超越财产征用条款终结的历史?

Joe Tomlinson
{"title":"超越财产征用条款终结的历史?","authors":"Joe Tomlinson","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3450114","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The ruling of the House of Lords in Anisminic was quickly in “every administrative lawyer’s manual” but was not necessarily in their good books. Analysis of the judgment was produced in a steady stream in the years after it was handed down. In keeping with the dominant style of the times, much of this commentary was in the best traditions of technical, doctrinal administrative law, only obliquely connected to normative concerns about constitutional order. Fifty years later, styles of public law scholarship have changed significantly but Anisminic remains relevant and the subject of debate. Also in keeping with the prevailing style of public law, contemporary analysis of ouster clauses frames the core issue as a perpetual, complex conflict between the Rule of Law, Parliamentary Sovereignty, and the separation of powers — and differing conceptions of the nature, status, and relationship of those constitutional principles. For the most part, the debate consists of some scholars critiquing the continued application of the ruling as an affront to Parliamentary Sovereignty and others suggesting it recognises and protects the fundamental character of the Rule of Law. Between these two stances are a spectrum of different views about how these two principles, along with the separation of powers, ought to relate to each other. The contours of the contemporary debate around ouster clauses are very well-known, almost to the extent that the debate around the next ouster clauses case (whenever it may arise) is largely predictable. When this state of affairs is seen in light of the fact that the UK Supreme Court has once again effectively confirmed the Anisminic approach in a recent case, there is almost a sense that we appear to have reached, to coin a phrase, the “end of ouster clause history.” It therefore seems a fitting moment to ask one of the most basic questions that can be posed of any legal principle: does it work? If we assume the broad purpose of Anisminc was to ensure common law control on minimum access to judicial review, does it achieve that end? \n \nThe argument in this paper is that, when placed in the wider context of restrictions on access to judicial review, the Anisminic approach can only make a minimal substantive contribution to ensuring the accessibility of the judicial review process. Other factors, such as the cost risks of bringing a case, exclude far more people from judicial review than ouster clauses. Given this state of affairs, I suggest that those genuinely concerned with access to judicial review, and how it may be protected through law, must now move beyond traditional Anisminc-type arguments and towards considering what the ruling’s underlying philosophy may have to say about other types of restriction.","PeriodicalId":393421,"journal":{"name":"Executive Decision-Making and the Courts","volume":"20 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-09-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Beyond the End of Ouster Clause History?\",\"authors\":\"Joe Tomlinson\",\"doi\":\"10.2139/ssrn.3450114\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"The ruling of the House of Lords in Anisminic was quickly in “every administrative lawyer’s manual” but was not necessarily in their good books. Analysis of the judgment was produced in a steady stream in the years after it was handed down. In keeping with the dominant style of the times, much of this commentary was in the best traditions of technical, doctrinal administrative law, only obliquely connected to normative concerns about constitutional order. Fifty years later, styles of public law scholarship have changed significantly but Anisminic remains relevant and the subject of debate. Also in keeping with the prevailing style of public law, contemporary analysis of ouster clauses frames the core issue as a perpetual, complex conflict between the Rule of Law, Parliamentary Sovereignty, and the separation of powers — and differing conceptions of the nature, status, and relationship of those constitutional principles. For the most part, the debate consists of some scholars critiquing the continued application of the ruling as an affront to Parliamentary Sovereignty and others suggesting it recognises and protects the fundamental character of the Rule of Law. Between these two stances are a spectrum of different views about how these two principles, along with the separation of powers, ought to relate to each other. The contours of the contemporary debate around ouster clauses are very well-known, almost to the extent that the debate around the next ouster clauses case (whenever it may arise) is largely predictable. When this state of affairs is seen in light of the fact that the UK Supreme Court has once again effectively confirmed the Anisminic approach in a recent case, there is almost a sense that we appear to have reached, to coin a phrase, the “end of ouster clause history.” It therefore seems a fitting moment to ask one of the most basic questions that can be posed of any legal principle: does it work? If we assume the broad purpose of Anisminc was to ensure common law control on minimum access to judicial review, does it achieve that end? \\n \\nThe argument in this paper is that, when placed in the wider context of restrictions on access to judicial review, the Anisminic approach can only make a minimal substantive contribution to ensuring the accessibility of the judicial review process. Other factors, such as the cost risks of bringing a case, exclude far more people from judicial review than ouster clauses. Given this state of affairs, I suggest that those genuinely concerned with access to judicial review, and how it may be protected through law, must now move beyond traditional Anisminc-type arguments and towards considering what the ruling’s underlying philosophy may have to say about other types of restriction.\",\"PeriodicalId\":393421,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Executive Decision-Making and the Courts\",\"volume\":\"20 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2019-09-08\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"1\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Executive Decision-Making and the Courts\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3450114\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Executive Decision-Making and the Courts","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3450114","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

摘要

上议院的裁决很快就被写入了“每一个行政律师的手册”,但不一定是他们的好书。对判决书的分析在判决书发布后的几年里不断涌现。为了与当时的主流风格保持一致,这些评注中的大部分都是技术性的、理论性的行政法的最佳传统,只是间接地与对宪法秩序的规范性关注联系在一起。五十年后,公法学术的风格发生了重大变化,但反神主义仍然是相关的和辩论的主题。同样与公法的流行风格保持一致,当代对罢免条款的分析将核心问题定义为法治、议会主权和三权分立之间永恒而复杂的冲突,以及对这些宪法原则的性质、地位和关系的不同概念。在大多数情况下,辩论包括一些学者批评该裁决的继续适用是对议会主权的侮辱,而其他人则认为它承认并保护了法治的基本特征。在这两种立场之间存在着一系列关于这两项原则以及三权分立应该如何相互关联的不同观点。围绕财产侵占条款的当代辩论的轮廓是众所周知的,几乎在某种程度上,围绕下一个财产侵占条款案件的辩论(无论何时出现)在很大程度上是可以预测的。鉴于英国最高法院在最近的一个案件中再次有效地确认了反神主义的做法,当我们看到这种情况时,几乎有一种感觉,我们似乎已经达到了一个短语,“罢免条款历史的终结”。因此,现在似乎是提出任何法律原则都可以提出的最基本问题之一的合适时机:它有效吗?如果我们假设Anisminc的广泛目的是确保普通法对最低限度司法审查的控制,那么它是否达到了这一目的?本文的论点是,当置于限制获得司法审查的更广泛背景下时,反主义方法只能对确保司法审查程序的可及性作出最低限度的实质性贡献。其他因素,如提起诉讼的成本风险,将更多的人排除在司法审查之外,而不是财产剥夺条款。鉴于这种情况,我建议那些真正关心司法审查的机会,以及如何通过法律来保护它的人,现在必须超越传统的反宗教主义式的论点,转而考虑裁决的基本哲学可能对其他类型的限制有何看法。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Beyond the End of Ouster Clause History?
The ruling of the House of Lords in Anisminic was quickly in “every administrative lawyer’s manual” but was not necessarily in their good books. Analysis of the judgment was produced in a steady stream in the years after it was handed down. In keeping with the dominant style of the times, much of this commentary was in the best traditions of technical, doctrinal administrative law, only obliquely connected to normative concerns about constitutional order. Fifty years later, styles of public law scholarship have changed significantly but Anisminic remains relevant and the subject of debate. Also in keeping with the prevailing style of public law, contemporary analysis of ouster clauses frames the core issue as a perpetual, complex conflict between the Rule of Law, Parliamentary Sovereignty, and the separation of powers — and differing conceptions of the nature, status, and relationship of those constitutional principles. For the most part, the debate consists of some scholars critiquing the continued application of the ruling as an affront to Parliamentary Sovereignty and others suggesting it recognises and protects the fundamental character of the Rule of Law. Between these two stances are a spectrum of different views about how these two principles, along with the separation of powers, ought to relate to each other. The contours of the contemporary debate around ouster clauses are very well-known, almost to the extent that the debate around the next ouster clauses case (whenever it may arise) is largely predictable. When this state of affairs is seen in light of the fact that the UK Supreme Court has once again effectively confirmed the Anisminic approach in a recent case, there is almost a sense that we appear to have reached, to coin a phrase, the “end of ouster clause history.” It therefore seems a fitting moment to ask one of the most basic questions that can be posed of any legal principle: does it work? If we assume the broad purpose of Anisminc was to ensure common law control on minimum access to judicial review, does it achieve that end? The argument in this paper is that, when placed in the wider context of restrictions on access to judicial review, the Anisminic approach can only make a minimal substantive contribution to ensuring the accessibility of the judicial review process. Other factors, such as the cost risks of bringing a case, exclude far more people from judicial review than ouster clauses. Given this state of affairs, I suggest that those genuinely concerned with access to judicial review, and how it may be protected through law, must now move beyond traditional Anisminc-type arguments and towards considering what the ruling’s underlying philosophy may have to say about other types of restriction.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信