{"title":"替代制裁道路上的错误转向:对羞辱性惩罚和恢复性司法未来的思考","authors":"Dan Markel","doi":"10.4324/9781315243290-15","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Recently Yale Law School Professor Dan Kahan admitted that, at least with respect to his prior endorsement of shaming punishments, the time has come to recant. Known inside and outside the legal academy for his decade-long defense of shaming as an alternative to incarceration, Kahan took pains to publicly repudiate his earlier embrace of shaming punishments at a symposium convened by the Texas Law Review. True to form, Kahan recanted in style. Rather than simply capitulate to his critics' arguments about the purported inefficiency or injustice of shaming punishments, Kahan explained that he had anticipated and addressed those challenges in his earlier work. Instead, Kahan identified what was really wrong with shaming sanctions: they suffer from a problem of partisanship. In other words, when shaming punishments are deployed, they signal that society has chosen sides with those who elevate community values or hierarchy over individuality and equality. Such partisanship is flawed, for Kahan, because it undermines the acceptability of shaming as an alternative to incarceration. In other words, shaming punishments flout what Kahan calls the principle of expressive overdetermination. A law or policy is expressively overdetermined when it bears meanings sufficiently rich in nature and large in number to enable diverse cultural groups to find simultaneously affirmation of their values within it. Because of the social meaning handicap under which shaming labored, Kahan predicted that shaming punishments cannot ultimate provide a viable alternative to imprisonment because they are too socially divisive. Changing course, Kahan instead argued that we should expand efforts to implement restorative justice programs as a pragmatic alternative to incarceration because such programs do satisfy the criterion of expressive overdetermination and at the same time would help expand our punitive arsenal beyond our orthodox reliance on mass incarceration. In other words, restorative justice has a real hope of achieving political acceptability as an alternative to incarceration. Kahan's renunciation of shaming punishments and subsequent endorsement of restorative justice are significant developments, at least among those of us who study and teach about the institutions and practices of punishment. Although I applaud Kahan's volte-face on shaming punishments - I was one of the critics who argued shaming was both illiberal and incompatible with principles of retributive justice - I think his new arguments are also unsuccessful, though for different reasons. This paper unfolds in four parts. Part I provides an overview of the alternative sanctions movement; this Part can be skimmed or ignored by those already familiar with the state of play in this area. The balance of the paper outlines Kahan's views in his recent piece and identifies three problems. First, the basis for Kahan's claim that shaming should be rejected is ultimately best understood as an empirical claim, not a theoretical one, and Kahan adduces little support to sustain the empirical claim that shaming won't secure widespread support. Moreover, even if such support existed, Kahan does not explain why any partisan wrangling over shaming cannot be handled by the institutions of liberal democracy. Second, Kahan's claims against his critics are inaccurate along two important dimensions: first, he mistakenly accuses his critics of status quo bias, and second, he attributes to them truth-insensitive motivations for which there is no evidence. Finally, and most importantly, Kahan's enthusiasm for restorative justice is likely to wane as he realizes that restorative justice, once scrutinized carefully, is prone to manifest the same kind of social meaning handicaps that shaming has experienced. Consequently, Kahan may have to recant - again.","PeriodicalId":348482,"journal":{"name":"Shame Punishment","volume":"4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2006-10-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"7","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Wrong Turns on the Road to Alternative Sanctions: Reflections on the Future of Shaming Punishments and Restorative Justice\",\"authors\":\"Dan Markel\",\"doi\":\"10.4324/9781315243290-15\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Recently Yale Law School Professor Dan Kahan admitted that, at least with respect to his prior endorsement of shaming punishments, the time has come to recant. Known inside and outside the legal academy for his decade-long defense of shaming as an alternative to incarceration, Kahan took pains to publicly repudiate his earlier embrace of shaming punishments at a symposium convened by the Texas Law Review. True to form, Kahan recanted in style. Rather than simply capitulate to his critics' arguments about the purported inefficiency or injustice of shaming punishments, Kahan explained that he had anticipated and addressed those challenges in his earlier work. Instead, Kahan identified what was really wrong with shaming sanctions: they suffer from a problem of partisanship. In other words, when shaming punishments are deployed, they signal that society has chosen sides with those who elevate community values or hierarchy over individuality and equality. Such partisanship is flawed, for Kahan, because it undermines the acceptability of shaming as an alternative to incarceration. In other words, shaming punishments flout what Kahan calls the principle of expressive overdetermination. A law or policy is expressively overdetermined when it bears meanings sufficiently rich in nature and large in number to enable diverse cultural groups to find simultaneously affirmation of their values within it. Because of the social meaning handicap under which shaming labored, Kahan predicted that shaming punishments cannot ultimate provide a viable alternative to imprisonment because they are too socially divisive. Changing course, Kahan instead argued that we should expand efforts to implement restorative justice programs as a pragmatic alternative to incarceration because such programs do satisfy the criterion of expressive overdetermination and at the same time would help expand our punitive arsenal beyond our orthodox reliance on mass incarceration. In other words, restorative justice has a real hope of achieving political acceptability as an alternative to incarceration. Kahan's renunciation of shaming punishments and subsequent endorsement of restorative justice are significant developments, at least among those of us who study and teach about the institutions and practices of punishment. Although I applaud Kahan's volte-face on shaming punishments - I was one of the critics who argued shaming was both illiberal and incompatible with principles of retributive justice - I think his new arguments are also unsuccessful, though for different reasons. This paper unfolds in four parts. Part I provides an overview of the alternative sanctions movement; this Part can be skimmed or ignored by those already familiar with the state of play in this area. The balance of the paper outlines Kahan's views in his recent piece and identifies three problems. First, the basis for Kahan's claim that shaming should be rejected is ultimately best understood as an empirical claim, not a theoretical one, and Kahan adduces little support to sustain the empirical claim that shaming won't secure widespread support. Moreover, even if such support existed, Kahan does not explain why any partisan wrangling over shaming cannot be handled by the institutions of liberal democracy. Second, Kahan's claims against his critics are inaccurate along two important dimensions: first, he mistakenly accuses his critics of status quo bias, and second, he attributes to them truth-insensitive motivations for which there is no evidence. Finally, and most importantly, Kahan's enthusiasm for restorative justice is likely to wane as he realizes that restorative justice, once scrutinized carefully, is prone to manifest the same kind of social meaning handicaps that shaming has experienced. Consequently, Kahan may have to recant - again.\",\"PeriodicalId\":348482,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Shame Punishment\",\"volume\":\"4 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2006-10-19\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"7\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Shame Punishment\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315243290-15\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Shame Punishment","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315243290-15","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
摘要
最近,耶鲁大学法学院教授丹·卡汉承认,至少就他之前支持的羞辱性惩罚而言,现在是时候放弃了。在法律界内外,卡汉因其长达十年的辩护,将羞辱作为监禁的替代方案而闻名,他在《德克萨斯法律评论》(Texas Law Review)召开的一次研讨会上,煞费苦心地公开否认了他早些时候对羞辱惩罚的支持。一如既往,卡汗以自己的风格宣布放弃。而不是简单地屈服于他的批评者的论点,即所谓的效率低下或不公正的羞辱惩罚,卡汉解释说,他在早期的工作中已经预见并解决了这些挑战。相反,卡汉指出了羞辱性制裁的真正问题:它们存在党派偏见问题。换句话说,当实施羞辱性惩罚时,它们表明社会已经选择了那些将社区价值或等级置于个性和平等之上的人。对卡汉来说,这种党派之争是有缺陷的,因为它破坏了羞辱作为监禁替代方案的可接受性。换句话说,羞辱性惩罚蔑视Kahan所说的表达性过度决定原则。当一项法律或政策具有足够丰富的性质和大量的意义,使不同的文化群体能够同时在其中找到对其价值的肯定时,它就是表达性的过度确定。由于羞耻感在社会意义上的障碍,卡汉预测,羞耻感惩罚最终无法提供一种可行的替代监禁的方法,因为它们在社会上太过分裂。改变路线,Kahan认为我们应该扩大实施恢复性司法项目的努力,作为监禁的一种务实的替代方案,因为这些项目确实满足了表达性过度决定的标准,同时也有助于扩大我们的惩罚性武器,超越我们对大规模监禁的传统依赖。换句话说,作为监禁的替代方案,恢复性司法确实有希望获得政治上的接受。卡汉对羞辱性惩罚的放弃以及随后对恢复性司法的支持是一项重大的发展,至少对我们这些研究和教授惩罚制度和实践的人来说是如此。尽管我赞赏卡汉在羞辱性惩罚问题上的大转变——我曾是认为羞辱既不自由又与报应性正义原则不相容的批评者之一——但我认为他的新论点也不成功,尽管原因不同。本文分为四个部分展开。第一部分概述了替代制裁运动;对于那些已经熟悉这一领域的游戏状态的人来说,这一部分可以被略读或忽略。文章的结语概述了Kahan在他最近的文章中的观点,并指出了三个问题。首先,Kahan关于羞耻应该被拒绝的主张的基础最终最好被理解为经验主张,而不是理论主张,并且Kahan几乎没有引用任何支持来支持羞耻不会获得广泛支持的经验主张。此外,即使存在这样的支持,卡汉也没有解释为什么自由民主制度不能处理任何关于羞辱的党派争论。其次,卡汉对批评者的指控在两个重要方面是不准确的:第一,他错误地指责批评者对现状有偏见;第二,他把没有证据的不顾真相的动机归咎于批评者。最后,也是最重要的一点,卡汉对恢复性正义的热情可能会减弱,因为他意识到,一旦被仔细审视,恢复性正义很容易表现出与羞耻经历过的同样的社会意义障碍。因此,卡汉可能不得不再次放弃。
Wrong Turns on the Road to Alternative Sanctions: Reflections on the Future of Shaming Punishments and Restorative Justice
Recently Yale Law School Professor Dan Kahan admitted that, at least with respect to his prior endorsement of shaming punishments, the time has come to recant. Known inside and outside the legal academy for his decade-long defense of shaming as an alternative to incarceration, Kahan took pains to publicly repudiate his earlier embrace of shaming punishments at a symposium convened by the Texas Law Review. True to form, Kahan recanted in style. Rather than simply capitulate to his critics' arguments about the purported inefficiency or injustice of shaming punishments, Kahan explained that he had anticipated and addressed those challenges in his earlier work. Instead, Kahan identified what was really wrong with shaming sanctions: they suffer from a problem of partisanship. In other words, when shaming punishments are deployed, they signal that society has chosen sides with those who elevate community values or hierarchy over individuality and equality. Such partisanship is flawed, for Kahan, because it undermines the acceptability of shaming as an alternative to incarceration. In other words, shaming punishments flout what Kahan calls the principle of expressive overdetermination. A law or policy is expressively overdetermined when it bears meanings sufficiently rich in nature and large in number to enable diverse cultural groups to find simultaneously affirmation of their values within it. Because of the social meaning handicap under which shaming labored, Kahan predicted that shaming punishments cannot ultimate provide a viable alternative to imprisonment because they are too socially divisive. Changing course, Kahan instead argued that we should expand efforts to implement restorative justice programs as a pragmatic alternative to incarceration because such programs do satisfy the criterion of expressive overdetermination and at the same time would help expand our punitive arsenal beyond our orthodox reliance on mass incarceration. In other words, restorative justice has a real hope of achieving political acceptability as an alternative to incarceration. Kahan's renunciation of shaming punishments and subsequent endorsement of restorative justice are significant developments, at least among those of us who study and teach about the institutions and practices of punishment. Although I applaud Kahan's volte-face on shaming punishments - I was one of the critics who argued shaming was both illiberal and incompatible with principles of retributive justice - I think his new arguments are also unsuccessful, though for different reasons. This paper unfolds in four parts. Part I provides an overview of the alternative sanctions movement; this Part can be skimmed or ignored by those already familiar with the state of play in this area. The balance of the paper outlines Kahan's views in his recent piece and identifies three problems. First, the basis for Kahan's claim that shaming should be rejected is ultimately best understood as an empirical claim, not a theoretical one, and Kahan adduces little support to sustain the empirical claim that shaming won't secure widespread support. Moreover, even if such support existed, Kahan does not explain why any partisan wrangling over shaming cannot be handled by the institutions of liberal democracy. Second, Kahan's claims against his critics are inaccurate along two important dimensions: first, he mistakenly accuses his critics of status quo bias, and second, he attributes to them truth-insensitive motivations for which there is no evidence. Finally, and most importantly, Kahan's enthusiasm for restorative justice is likely to wane as he realizes that restorative justice, once scrutinized carefully, is prone to manifest the same kind of social meaning handicaps that shaming has experienced. Consequently, Kahan may have to recant - again.