{"title":"The Sounds of Silence: Reconsidering the Invocation of the Right to Remain Silent Under Miranda","authors":"Mark S. Strauss","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1105472","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In Miranda v. Arizona, the Supreme Court required that prior to any custodial interrogation a suspect must be informed that he has the right to remain silent and the right to an attorney and that no interrogation can occur until the suspect waives these rights. Although these protections seem on first blush to effectively empower a suspect to choose whether to speak to the police, many have deemed Miranda a spectacular failure. There are numerous critics of the Miranda decision and its progeny on a variety of levels, but what has received too little attention is whether the most basic protection of the Miranda decision operates effectively. That is, how can a suspect effectively assert the right to remain silent and do the police appropriately respect such an assertion? This paper attempts to answer that question by considering what constitutes an assertion of the right to remain silent. Although Miranda suggested that if an individual indicates in any manner at any time that he wishes to remain silent, the interrogation must cease, subsequent cases have required a more explicit invocation of the desire not to speak. Relying on Davis v. United States, a Supreme Court decision addressing the invocation of the right to counsel, the bulk of lower courts require that a suspect unambiguously invoke the right to remain silent. Such a transposition of the requirements for asserting the right to counsel with the right to remain silent is wrong as a matter of law, unwise as a matter of policy and threatens to eviscerate the core protection of Miranda. This article argues that the requirement that the right to remain silent be unambiguously asserted is inconsistent with the guarantees of Miranda. The passage of time since Miranda and Davis has revealed one indisputable fact: rarely do suspects invoke their rights. Only 20 per cent initially assert their rights rather than waive them and almost no suspects assert their rights after a valid waiver. While some suspects undoubtedly want to talk to the police, this paper argues that these statistics have a more nefarious explanation: courts have made is extremely difficult for suspects who want to assert their rights to do so. By cataloguing the state and federal cases since Davis that has addressed the right to remain silent, I attempt to demonstrate how the lower courts have gone to extraordinary lengths to classify even seemingly clear invocations as ambiguous statements which can be ignored by the police. As a result, Miranda's promise that suspects freely determine whether and when they wish to submit to custodial interrogation is an empty one.","PeriodicalId":83315,"journal":{"name":"The William and Mary Bill of Rights journal : a student publication of the Marshall-Wythe School of Law","volume":"19 1","pages":"773"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2008-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"5","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The William and Mary Bill of Rights journal : a student publication of the Marshall-Wythe School of Law","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1105472","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Abstract
In Miranda v. Arizona, the Supreme Court required that prior to any custodial interrogation a suspect must be informed that he has the right to remain silent and the right to an attorney and that no interrogation can occur until the suspect waives these rights. Although these protections seem on first blush to effectively empower a suspect to choose whether to speak to the police, many have deemed Miranda a spectacular failure. There are numerous critics of the Miranda decision and its progeny on a variety of levels, but what has received too little attention is whether the most basic protection of the Miranda decision operates effectively. That is, how can a suspect effectively assert the right to remain silent and do the police appropriately respect such an assertion? This paper attempts to answer that question by considering what constitutes an assertion of the right to remain silent. Although Miranda suggested that if an individual indicates in any manner at any time that he wishes to remain silent, the interrogation must cease, subsequent cases have required a more explicit invocation of the desire not to speak. Relying on Davis v. United States, a Supreme Court decision addressing the invocation of the right to counsel, the bulk of lower courts require that a suspect unambiguously invoke the right to remain silent. Such a transposition of the requirements for asserting the right to counsel with the right to remain silent is wrong as a matter of law, unwise as a matter of policy and threatens to eviscerate the core protection of Miranda. This article argues that the requirement that the right to remain silent be unambiguously asserted is inconsistent with the guarantees of Miranda. The passage of time since Miranda and Davis has revealed one indisputable fact: rarely do suspects invoke their rights. Only 20 per cent initially assert their rights rather than waive them and almost no suspects assert their rights after a valid waiver. While some suspects undoubtedly want to talk to the police, this paper argues that these statistics have a more nefarious explanation: courts have made is extremely difficult for suspects who want to assert their rights to do so. By cataloguing the state and federal cases since Davis that has addressed the right to remain silent, I attempt to demonstrate how the lower courts have gone to extraordinary lengths to classify even seemingly clear invocations as ambiguous statements which can be ignored by the police. As a result, Miranda's promise that suspects freely determine whether and when they wish to submit to custodial interrogation is an empty one.
在米兰达诉亚利桑那州案中,最高法院要求,在进行任何拘留讯问之前,必须告知嫌疑人他有权保持沉默,有权聘请律师,在嫌疑人放弃这些权利之前,不得进行讯问。尽管乍一看,这些保护措施似乎有效地赋予了嫌疑人选择是否与警方交谈的权利,但许多人认为米兰达案是一个巨大的失败。对米兰达判决及其后续判决有许多不同层次的批评,但对米兰达判决的最基本保护是否有效运作的关注太少。也就是说,嫌疑人如何有效地维护保持沉默的权利,警察是否适当地尊重这种权利?本文试图通过考虑什么构成保持沉默的权利的主张来回答这个问题。虽然米兰达建议如果一个人在任何时候以任何方式表示他希望保持沉默,审讯必须停止,但随后的案件要求更明确地援引不想说话的愿望。根据最高法院对戴维斯诉美国案(Davis v. United States)的裁决,大多数下级法院都要求嫌疑人明确地援引保持沉默的权利。戴维斯诉美国案涉及请求律师的权利。从法律上讲,这种将辩护权与保持沉默权的要求相违背的做法是错误的,从政策上讲也是不明智的,而且有可能破坏《米兰达》的核心保护。本文认为,保持沉默的权利必须得到明确的主张,这一要求与《米兰达》的保障不一致。自从米兰达和戴维斯案以来,时间的流逝揭示了一个不争的事实:嫌疑人很少行使他们的权利。只有20%的人最初主张自己的权利,而不是放弃这些权利,几乎没有嫌疑人在获得有效的放弃后主张自己的权利。虽然一些嫌疑人无疑想要与警方交谈,但本文认为,这些统计数据有一个更邪恶的解释:法院对那些想要维护自己权利的嫌疑人来说是极其困难的。通过对自戴维斯案以来涉及保持沉默权利的州和联邦案件进行分类,我试图证明下级法院是如何不遗余力地将看似清晰的请求归类为可以被警察忽视的模棱两可的陈述。因此,米兰达关于嫌疑人自由决定是否以及何时愿意接受拘留审讯的承诺是一个空洞的承诺。