The Buridan-Volpin Derivation System; Properties and Justification

Sven Storms
{"title":"The Buridan-Volpin Derivation System; Properties and Justification","authors":"Sven Storms","doi":"10.1017/bsl.2022.35","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Logic is traditionally considered to be a purely syntactic discipline, at least in principle. However, prof. David Isles has shown that this ideal is not yet met in traditional logic. Semantic residue is present in the assumption that the domain of a variable should be fixed in advance of a derivation, and also in the notion that a numerical notation must refer to a number rather than be considered a mathematical object in and of itself. Based on his work, the central question of this thesis is what kind of logic, if any, results from removing this semantic residue from traditional logic. We differ from traditional logic in two significant ways. The first is that the assumption that a numerical notation must refer to a number is denied. Numerical notations are considered as mathematical objects in their own right, related to each other by means of rewrite rules. The traditional notion of reference is then replaced by the notion of reduction (by means of the rewrite rules) to a normal form. Two numerical notations that reduce to the same normal form would traditionally be considered identical, as they would refer to the same number, and hence they would be interchangeable salva veritate. In the new system, called Buridan-Volpin (BV), the numerical notations themselves are the elements of the domains of variables, and two numerical notations that reduce to the same normal form need not be interchangeable salva veritate, except when they are syntactically identical (i.e., have the same Gödel number). The second is that we do away with the assumption that the domains of variables need to be fixed in advance of a derivation. Instead we focus on what is needed to guarantee preservation of truth in every step of a derivation. These conditions on the domains of the variables, accumulated in the course of a derivation, are combined in a reference grammar. Whereas traditionally a derivation is considered valid when the conclusion follows from the premisses by way of the derivation rules (and possibly axioms), in the BV system a derivation must meet the extra condition that no inconsistency occurs within the reference grammar. For if the reference grammar were to give rise to inconsistency (i.e., it would be impossible to assign domains to all the variables without breaking at least one of the conditions placed on them in the reference grammar), there is no longer a guarantee that truth has been preserved in every step of the derivation, and hence the truth of the conclusion is not guaranteed by the derivation. In Chapter 2 the BV system is introduced in some formal detail. Chapter 3 gives some examples of derivations, notably totality of addition, multiplication and exponentiation, as well as a lemma needed for the proof of Euclid’s Theorem. These examples, taken from prof. Isles’ First-Order Reasoning and Primitive Recursive Natural Number Notations, show that there is a real proof-theoretical difference between traditional logic and the BV system. Here we also find the first major point of departure between myself and prof. Isles, centered on the notion of inheritance of conditions in the reference grammar by way of lemmata. These different points of view are best illustrated in the sections on the totality of exponentiation and on Euclid’s Lemma: prof. Isles maintains that the proof of totality of exponentiation is not BV valid, while I maintain that it is. But I do agree with him that the traditional proof of Euclid’s Lemma is not BV valid. Chapter 6 also expands the arguments for my choice in this matter. Now that it has been shown that there is a difference between traditional logic and BV, the properties of BV need to be examined. In Chapter 4 we give a proof of Cut-elimination for BV minus induction and the subformula property for BV, which allows us to prove the consistency of BV minus induction. We also expand on the reasons for excluding induction. In Chapter 5 we consider in detail the proof of a finite analog to the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem given by prof. Isles in his article with the same title. He proves that under certain conditions it is always possible, given the existence of a (possibly uncountable) model for a derivation, to give a finite model for this derivation. The system he considers deviates from BV as considered in this thesis in two significant ways: it does not contain the induction rule and the domains contain numbers instead of numerical notations. We then go on to show that it is possible to extend the result to include induction, in the sense that the existence of a possibly uncountable model for a derivation guarantees the existence of a model that is at most countable. We also consider the complications that arise from taking numerical expressions instead of numbers as the elements of domains. Finally, in Chapter 6 we consider the philosophical consequences of the BV system, informed by the formal results from the previous chapters. In particular we discuss the relation between reduction and reference, the status of reference grammars, the notion of induction and its function within BV, and some brief considerations on the consequences of the BV system for the discussion regarding nominalism and realism with regard to mathematical objects. The object of the chapter is twofold. On the one hand applying the formal results to philosophical questions, on the other hand arguing that BV is not just a theoretically acceptable alternative to traditional logic, but is in fact deserving of further development and research into its properties. The latter will probably appeal most to those of a nominalist and/or finitist bent. Abstract prepared by Harrie de Swart and Sven Storms. E-mail: sven.storms@tilburguniversity.edu URL: https://research.tilburguniversity.edu/files/61701294/Storms_The_ Buridan_Volpin_04_05_2022.pdf","PeriodicalId":22265,"journal":{"name":"The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic","volume":"54 1","pages":"533 - 535"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2022-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/bsl.2022.35","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Abstract Logic is traditionally considered to be a purely syntactic discipline, at least in principle. However, prof. David Isles has shown that this ideal is not yet met in traditional logic. Semantic residue is present in the assumption that the domain of a variable should be fixed in advance of a derivation, and also in the notion that a numerical notation must refer to a number rather than be considered a mathematical object in and of itself. Based on his work, the central question of this thesis is what kind of logic, if any, results from removing this semantic residue from traditional logic. We differ from traditional logic in two significant ways. The first is that the assumption that a numerical notation must refer to a number is denied. Numerical notations are considered as mathematical objects in their own right, related to each other by means of rewrite rules. The traditional notion of reference is then replaced by the notion of reduction (by means of the rewrite rules) to a normal form. Two numerical notations that reduce to the same normal form would traditionally be considered identical, as they would refer to the same number, and hence they would be interchangeable salva veritate. In the new system, called Buridan-Volpin (BV), the numerical notations themselves are the elements of the domains of variables, and two numerical notations that reduce to the same normal form need not be interchangeable salva veritate, except when they are syntactically identical (i.e., have the same Gödel number). The second is that we do away with the assumption that the domains of variables need to be fixed in advance of a derivation. Instead we focus on what is needed to guarantee preservation of truth in every step of a derivation. These conditions on the domains of the variables, accumulated in the course of a derivation, are combined in a reference grammar. Whereas traditionally a derivation is considered valid when the conclusion follows from the premisses by way of the derivation rules (and possibly axioms), in the BV system a derivation must meet the extra condition that no inconsistency occurs within the reference grammar. For if the reference grammar were to give rise to inconsistency (i.e., it would be impossible to assign domains to all the variables without breaking at least one of the conditions placed on them in the reference grammar), there is no longer a guarantee that truth has been preserved in every step of the derivation, and hence the truth of the conclusion is not guaranteed by the derivation. In Chapter 2 the BV system is introduced in some formal detail. Chapter 3 gives some examples of derivations, notably totality of addition, multiplication and exponentiation, as well as a lemma needed for the proof of Euclid’s Theorem. These examples, taken from prof. Isles’ First-Order Reasoning and Primitive Recursive Natural Number Notations, show that there is a real proof-theoretical difference between traditional logic and the BV system. Here we also find the first major point of departure between myself and prof. Isles, centered on the notion of inheritance of conditions in the reference grammar by way of lemmata. These different points of view are best illustrated in the sections on the totality of exponentiation and on Euclid’s Lemma: prof. Isles maintains that the proof of totality of exponentiation is not BV valid, while I maintain that it is. But I do agree with him that the traditional proof of Euclid’s Lemma is not BV valid. Chapter 6 also expands the arguments for my choice in this matter. Now that it has been shown that there is a difference between traditional logic and BV, the properties of BV need to be examined. In Chapter 4 we give a proof of Cut-elimination for BV minus induction and the subformula property for BV, which allows us to prove the consistency of BV minus induction. We also expand on the reasons for excluding induction. In Chapter 5 we consider in detail the proof of a finite analog to the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem given by prof. Isles in his article with the same title. He proves that under certain conditions it is always possible, given the existence of a (possibly uncountable) model for a derivation, to give a finite model for this derivation. The system he considers deviates from BV as considered in this thesis in two significant ways: it does not contain the induction rule and the domains contain numbers instead of numerical notations. We then go on to show that it is possible to extend the result to include induction, in the sense that the existence of a possibly uncountable model for a derivation guarantees the existence of a model that is at most countable. We also consider the complications that arise from taking numerical expressions instead of numbers as the elements of domains. Finally, in Chapter 6 we consider the philosophical consequences of the BV system, informed by the formal results from the previous chapters. In particular we discuss the relation between reduction and reference, the status of reference grammars, the notion of induction and its function within BV, and some brief considerations on the consequences of the BV system for the discussion regarding nominalism and realism with regard to mathematical objects. The object of the chapter is twofold. On the one hand applying the formal results to philosophical questions, on the other hand arguing that BV is not just a theoretically acceptable alternative to traditional logic, but is in fact deserving of further development and research into its properties. The latter will probably appeal most to those of a nominalist and/or finitist bent. Abstract prepared by Harrie de Swart and Sven Storms. E-mail: sven.storms@tilburguniversity.edu URL: https://research.tilburguniversity.edu/files/61701294/Storms_The_ Buridan_Volpin_04_05_2022.pdf
布里丹-沃尔平衍生系统;属性和论证
逻辑传统上被认为是一门纯粹的语法学科,至少在原则上是这样。然而,David Isles教授已经证明,这种理想在传统逻辑中尚未得到满足。语义残馀存在于变量的定义域应该在推导之前确定的假设中,也存在于数字符号必须指向数字而不是将其本身视为数学对象的概念中。基于他的工作,本论文的中心问题是,如果有的话,从传统逻辑中去除这种语义残余会产生什么样的逻辑。我们与传统逻辑在两个重要方面有所不同。首先,否定了数字符号必须指向数字的假设。数字符号被认为是独立的数学对象,通过重写规则相互关联。然后,传统的引用概念被还原概念(通过重写规则)取代为标准形式。两个简化为相同标准形式的数字符号通常被认为是相同的,因为它们指的是相同的数字,因此它们可以互换。在称为Buridan-Volpin (BV)的新系统中,数值符号本身是变量域的元素,两个简化为相同范式的数值符号不需要互换salva veritate,除非它们在语法上相同(即具有相同的Gödel数字)。第二,我们不再假设变量的定义域需要在求导之前确定。相反,我们关注的是在推导的每一步中需要什么来保证真理的保存。在派生过程中积累的变量域上的这些条件组合在一个参考语法中。传统上,当结论通过推导规则(也可能是公理)从前提推导出来时,推导被认为是有效的,而在BV系统中,推导必须满足参考语法中不存在不一致的额外条件。因为,如果参考语法引起了不一致(即不可能在不违反参考语法中规定的至少一个条件的情况下给所有的变量指定域),那么就不能保证在推导的每一步中都保留了真理,因此推导就不能保证结论的真实性。第二章详细介绍了BV系统。第三章给出了一些推导的例子,特别是加法、乘法和幂的总和,以及证明欧几里得定理所需要的一个引理。这些例子摘自Isles教授的一阶推理和原始递归自然数符号,表明传统逻辑和BV系统之间存在着真正的证明理论差异。在这里,我们还发现了我和艾尔斯教授之间的第一个主要出发点,集中在参考语法中通过引理继承条件的概念上。这些不同的观点在关于乘数总和和欧几里得引理的章节中得到了最好的说明:艾尔斯教授坚持认为乘数总和的证明是不完全有效的,而我坚持认为它是有效的。但我同意他的观点,传统的欧几里得引理证明是不完全有效的。第六章也扩展了我在这个问题上选择的理由。既然已经证明了传统逻辑和BV之间存在差异,那么就需要对BV的性质进行检验。第四章给出了BV负归纳法的切消证明和BV的子公式性质,从而证明了BV负归纳法的一致性。我们还扩展了排除归纳的原因。在第五章中,我们详细考虑了Isles教授在他的同名文章中给出的Löwenheim-Skolem定理的有限类比的证明。他证明了在一定条件下,给定一个推导的(可能不可数的)模型的存在,总是有可能给出这个推导的有限模型。他所考虑的系统在两个重要方面偏离了本文所考虑的BV:它不包含归纳规则和域包含数字而不是数字符号。然后我们继续证明可以将结果扩展到包括归纳法,在某种意义上,一个推导的可能不可数模型的存在保证了一个模型的存在,这个模型最多是可数的。我们还考虑了采用数值表达式而不是数字作为域元素所引起的复杂性。最后,在第6章中,我们根据前几章的形式结果考虑了BV系统的哲学结果。 我们特别讨论了还原和指称的关系,指称语法的地位,归纳的概念及其在BV中的作用,并简要地考虑了关于数学对象的唯名论和实在论的讨论的BV系统的结果。本章的目的是双重的。一方面将形式结果应用于哲学问题,另一方面论证了逻辑逻辑不仅是传统逻辑的一种理论上可接受的替代,而且实际上值得进一步发展和研究其性质。后者可能最吸引那些唯名论和/或有限主义倾向。摘要由Harrie de Swart和Sven Storms准备。电子邮件:sven.storms@tilburguniversity.edu URL: https://research.tilburguniversity.edu/files/61701294/Storms_The_ Buridan_Volpin_04_05_2022.pdf
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信