谁能只见树木不见森林?从依赖解析文本中提取多词负极性项

F. Richter, Fabienne Fritzinger, Marion Weller
{"title":"谁能只见树木不见森林?从依赖解析文本中提取多词负极性项","authors":"F. Richter, Fabienne Fritzinger, Marion Weller","doi":"10.21248/jlcl.25.2010.130","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Ever since the groundbreaking work by Fauconnier (1975) and Ladusaw (1980), research on negative polarity items (npis) has been dominated by two fundamental assumptions about the licensing contexts of npis and their inherent semantic-pragmatic properties. The contexts in which npis may occur felicitously are said to have the semantic property of being downward entailing (which we will briefly explain below), and the elements themselves are often said to be located at the end of a pragmatically motivated scale, typically signalling a minimal amount, a smallest size, or similar concept. While the Ladusaw-Fauconnier theory has been substantially refined over time, and while there are very diverse variations on how the technical details of the theory are spelled out, its core insights are currently widely accepted and remain a point of reference for practically any ‘formal’ theory of npis. Some theories are syntactic in nature and formulate the relevant scope constraints relative to (possibly quite abstract) syntactic configurations, others are semantic and define hierarchies of negations of varying strength, and yet another group of theories is predominantly pragmatic, relying heavily on scalar implicatures, domain widening, and related concepts. There are, of course, also approaches in which syntax, semantics, and pragmatics all play a role. Overall, the number of papers and books that have been published on the subject of npis over the last 40 years is nothing short of intimidating.1 Given the sheer volume of the npi literature, it is all the more surprising and striking that much of the discussion revolves around a very small set of items. Especially some of the most sophisticated and influential papers, such as Kadmon and Landman (1993), Krifka (1995), and Chierchia (2006), discuss hardly more than a handful of items, and some studies almost exclusively focus on one, viz. English any, which can be regarded as the classical example for a minimizer, with its variants anything, anyone, anybody, anywhere, etc. Since with any one of the most prominent items of interest is a minimizer, investigations into the significance of this particular property for the entire class of npis have turned into a dominating topic and occasionally even push aside the observation that being a minimizer is not a necessary (nor a sufficient) property of npis. As a result of its narrow empirical focus, the tendency to build a very comprehensive theory on an extremely small, carefully chosen but deeply researched set of examples is characteristic for large parts of the literature on npis. This might mean that only a fraction of the properties and behavior of npis are treated in current theories.","PeriodicalId":402489,"journal":{"name":"J. Lang. Technol. Comput. Linguistics","volume":"62 3 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2010-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"4","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Who Can See the Forest for the Trees? Extracting Multiword Negative Polarity Items from Dependency-Parsed Text\",\"authors\":\"F. Richter, Fabienne Fritzinger, Marion Weller\",\"doi\":\"10.21248/jlcl.25.2010.130\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Ever since the groundbreaking work by Fauconnier (1975) and Ladusaw (1980), research on negative polarity items (npis) has been dominated by two fundamental assumptions about the licensing contexts of npis and their inherent semantic-pragmatic properties. The contexts in which npis may occur felicitously are said to have the semantic property of being downward entailing (which we will briefly explain below), and the elements themselves are often said to be located at the end of a pragmatically motivated scale, typically signalling a minimal amount, a smallest size, or similar concept. While the Ladusaw-Fauconnier theory has been substantially refined over time, and while there are very diverse variations on how the technical details of the theory are spelled out, its core insights are currently widely accepted and remain a point of reference for practically any ‘formal’ theory of npis. Some theories are syntactic in nature and formulate the relevant scope constraints relative to (possibly quite abstract) syntactic configurations, others are semantic and define hierarchies of negations of varying strength, and yet another group of theories is predominantly pragmatic, relying heavily on scalar implicatures, domain widening, and related concepts. There are, of course, also approaches in which syntax, semantics, and pragmatics all play a role. Overall, the number of papers and books that have been published on the subject of npis over the last 40 years is nothing short of intimidating.1 Given the sheer volume of the npi literature, it is all the more surprising and striking that much of the discussion revolves around a very small set of items. Especially some of the most sophisticated and influential papers, such as Kadmon and Landman (1993), Krifka (1995), and Chierchia (2006), discuss hardly more than a handful of items, and some studies almost exclusively focus on one, viz. English any, which can be regarded as the classical example for a minimizer, with its variants anything, anyone, anybody, anywhere, etc. Since with any one of the most prominent items of interest is a minimizer, investigations into the significance of this particular property for the entire class of npis have turned into a dominating topic and occasionally even push aside the observation that being a minimizer is not a necessary (nor a sufficient) property of npis. As a result of its narrow empirical focus, the tendency to build a very comprehensive theory on an extremely small, carefully chosen but deeply researched set of examples is characteristic for large parts of the literature on npis. This might mean that only a fraction of the properties and behavior of npis are treated in current theories.\",\"PeriodicalId\":402489,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"J. Lang. Technol. Comput. Linguistics\",\"volume\":\"62 3 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2010-07-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"4\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"J. Lang. Technol. Comput. Linguistics\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.21248/jlcl.25.2010.130\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"J. Lang. Technol. Comput. Linguistics","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.21248/jlcl.25.2010.130","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4

摘要

自从Fauconnier(1975)和Ladusaw(1980)的开创性工作以来,对负极性条目的研究一直被关于负极性条目的许可语境及其固有的语义-语用特性的两个基本假设所主导。npi可能恰当出现的上下文被认为具有向下延伸的语义属性(我们将在下面简要解释),并且这些元素本身通常被认为位于语用动机尺度的末端,通常表示最小的量,最小的尺寸或类似的概念。虽然Ladusaw-Fauconnier理论随着时间的推移已经得到了很大的改进,虽然在如何阐述该理论的技术细节方面存在着非常不同的变化,但其核心见解目前被广泛接受,并且仍然是几乎任何“正式”npi理论的参考点。一些理论本质上是句法的,并制定了相对于(可能相当抽象的)句法配置的相关范围约束,其他理论是语义的,并定义了不同强度的否定层次结构,还有一组理论主要是实用的,严重依赖于标量含义、领域扩展和相关概念。当然,也有语法、语义和语用学都起作用的方法。总的来说,在过去的40年里,关于npis主题的论文和书籍的出版数量简直令人生畏考虑到npi文献的绝对数量,更令人惊讶和引人注目的是,大部分讨论都围绕着非常小的一组项目。尤其是一些最复杂和最有影响力的论文,如Kadmon和Landman (1993), Krifka(1995)和Chierchia(2006),几乎只讨论了几个项目,有些研究几乎只关注一个,即English any,它可以被视为最小化的经典例子,它的变体是anything, anyone, anyone, anywhere等。由于任何一个最引人注目的项目都是最小化器,因此对这一特定属性对整个npi类的重要性的调查已经成为一个主导话题,偶尔甚至会把最小化器不是npi必要(也不是充分)属性的观察推到一边。由于其狭隘的经验焦点,倾向于在极小的,精心选择但深入研究的一组例子上建立一个非常全面的理论,这是大部分关于npi的文献的特点。这可能意味着,在目前的理论中,只有一小部分npi的性质和行为得到了处理。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Who Can See the Forest for the Trees? Extracting Multiword Negative Polarity Items from Dependency-Parsed Text
Ever since the groundbreaking work by Fauconnier (1975) and Ladusaw (1980), research on negative polarity items (npis) has been dominated by two fundamental assumptions about the licensing contexts of npis and their inherent semantic-pragmatic properties. The contexts in which npis may occur felicitously are said to have the semantic property of being downward entailing (which we will briefly explain below), and the elements themselves are often said to be located at the end of a pragmatically motivated scale, typically signalling a minimal amount, a smallest size, or similar concept. While the Ladusaw-Fauconnier theory has been substantially refined over time, and while there are very diverse variations on how the technical details of the theory are spelled out, its core insights are currently widely accepted and remain a point of reference for practically any ‘formal’ theory of npis. Some theories are syntactic in nature and formulate the relevant scope constraints relative to (possibly quite abstract) syntactic configurations, others are semantic and define hierarchies of negations of varying strength, and yet another group of theories is predominantly pragmatic, relying heavily on scalar implicatures, domain widening, and related concepts. There are, of course, also approaches in which syntax, semantics, and pragmatics all play a role. Overall, the number of papers and books that have been published on the subject of npis over the last 40 years is nothing short of intimidating.1 Given the sheer volume of the npi literature, it is all the more surprising and striking that much of the discussion revolves around a very small set of items. Especially some of the most sophisticated and influential papers, such as Kadmon and Landman (1993), Krifka (1995), and Chierchia (2006), discuss hardly more than a handful of items, and some studies almost exclusively focus on one, viz. English any, which can be regarded as the classical example for a minimizer, with its variants anything, anyone, anybody, anywhere, etc. Since with any one of the most prominent items of interest is a minimizer, investigations into the significance of this particular property for the entire class of npis have turned into a dominating topic and occasionally even push aside the observation that being a minimizer is not a necessary (nor a sufficient) property of npis. As a result of its narrow empirical focus, the tendency to build a very comprehensive theory on an extremely small, carefully chosen but deeply researched set of examples is characteristic for large parts of the literature on npis. This might mean that only a fraction of the properties and behavior of npis are treated in current theories.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信