet to do this would evade the very real force of his claim: to what degree do I disguise myself from myself? Am I merely a sum of contradictions masquerading as a quasi-coherent self? Is not the self which I present to the world ever-changing, duplicitous, multiplicitous? Is not this self, too, a fiction? One created out of an inability to account for my contradictions? The range of questions which erupt from Pascal’s aphorism must be circumscribed if one wishes to attain anything like an answer to them. One way in which we most overtly contradict ourselves is in and through our emotions. Such contradictions are monstrous insofar as the self which experiences these contradictory emotions is a whole self-made of discordant parts, namely differing emotional states, rather than a whole comprised of harmonious, non-contradictory parts. Pascal addresses the issue of a contradictory self succinctly in his aphorism while Søren Kierkegaard “performs” it in his Diapsalmata and in his works in general. This preliminary reflection inspired by Pascal’s aphorism leads me to consider Kierkegaard’s Diapsalmata as a monstrous philosophy of emotions. Before addressing the relationship between the different moods which appear in the Diapsalmata, I shall provide some context for that work. The authorship of Kierkegaard's Either/Or is obfuscated by pseudonyms. Either/Or is, as discussed in its preface by Victor Eremita, Kierkegaard’s first pseudonym, a collection of essays, letters, and fragments from two authors whom Eremita discovered. He names them A and B, respectively. Author A’s writings are inclined toward the “aesthetic” while Author B is inclined toward the “ethical.” Either/Or is principally a work which attempts to put these two authors and the aesthetic and ethical they represent in dialectical tension. Along with these three pseudonyms, Author A discovers a diary of a man named Johannes, giving us a fourth pseudonym. Eremita embeds this diary within A’s own works, seeing that Johannes’ diary shares a similar aesthetic comportment to A’s own writings and believing Author A and Johannes to be the same person. Yet, of course, all of these authors are just Kierkegaard playing different roles. Through the power of the pseudonym and the obfuscation of authorship, Kierkegaard takes on the roles of a discoverer and editor of unknown works, an aesthetic writer of melancholic poetry and philosophy, a judge who rebuts the aesthetic writer’s stance in favor of the ethical, and so on. While Pascal uses poetic hyperbole to confront man’s contradictions, Kierkegaard textually “performs” these contradictions through the writings of the pseudonyms. These contradictions only begin to show when considering Kierkegaard’s pseudonyms in relation to each other––any particular pseudonym’s writing is self-consistent. The internal conflict of Either/Or gives rise to dialogical relationships between its fictional authors. As mentioned above, Author A and Author B represent a tension between the aesthetic and the ethical. Author B is a judge whose writings are largely clinically written moral condemnations of the amoral, existential, and emotional writings of Author A, who claims to be a poet. he two authors’ writings support worldviews which are in tension with one another. Kierkegaard’s different “stages of experience” (namely the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal Currie Volume 14 Issue 1 Winter 2019 3 stages) operate with a similarly crucial tension: the aesthetic is always in conflict with the ethical as the ethical is always in conflict with the religious. The distinctions between these stages, however, are not entirely rigid as they inhere in one another to varying degrees. The tension of the three stages gives rise to two liminal stages: The ironic stage arises between the tension of the aesthetic and the ethical, and the comedic stage arises between the ethical and the religious. One does not solely occupy distinct stages at distinct times but rather bleeds between them and often occupies various stages simultaneously. Thus, like Pascal’s conception of the contradictory, selfdeceiving self, Kierkegaard presents a self in contradiction with itself, a self which can occupy and experience stages of experience which are at odds with one another. Kierkegaard seems to have intended the whole of Either/Or to act as an extensive thought experiment. It places the different authors’ writings in tension with one another and refuses to resolve the tension, inviting engaged readers to reconcile the views in tension and seek their own conclusion. Given the structure of the text, Kierkegaard shows himself as a contradictory self by occupying these different stages through the pseudonyms. This calls into question the degree to which Kierkegaard himself embodies each of the authors of the text and, furthermore, which authors originated from his own genuine experience and which, though still originating from him, are the product of ingenious artifice. Around the time he was writing Either/Or and had a falling out with the love of his life, Regine, he declared that the aesthetic was ultimately his “element.” In a letter to his friend Boesen, he said, “This matter [between Regine and I] ... has two sides, an ethical and an aesthetic... The aesthetic is above all my element. As soon as the ethical asserts itself, it easily gains power over me. I become a quite different person, I know no bounds for what my duties may be, et cetera” (Garff, 205). With this in mind, one approaches Either/Or differently, particularly Author A’s aesthetic writings. Of A’s writings, the Diapsalmata are perhaps the most affecting and devastating. The work is a brief collection of disordered aphorisms, which are pithy statements that exist somewhere between the concision of an axiom or maxim and the evocative immediacy of a poem. Kierkegaard could not have created the aphorisms in the Diapsalmata solely through artifice––these aphorisms must have come from lived experience. With this initial impression of the work and the fact that Kierkegaard himself, at least around the time of Either/Or’s genesis, claimed he favored the aesthetic above all else, one can say with some confidence that the Diapsalmata is more or less directly from Kierkegaard himself, masked by the pseudonym attached to it and a product of the pseudonym which gives way to the very expression of his experiences. A pseudonym both obscures and makes clear. From here it would be best to interrogate the relationship between the aphorisms in the work and begin to develop a philosophy of emotions. The moods of the Diapsalmata oscillate from bored to ecstatic; from melancholic to comedic; from nihilistic to life-affirming. The contradictory nature of the work initially confuses the reader. Author A himself occasionally thematizes contradiction in the Diapsalmata. In one instance, A says, “There are, as is known, insects that die in the moment of fertilization. So, it is with all joy: life’s highest, most splendid moment of enjoyment is accompanied by death” (Kierkegaard, 20). Here the highest experiences in life are met with their contrary, if taken literally. This may also be taken metaphorically. One does not usually die after experiencing the enjoyment A alludes to, but Oregon Undergraduate Research Journal Currie Volume 14 Issue 1 Winter 2019 4 perhaps one feels as though one had died in the fallout of this moment of
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信