{"title":"Patrick J. O'Sullivan:《经济方法论与选择自由》,伦敦:Allen & Unwin, 1987,第17页,265","authors":"L. Boland","doi":"10.1017/S1042771600005834","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This book opens with a Forward by Mark Blaug. The book is about \"a critical philosophically based approach to the methodology of science guided by the regulative criterion of truth\" (p. 3). As a case study, O'SuUivan applies his approach to economics (Chapters 5-11). However, the book is more generally about the \"methodology of human science\" This review will focus primarily on the case-study. The main idea that O'SuUivan wishes economists to understand is that there is a difference between \"objectivist-behaviorist\" methodology based on mechanical-causal explanations of human behavior and what he calls the \"subjectivist-interpretive\" approach with its related teleological mode of explanation. He argues extensively that mainstream economists (i.e. neoclassical economists) are always caught in a contradiction between \"precept\" and \"practice\". Specifically, economists think they are engaged in the mechanical-causal mode of explanation that is usually associated with the physical sciences. In practice mainstream economists always rely on some form of the assumption that individual decision makers are optimizing. Not only is this assumption a subjective matter of interpreting the actions of other individuals but it is also teleological (involving the goals of the individual decision maker). O'SuUivan seems to think that these two approaches to methodology and explanation are unambiguously contradictory. He reviews the practice and methodological preaching of Milton Friedman, Paul Samuelson and Richard Lipsey as well as the long-forgotten methodological views of John Stuart Mill, Alfred Marshall and John Maynard Keynes. Everyone of these famous leading economists practice some form of subjectivist-interpretive teleological explanatory methodology while advocating an objectivist-behaviorist methodology. The only economists recognized for not being caught in such an alleged contradiction are the Austrians who consistently practice the subjectivist-interpretive approach to economic methodology. By comparing Austrian and mainstream economics from the perspective of the subjectivist-interpretive methodology O'SuUivan is certainly raising an important question for modern historians of economic thought. If both Austrians and mainstream economists practice the subjectivist-interpretive approach to economic methodology, why have Austrian economists had so little impact on mainstream economics? (Hayek is probably an exception but nobody seems to know why.) Unfortunately, O'SuUivan does not provide a clear answer to this question. Nevertheless, the evidence he presents in his case study is worthy of consideration.","PeriodicalId":123974,"journal":{"name":"History of Economics Society Bulletin","volume":"53 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"1989-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Patrick J. O'Sullivan, Economic Methodology and Freedom to Choose, London: Allen & Unwin, 1987, Pp. xvii, 265\",\"authors\":\"L. Boland\",\"doi\":\"10.1017/S1042771600005834\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"This book opens with a Forward by Mark Blaug. The book is about \\\"a critical philosophically based approach to the methodology of science guided by the regulative criterion of truth\\\" (p. 3). As a case study, O'SuUivan applies his approach to economics (Chapters 5-11). However, the book is more generally about the \\\"methodology of human science\\\" This review will focus primarily on the case-study. The main idea that O'SuUivan wishes economists to understand is that there is a difference between \\\"objectivist-behaviorist\\\" methodology based on mechanical-causal explanations of human behavior and what he calls the \\\"subjectivist-interpretive\\\" approach with its related teleological mode of explanation. He argues extensively that mainstream economists (i.e. neoclassical economists) are always caught in a contradiction between \\\"precept\\\" and \\\"practice\\\". Specifically, economists think they are engaged in the mechanical-causal mode of explanation that is usually associated with the physical sciences. In practice mainstream economists always rely on some form of the assumption that individual decision makers are optimizing. Not only is this assumption a subjective matter of interpreting the actions of other individuals but it is also teleological (involving the goals of the individual decision maker). O'SuUivan seems to think that these two approaches to methodology and explanation are unambiguously contradictory. He reviews the practice and methodological preaching of Milton Friedman, Paul Samuelson and Richard Lipsey as well as the long-forgotten methodological views of John Stuart Mill, Alfred Marshall and John Maynard Keynes. Everyone of these famous leading economists practice some form of subjectivist-interpretive teleological explanatory methodology while advocating an objectivist-behaviorist methodology. The only economists recognized for not being caught in such an alleged contradiction are the Austrians who consistently practice the subjectivist-interpretive approach to economic methodology. By comparing Austrian and mainstream economics from the perspective of the subjectivist-interpretive methodology O'SuUivan is certainly raising an important question for modern historians of economic thought. If both Austrians and mainstream economists practice the subjectivist-interpretive approach to economic methodology, why have Austrian economists had so little impact on mainstream economics? (Hayek is probably an exception but nobody seems to know why.) Unfortunately, O'SuUivan does not provide a clear answer to this question. Nevertheless, the evidence he presents in his case study is worthy of consideration.\",\"PeriodicalId\":123974,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"History of Economics Society Bulletin\",\"volume\":\"53 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"1989-03-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"History of Economics Society Bulletin\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1042771600005834\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"History of Economics Society Bulletin","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1042771600005834","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
摘要
这本书以马克·布劳格的《未来》开篇。这本书是关于“以真理的规范标准为指导,以批判哲学为基础的科学方法论”(第3页)。作为一个案例研究,O'SuUivan将他的方法应用于经济学(第5-11章)。然而,这本书更一般地是关于“人文科学的方法论”,这篇评论将主要集中在个案研究。O'SuUivan希望经济学家理解的主要观点是,基于对人类行为的机械因果解释的“客观主义-行为主义”方法与他所称的“主观主义-解释”方法及其相关的目的论解释模式之间存在差异。他广泛地论述了主流经济学家(即新古典经济学家)总是陷入“戒律”与“实践”的矛盾之中。具体来说,经济学家认为他们从事的是通常与物理科学相关的机械因果解释模式。在实践中,主流经济学家总是依赖于某种形式的假设,即个体决策者是最优的。这种假设不仅是解释其他个体行为的主观问题,而且也是目的论的(涉及个体决策者的目标)。O'SuUivan似乎认为这两种方法和解释是明确矛盾的。他回顾了米尔顿·弗里德曼(Milton Friedman)、保罗·萨缪尔森(Paul Samuelson)和理查德·利普西(Richard Lipsey)的实践和方法论说教,以及约翰·斯图尔特·穆勒(John Stuart Mill)、阿尔弗雷德·马歇尔(Alfred Marshall)和约翰·梅纳德·凯恩斯(John Maynard Keynes)被遗忘已久的方法论观点。这些著名的经济学家在倡导客观主义-行为主义方法论的同时,都在实践某种形式的主观主义-解释目的论解释方法论。唯一被认为没有陷入这种所谓矛盾的经济学家是奥地利学派的经济学家,他们一贯采用主观主义解释方法来研究经济方法论。通过从主观主义解释方法论的角度比较奥地利学派和主流经济学,奥苏万无疑为现代经济思想史提出了一个重要的问题。如果奥地利学派和主流经济学家都在经济学方法论上采用主观主义解释方法,为什么奥地利学派经济学家对主流经济学的影响如此之小?(哈耶克可能是个例外,但似乎没人知道原因。)不幸的是,奥苏文并没有对这个问题给出一个明确的答案。然而,他在案例研究中提出的证据值得考虑。
Patrick J. O'Sullivan, Economic Methodology and Freedom to Choose, London: Allen & Unwin, 1987, Pp. xvii, 265
This book opens with a Forward by Mark Blaug. The book is about "a critical philosophically based approach to the methodology of science guided by the regulative criterion of truth" (p. 3). As a case study, O'SuUivan applies his approach to economics (Chapters 5-11). However, the book is more generally about the "methodology of human science" This review will focus primarily on the case-study. The main idea that O'SuUivan wishes economists to understand is that there is a difference between "objectivist-behaviorist" methodology based on mechanical-causal explanations of human behavior and what he calls the "subjectivist-interpretive" approach with its related teleological mode of explanation. He argues extensively that mainstream economists (i.e. neoclassical economists) are always caught in a contradiction between "precept" and "practice". Specifically, economists think they are engaged in the mechanical-causal mode of explanation that is usually associated with the physical sciences. In practice mainstream economists always rely on some form of the assumption that individual decision makers are optimizing. Not only is this assumption a subjective matter of interpreting the actions of other individuals but it is also teleological (involving the goals of the individual decision maker). O'SuUivan seems to think that these two approaches to methodology and explanation are unambiguously contradictory. He reviews the practice and methodological preaching of Milton Friedman, Paul Samuelson and Richard Lipsey as well as the long-forgotten methodological views of John Stuart Mill, Alfred Marshall and John Maynard Keynes. Everyone of these famous leading economists practice some form of subjectivist-interpretive teleological explanatory methodology while advocating an objectivist-behaviorist methodology. The only economists recognized for not being caught in such an alleged contradiction are the Austrians who consistently practice the subjectivist-interpretive approach to economic methodology. By comparing Austrian and mainstream economics from the perspective of the subjectivist-interpretive methodology O'SuUivan is certainly raising an important question for modern historians of economic thought. If both Austrians and mainstream economists practice the subjectivist-interpretive approach to economic methodology, why have Austrian economists had so little impact on mainstream economics? (Hayek is probably an exception but nobody seems to know why.) Unfortunately, O'SuUivan does not provide a clear answer to this question. Nevertheless, the evidence he presents in his case study is worthy of consideration.