Some Thoughts on Law and Economics and the Theory of Second Best

J. Donohue
{"title":"Some Thoughts on Law and Economics and the Theory of Second Best","authors":"J. Donohue","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.168612","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This paper addresses the implications of the Theory of the Second Best for law and economics scholarship. The theory of the second best is at once fascinating and paralyzing. Fascinating because it so powerfully assaults much of modern economic theory; paralyzing in that it does not offer a clear replacement for what is purports to destroy. Dick Markovits, who has done so much to keep this important theory in the minds of law and economics scholars, gives an example that suggests the difficulty: a tort doctrine is implemented which compels manufacturers to pay the cost imposed by their discharge of pollutants into any body of water. At first blush, the policy change seems unambiguously good. Prior to the doctrinal change, manufacturers who dumped noxious chemicals and metals into bodies of water created \"externalities\", social costs that they imposed with impunity. As a result, a manufacturer would maximize profits by discharging pollutants whenever there was even the slightest benefit in so doing. In other words, instead of providing an incentive to promote the public good, the presence of large external costs in a market system encourages undeniably harmful activity. It would seem that eliminating this perverse incentive could only be beneficial, and, at least in the absence of the theory of the second best, this logic would be unassailable. But once the disruptive theory of the second best is introduced, all bets are off unless there happens to be no other distortion in the economy, a most unlikely event. The paper examines a variety of applications of the theory, including a paper by Fullerton and Metcalf that demonstrates that many scholars have been unduly optimistic in asserting that pollution taxes will yield the double dividend of a better environment and more tax revenues with less deadweight loss. In so doing, Fullerton and Metcalf have certainly diminished the prospect, advocated by some, that excess pollution taxes will be imposed to reduce the deadweight loss from distortionate labor taxes. Their paper also shows, however, that, as between the competing policies of the pollution tax or the pollution quota, the former is clearly preferable. Since Fullerton and Metcalf also demonstrate why business strongly prefers the quota to the tax, we may have our own ironic version of the second best in operation here. Three states of the world are plausible: 1) the overtaxation state that Fullerton and Metcalf attack; 2) the precise Pigovian tax rate that they presumably endorse; and 3) the command and control regulation (the undertaxation state) that business so strongly prefers. Since the pressures of special interests have clearly biased policy towards state (3), arguments in favor of position (1) might have corrected the political imbalance, thereby making position (2) more likely. Now that Fullerton and Metcalf have strongly denounced position (1), the counterbalance to the special interest bias towards state (3) is removed, making (3), the admittedly worst of the three outcomes, more likely than (2). This is clearly a frustrating aspect of the theory of the second best, because if the analysis of imperfections extends to political failures, then making truthful claims about the undesirability of certain policies may cause more harm than good. It is not hard to see why most academics shy away from this broad conception of the theory.","PeriodicalId":90732,"journal":{"name":"Stanford technology law review : STLR : an online high-technology law journal from Stanford Law School","volume":"26 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"1998-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"2","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Stanford technology law review : STLR : an online high-technology law journal from Stanford Law School","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.168612","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2

Abstract

This paper addresses the implications of the Theory of the Second Best for law and economics scholarship. The theory of the second best is at once fascinating and paralyzing. Fascinating because it so powerfully assaults much of modern economic theory; paralyzing in that it does not offer a clear replacement for what is purports to destroy. Dick Markovits, who has done so much to keep this important theory in the minds of law and economics scholars, gives an example that suggests the difficulty: a tort doctrine is implemented which compels manufacturers to pay the cost imposed by their discharge of pollutants into any body of water. At first blush, the policy change seems unambiguously good. Prior to the doctrinal change, manufacturers who dumped noxious chemicals and metals into bodies of water created "externalities", social costs that they imposed with impunity. As a result, a manufacturer would maximize profits by discharging pollutants whenever there was even the slightest benefit in so doing. In other words, instead of providing an incentive to promote the public good, the presence of large external costs in a market system encourages undeniably harmful activity. It would seem that eliminating this perverse incentive could only be beneficial, and, at least in the absence of the theory of the second best, this logic would be unassailable. But once the disruptive theory of the second best is introduced, all bets are off unless there happens to be no other distortion in the economy, a most unlikely event. The paper examines a variety of applications of the theory, including a paper by Fullerton and Metcalf that demonstrates that many scholars have been unduly optimistic in asserting that pollution taxes will yield the double dividend of a better environment and more tax revenues with less deadweight loss. In so doing, Fullerton and Metcalf have certainly diminished the prospect, advocated by some, that excess pollution taxes will be imposed to reduce the deadweight loss from distortionate labor taxes. Their paper also shows, however, that, as between the competing policies of the pollution tax or the pollution quota, the former is clearly preferable. Since Fullerton and Metcalf also demonstrate why business strongly prefers the quota to the tax, we may have our own ironic version of the second best in operation here. Three states of the world are plausible: 1) the overtaxation state that Fullerton and Metcalf attack; 2) the precise Pigovian tax rate that they presumably endorse; and 3) the command and control regulation (the undertaxation state) that business so strongly prefers. Since the pressures of special interests have clearly biased policy towards state (3), arguments in favor of position (1) might have corrected the political imbalance, thereby making position (2) more likely. Now that Fullerton and Metcalf have strongly denounced position (1), the counterbalance to the special interest bias towards state (3) is removed, making (3), the admittedly worst of the three outcomes, more likely than (2). This is clearly a frustrating aspect of the theory of the second best, because if the analysis of imperfections extends to political failures, then making truthful claims about the undesirability of certain policies may cause more harm than good. It is not hard to see why most academics shy away from this broad conception of the theory.
关于法律经济学与次优理论的几点思考
本文论述了次优理论对法律和经济学学术的影响。第二好的理论既迷人又令人麻痹。它之所以引人入胜,是因为它如此有力地攻击了许多现代经济理论;瘫痪的原因在于,它没有提供一个明确的替代品来取代它所声称要摧毁的东西。迪克·马科维茨(Dick Markovits)为使这一重要理论在法律和经济学者的脑海中留下深刻印象做了大量工作,他举了一个例子来说明其中的困难:一种侵权原则的实施迫使制造商支付因向任何水体排放污染物而产生的成本。乍一看,政策变化似乎毫无疑问是好的。在教义改变之前,向水体中倾倒有毒化学物质和金属的制造商制造了“外部性”,即他们不受惩罚地强加的社会成本。因此,制造商会通过排放污染物来最大化利润,即使这样做有一点点好处。换句话说,市场体系中存在的巨额外部成本并没有提供促进公共利益的激励,反而鼓励了无可否认的有害活动。消除这种不正当的激励似乎只会是有益的,而且,至少在没有次优理论的情况下,这种逻辑将是无懈可击的。但是,一旦引入了次优的颠覆性理论,所有的赌注都被取消了,除非碰巧经济中没有其他扭曲,这是最不可能发生的事情。这篇论文考察了该理论的各种应用,包括富勒顿和梅特卡夫的一篇论文,该论文表明,许多学者过于乐观地断言,污染税将带来更好的环境和更多的税收收入以及更少的无谓损失的双重红利。富勒顿和梅特卡夫这样做,无疑削弱了一些人提倡的前景,即征收过多的污染税,以减少扭曲的劳动税带来的无谓损失。然而,他们的论文也表明,在污染税和污染配额这两个相互竞争的政策之间,前者显然更可取。由于富勒顿和梅特卡夫也证明了为什么企业强烈倾向于配额而不是税收,我们可能在这里有我们自己的第二好的讽刺版本。世界上有三种状态是合理的:1)富勒顿和梅特卡夫攻击的税收过重的国家;2)他们可能支持的精确的庇古税率;3)企业非常喜欢的命令和控制监管(税收不足的国家)。由于特殊利益集团的压力使政策明显偏向于国家(3),支持立场(1)的论点可能已经纠正了政治失衡,从而使立场(2)更有可能。既然富勒顿和梅特卡夫已经强烈谴责了立场(1),那么对国家特殊利益偏见(3)的平衡就被消除了,使得(3)——三种结果中公认最坏的一种——比(2)更有可能出现。这显然是次优理论令人沮丧的一面,因为如果对不完美的分析延伸到政治失败上,那么对某些政策的不可取做出真实的声明可能会造成更多的伤害而不是好处。不难看出为什么大多数学者回避这一广义的理论概念。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信