The Rhetorical Arts in Late Antique and Early Medieval Ireland by Brian James Stone (review)

IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY
Conor O’Brien
{"title":"The Rhetorical Arts in Late Antique and Early Medieval Ireland by Brian James Stone (review)","authors":"Conor O’Brien","doi":"10.1353/rht.2023.a900077","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Glazebrook overstates the rhetorical and ideological polarisation of prostituted and citizen-status women. She writes that “In oratory, female sex laborers’ associations with citizens disrupt the social fabric, in contrast to citizen kinswomen” (42); the “blame discourse lobbed against [wives and daughters] in Archaic and earlier Classical texts [as “weak links” in the household] is . . . replaced by a discourse of risk centring on the sex laborer” (61). The suggestion of a chronological or generic shift in anxiety or blame away from wives and daughters and onto “sex laborers” does not stand. The accusations made against Alke in Isaios 6, that she has damaged the oikos’s integrity by introducing illegitimate children (with implications for the integrity of genos, phratry, deme, and polis), and exercises undue influence over the oikos by manipulation, are levelled in the same or similar forms against citizen-status women in late Classical forensic speeches: Euphiletus’s wife in Lysias 1; Khrysilla in Andocides 1; arguably Eleios’s wife in the lost counter-argument to Isaios 2. Even in Isaios 6, Euktemon threatens to marry Demokhares’s sister and use her to introduce further illegitimate children. Similarly, Glazebrook’s argument about Neaira culminates in an extended quotation of §§110-111, where Apollodoros asks the jurors how their wives, daughters, and mothers will respond if they say they have acquitted Neaira. Her quotation (80) ends with the imagined fury of the sophronestatai (morally superior) “of the women,” cutting off before Apollodoros warns that acquittal will vindicate the anoētoi (silly, perhaps “susceptible,” [morally] careless). Glazebrook argues that “describing the women with the superlative sōphronestatai . . . differentiates citizen women from Neaira and her daughter”; differential vocabulary “highlights the importance of sexual behaviour to the concept of sōphrosunē and citizenship in this speech”—but Apollodoros’s phrasing allows that jurors may imagine anoētoi among their female kin. When Glazebrook continues the quotation on p. 88, her argument about the wording of the longer passage acknowledges and even relies on imagined anoētoi kin, undermining her earlier reading. Glazebrook explicitly focuses on rhetoric rather than reality: Lysias 4 and Isaios 6, she writes, “offer a rare glimpse into the possible lives of marginal women in the Athenian household and polis” (61)—but she leaves it at that. The book examines “sexual labor” as a rhetorical tool rather than a reality, but the examination is illuminating and useful.","PeriodicalId":40200,"journal":{"name":"Res Rhetorica","volume":"10 2 1","pages":"214 - 216"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Res Rhetorica","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/rht.2023.a900077","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Glazebrook overstates the rhetorical and ideological polarisation of prostituted and citizen-status women. She writes that “In oratory, female sex laborers’ associations with citizens disrupt the social fabric, in contrast to citizen kinswomen” (42); the “blame discourse lobbed against [wives and daughters] in Archaic and earlier Classical texts [as “weak links” in the household] is . . . replaced by a discourse of risk centring on the sex laborer” (61). The suggestion of a chronological or generic shift in anxiety or blame away from wives and daughters and onto “sex laborers” does not stand. The accusations made against Alke in Isaios 6, that she has damaged the oikos’s integrity by introducing illegitimate children (with implications for the integrity of genos, phratry, deme, and polis), and exercises undue influence over the oikos by manipulation, are levelled in the same or similar forms against citizen-status women in late Classical forensic speeches: Euphiletus’s wife in Lysias 1; Khrysilla in Andocides 1; arguably Eleios’s wife in the lost counter-argument to Isaios 2. Even in Isaios 6, Euktemon threatens to marry Demokhares’s sister and use her to introduce further illegitimate children. Similarly, Glazebrook’s argument about Neaira culminates in an extended quotation of §§110-111, where Apollodoros asks the jurors how their wives, daughters, and mothers will respond if they say they have acquitted Neaira. Her quotation (80) ends with the imagined fury of the sophronestatai (morally superior) “of the women,” cutting off before Apollodoros warns that acquittal will vindicate the anoētoi (silly, perhaps “susceptible,” [morally] careless). Glazebrook argues that “describing the women with the superlative sōphronestatai . . . differentiates citizen women from Neaira and her daughter”; differential vocabulary “highlights the importance of sexual behaviour to the concept of sōphrosunē and citizenship in this speech”—but Apollodoros’s phrasing allows that jurors may imagine anoētoi among their female kin. When Glazebrook continues the quotation on p. 88, her argument about the wording of the longer passage acknowledges and even relies on imagined anoētoi kin, undermining her earlier reading. Glazebrook explicitly focuses on rhetoric rather than reality: Lysias 4 and Isaios 6, she writes, “offer a rare glimpse into the possible lives of marginal women in the Athenian household and polis” (61)—but she leaves it at that. The book examines “sexual labor” as a rhetorical tool rather than a reality, but the examination is illuminating and useful.
古代晚期和中世纪早期爱尔兰的修辞艺术布莱恩·詹姆斯·斯通(书评)
格莱泽布鲁克夸大了卖淫妇女和公民地位妇女在修辞和意识形态上的两极分化。她写道:“在演讲中,女性性工作者与公民的联系破坏了社会结构,这与公民的女性亲属形成了对比”(42);“在古代和早期的古典文本中,指责[妻子和女儿]的话语[作为家庭中的“薄弱环节”]是……取而代之的是以性工作者为中心的风险话语”(61)。那种认为焦虑或指责从妻子和女儿身上转移到“性工作者”身上的说法是站不住脚的。在《以赛亚书》第6章中,对阿尔克的指控是,她通过引入私生子(暗示了genos, phratry, deme和polis的完整性)破坏了oikos的完整性,并通过操纵对oikos施加了不当影响,这些指控在古典晚期的法庭演讲中以相同或类似的形式针对公民身份的女性:《吕西亚斯书》第1章中,尤非利托的妻子;菊苣属1;可以说是以利俄的妻子,在《以赛亚书》第二章中。甚至在《以赛亚书》第6章中,Euktemon也威胁要娶Demokhares的妹妹,并利用她来引进更多的私生子。同样,Glazebrook关于Neaira的争论在§110-111的延伸引用中达到高潮,Apollodoros问陪审员,如果他们说他们无罪释放了Neaira,他们的妻子,女儿和母亲会如何回应。她的引言(80)以想象中的“女人们”的愤怒结束,在阿波罗多罗斯警告说无罪释放将证明anoētoi(愚蠢的,也许“易受影响的”,[道德上的]粗心大意)是正确的之前就结束了。格莱泽布鲁克认为,“用最高级的sōphronestatai来描述女性……将公民妇女与Neaira和她的女儿区分开来”;不同的词汇“突出了性行为对sōphrosunē和公民身份概念的重要性”——但阿波罗多罗斯的措辞允许陪审员想象anoētoi在他们的女性亲属中。当格莱泽布鲁克在第88页继续引用这段话时,她对较长段落措辞的争论承认,甚至依赖于想象中的anoētoi亲属,破坏了她之前的阅读。格拉泽布鲁克明确地关注修辞而不是现实:她写道,《吕西亚斯》第4章和《以赛俄斯》第6章“提供了对雅典家庭和城邦中边缘女性可能生活的罕见一瞥”(61)——但她就此止步。这本书把“性劳动”作为一种修辞工具而不是现实来审视,但这种审视很有启发性,也很有用。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
Res Rhetorica
Res Rhetorica HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY-
CiteScore
0.30
自引率
0.00%
发文量
16
审稿时长
12 weeks
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信