Horace M. Kallen
{"title":"Ex Nihilo","authors":"Horace M. Kallen","doi":"10.4324/9780367854140-1","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In this paper, I analyze the connections between Plato’s Sophist and Gorgias’ On Not-Being or On Nature. I argue that the Sophist is best construed as a reaction to Gorgias’ oration, based on the dramatic context of the dialogue, hints in other dialogues, and the two works’ parallel argumentative concerns and structures. I further argue that this interpretation undermines some traditional claims about the Sophist, including the thesis that the Sophist marks a major revision or even abandonment of Plato’s earlier views. I then offer my own view that the dialogue is an exercise in intellectual purification, supporting this view with the dramatic elements of the Sophist. This view coheres well with my claim that Plato wrote the dialogue as a refutation of Gorgias and further supports my claims about developmental interpretations of the Sophist. Like many other Platonic dialogues, the Sophist displays a manifest concern for the question of what it means to be a philosopher. The Sophist is unique, however, in containing Plato’s longest sustained inquiry into what the philosopher is not—namely, a sophist. Plato’s portrayal of sophistry is, of course, more than a mere literary device for making the portrait of the philosopher clearer. Plato’s discussion of sophistry throughout the dialogues is intimately connected with the historical phenomenon of sophistry and its intellectual forefathers— particularly Gorgias. In fact, Plato polemically targets Gorgias and his teachings in twelve different dialogues. Given this conspicuous interest in Gorgias’ teachings, it is reasonable to assume that Plato read Gorgias’ widely known attack on Parmenidean philosophy, On Not-Being or On Nature. Therefore, in interpreting the Sophist, which deals extensively with Parmenides’ arguments, it would be prudent to investigate the connections between the philosophical content of the dialogue and Gorgias’ oration. In the following paper, I argue that one of Plato’s chief concerns in the Sophist is the refutation of the arguments found in Gorgias’ On Not-Being. I will first cite evidence in favor of this view, drawing from other dialogues as well as the dramatic elements in the Sophist itself. I will then show how the specific arguments in On Not-Being are both appropriated and addressed in the Sophist. Afterwards, I will show how my view informs 1 An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Steven Humphrey Student Philosophy Colloquium at University of Louisville on November 12, 2010, under the title “Plato contra Gorgias: Gorgias’ On Not-Being and the Philosophical Context of the Sophist.” Another early draft was presented under its current title at the SUNY Oneonta 16 Annual Undergraduate Philosophy Conference, which occurred April 28-30, 2011. 2 For a list of these occurrences, see Scott Consigny, Gorgias: Sophist and Artist (Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press, 2001), 37, and especially 217n. 5. Note that not all of these occurrences explicitly mention Gorgias by name. 3 For a discussion of the popularity of Gorgias’ tract, see Steve Hays, “On the Skeptical Influence of Gorgias’s On Non-Being,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 28 (1990): 327-337 (especially pp. 329-331 and 333-335). Hays points to Isocrates’ casual (but highly critical) allusions to On Not-Being and Aristophanes’ parody of On Not-Being in his Thesmophoriazuse (discussed below) as evidence that it could function as a paradigmatic example of philosophical and skeptical excesses. Hays argues that many Athenians were familiar with even the details of Gorgias’ arguments, to the point that “it seems virtually certain that Plato encountered people... who challenged his views with skeptical arguments learned from [On Not-Being]” (ibid., 335).","PeriodicalId":179691,"journal":{"name":"Creativity, Imagination, Logic","volume":"54 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-11-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"2","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Creativity, Imagination, Logic","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9780367854140-1","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2

摘要

本文分析了柏拉图的《诡辩家》与高尔吉亚的《论不存在》和《论自然》之间的联系。我认为《诡辩家》最好被解释为对戈尔吉亚演讲的反应,基于对话的戏剧性背景,其他对话中的暗示,以及这两部作品平行的争论关注点和结构。我进一步认为,这种解释削弱了关于《诡辩家》的一些传统主张,包括《诡辩家》标志着对柏拉图早期观点的重大修订甚至放弃的论点。然后,我提出了自己的观点,即对话是一种智力净化的练习,并以《诡辩家》的戏剧性元素来支持这一观点。这一观点与我认为柏拉图写《对话录》是为了反驳戈尔吉亚的观点相吻合,并进一步支持了我对《诡辩家》的发展解释的观点。像许多其他柏拉图式对话一样,《诡辩家》对成为哲学家意味着什么这个问题表现出明显的关注。然而,《诡辩家》的独特之处在于,它包含了柏拉图对哲学家不是什么的最长的持续探究——即,一个诡辩家。当然,柏拉图对诡辩的描绘不仅仅是一种文学手段,它使哲学家的形象更加清晰。柏拉图在《对话录》中对诡辩的讨论与诡辩的历史现象及其知识分子祖先——尤其是高尔吉亚——密切相关。事实上,柏拉图在十二篇不同的对话录中,以高尔吉亚和他的教导为辩论对象。鉴于柏拉图对戈尔吉亚的教导有如此明显的兴趣,我们有理由假设柏拉图读过戈尔吉亚对巴门尼德哲学的著名攻击,《论不存在》或《论自然》。因此,在解释《诡辩家》时,它广泛涉及巴门尼德的论点,研究对话的哲学内容与戈尔吉亚的演讲之间的联系将是谨慎的。在下面的文章中,我认为柏拉图在《诡辩家》中的主要关注点之一是反驳戈尔吉亚在《论不存在》中发现的论点。我将首先引用支持这一观点的证据,这些证据来自其他对话以及《智者》本身的戏剧性元素。然后我将展示《论不存在》中的具体论证是如何在《诡辩家》中被挪用和处理的。之后,我将展示我的观点是如何告诉人们的。这篇论文的早期版本于2010年11月12日在路易斯维尔大学举行的史蒂文·汉弗莱学生哲学研讨会上发表,题为“柏拉图与高尔吉亚的对立:高尔吉亚论不存在与诡辩家的哲学背景”。在2011年4月28日至30日举行的纽约州立大学奥内昂塔16届年度本科生哲学会议上,另一份早期草案以目前的标题提交。有关这些事件的列表,请参见斯科特·康尼,戈尔吉亚:诡辩家和艺术家(哥伦比亚,南卡罗来纳州:南卡罗莱纳大学出版社,2001年),第37页,特别是217n页。5. 请注意,并非所有这些事件都明确提到了戈尔吉亚的名字。3关于高尔吉亚小册子的流行程度的讨论,见史蒂夫·海斯,“论高尔吉亚关于非存在的怀疑影响”,哲学史杂志28(1990):327-337(特别是329-331和333-335页)。海斯指出,伊索克拉底在他的《论不存在》(Thesmophoriazuse)中不经意地(但高度批判地)暗示了《论不存在》,阿里斯托芬在《论不存在》(下面讨论)中模仿了《论不存在》,以此作为证据,证明它可以作为哲学和怀疑过度的典范。海斯认为,许多雅典人甚至熟悉戈尔吉亚论证的细节,以至于“柏拉图几乎肯定遇到了……他们用从[论不存在]中学到的怀疑论论点来挑战他的观点”(同上,335)。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Ex Nihilo
In this paper, I analyze the connections between Plato’s Sophist and Gorgias’ On Not-Being or On Nature. I argue that the Sophist is best construed as a reaction to Gorgias’ oration, based on the dramatic context of the dialogue, hints in other dialogues, and the two works’ parallel argumentative concerns and structures. I further argue that this interpretation undermines some traditional claims about the Sophist, including the thesis that the Sophist marks a major revision or even abandonment of Plato’s earlier views. I then offer my own view that the dialogue is an exercise in intellectual purification, supporting this view with the dramatic elements of the Sophist. This view coheres well with my claim that Plato wrote the dialogue as a refutation of Gorgias and further supports my claims about developmental interpretations of the Sophist. Like many other Platonic dialogues, the Sophist displays a manifest concern for the question of what it means to be a philosopher. The Sophist is unique, however, in containing Plato’s longest sustained inquiry into what the philosopher is not—namely, a sophist. Plato’s portrayal of sophistry is, of course, more than a mere literary device for making the portrait of the philosopher clearer. Plato’s discussion of sophistry throughout the dialogues is intimately connected with the historical phenomenon of sophistry and its intellectual forefathers— particularly Gorgias. In fact, Plato polemically targets Gorgias and his teachings in twelve different dialogues. Given this conspicuous interest in Gorgias’ teachings, it is reasonable to assume that Plato read Gorgias’ widely known attack on Parmenidean philosophy, On Not-Being or On Nature. Therefore, in interpreting the Sophist, which deals extensively with Parmenides’ arguments, it would be prudent to investigate the connections between the philosophical content of the dialogue and Gorgias’ oration. In the following paper, I argue that one of Plato’s chief concerns in the Sophist is the refutation of the arguments found in Gorgias’ On Not-Being. I will first cite evidence in favor of this view, drawing from other dialogues as well as the dramatic elements in the Sophist itself. I will then show how the specific arguments in On Not-Being are both appropriated and addressed in the Sophist. Afterwards, I will show how my view informs 1 An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Steven Humphrey Student Philosophy Colloquium at University of Louisville on November 12, 2010, under the title “Plato contra Gorgias: Gorgias’ On Not-Being and the Philosophical Context of the Sophist.” Another early draft was presented under its current title at the SUNY Oneonta 16 Annual Undergraduate Philosophy Conference, which occurred April 28-30, 2011. 2 For a list of these occurrences, see Scott Consigny, Gorgias: Sophist and Artist (Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press, 2001), 37, and especially 217n. 5. Note that not all of these occurrences explicitly mention Gorgias by name. 3 For a discussion of the popularity of Gorgias’ tract, see Steve Hays, “On the Skeptical Influence of Gorgias’s On Non-Being,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 28 (1990): 327-337 (especially pp. 329-331 and 333-335). Hays points to Isocrates’ casual (but highly critical) allusions to On Not-Being and Aristophanes’ parody of On Not-Being in his Thesmophoriazuse (discussed below) as evidence that it could function as a paradigmatic example of philosophical and skeptical excesses. Hays argues that many Athenians were familiar with even the details of Gorgias’ arguments, to the point that “it seems virtually certain that Plato encountered people... who challenged his views with skeptical arguments learned from [On Not-Being]” (ibid., 335).
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信