A Defense of Pluralist Egalitarianism under Severe Uncertainty: Axiomatic Characterization*

IF 2.9 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS
Akira Inoue, Kaname Miyagishima
{"title":"A Defense of Pluralist Egalitarianism under Severe Uncertainty: Axiomatic Characterization*","authors":"Akira Inoue,&nbsp;Kaname Miyagishima","doi":"10.1111/jopp.12276","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Severe uncertainty plays a critical role in many problems of distributive justice, such as social security, public health, public projects, budget deficits, and climate change. Under severe uncertainty, available information does not allow us to assign precise probabilities to possible states of affairs. A recent example of severe uncertainty is the impact of COVID-19. How policy-makers should evaluate different distributions of well-being in such a situation of severe uncertainty is of vital importance to society. Indeed, the COVID-19 pandemic has induced a need to ration medical resources, such as vaccines, using relevant principles of distribution. Such principles have been hotly debated by egalitarians, many of whom are pluralists.1 This article addresses the problem of the distribution of well-being by using an axiomatic approach to pluralist egalitarianism.</p><p>Rowe and Voorhoeve’s view can be interpreted as an axiomatic approach to pluralist egalitarianism; it helps to clarify competing claims of a relevant kind and thereby enables policy-makers to evaluate uncertain social situations. They illustrate this by showing how RV pluralist egalitarianism works in particular examples.</p><p>There is a need to articulate the axioms involved more explicitly, however, as well as to analyze more rigorously whether and to what extent those axioms are compatible with each other. Furthermore, to assess and choose between competing claims, it would be useful to have a criterion for social evaluation that satisfies the relevant axioms and that orders all possible distributions in a consistent manner. In this article, we introduce axioms of impartiality, efficiency, ex post egalitarianism, and social rationality under severe uncertainty, and address the issue of their compatibility. We then characterize a social evaluation criterion, <i>statewise maximin</i>, by those axioms.3</p><p>Although we focus on cases of severe uncertainty, our results show that axiomatization is invaluable in determining what kind of value pluralism is promising as an egalitarian theory. As Iwao Hirose has argued in a different but related context, pluralist theories are often unclear about how many principles they include and/or to what extent those principles are (in)compatible with each other.4 An axiomatic analysis can address these issues—through axiomatic characterization, we can spell out a normative criterion of pluralist egalitarianism.</p><p>The argument in this article proceeds as follows. Section II presents our basic framework. Section III specifies the principles of egalitarianism, impartiality, and social rationality. Section IV argues that a standard efficiency axiom under uncertainty, <i>ex ante Pareto,</i> is not compelling, and substitutes another axiom, <i>Pareto for equal or no risk</i>. Section V addresses <i>statewise maximin</i> and its axiomatic representation. Section VI presents some brief concluding remarks. The Appendix lays out a formal analysis.</p><p>In this section, we introduce the framework used for our analysis. Following Rowe and Voorhoeve, we use an Ellsberg-type example to epitomize the situation in which decision-makers cannot assign precise probabilities to the possible outcomes of their choice. Suppose that two individuals, Amy and Bob, choose a ball from an urn that contains an unknown number of red and black balls. This represents severe uncertainty. Suppose further that the final distribution of levels of well-being depends on the color of the ball drawn. Thus, the color refers to a state of the world. A social evaluator is expected to compare prospects by appealing to social preferences to evaluate uncertain social situations in terms of their relative desirability.</p><p>Let <math>\n <mi>R</mi></math> be the set of real numbers. <math>\n <mrow>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mo>∈</mo>\n <msup>\n <mi>R</mi>\n <mn>4</mn>\n </msup>\n </mrow></math> denotes a social prospect (or distribution) in question, which is described in Table 1.</p><p>Here, we assume that <math>\n <mrow>\n <mi>i</mi>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mi>A</mi>\n <mo>,</mo>\n <mspace></mspace>\n <mi>B</mi>\n </mrow></math> denotes Amy and Bob, and <math>\n <mrow>\n <mi>s</mi>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mi>r</mi>\n <mo>,</mo>\n <mi>b</mi>\n </mrow></math> denotes the state of the world described by the color of a drawn ball, respectively. <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mi>is</mi>\n </msub></math> represents individual <math>\n <mi>i</mi></math>’s well-being in <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> in state <math>\n <mi>s</mi></math>. For each individual <math>\n <mi>i</mi></math>, <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mfenced>\n <msub>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mi>ir</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>,</mo>\n <mspace></mspace>\n <msub>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mi>ib</mi>\n </msub>\n </mfenced>\n </mrow></math>. Moreover, let <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>r</mi>\n </msub></math> (resp. <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>b</mi>\n </msub></math>) be a final distribution of <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> when a red (resp. black) ball is drawn: that is,</p><p>Well-being levels are represented by real numbers that are fully measurable and ordinally interpersonally comparable.5 We assume that, although individuals do not ex ante know their final well-being levels, a social evaluator precisely estimates the final distributions in each state.</p><p>Each individual <math>\n <mi>i</mi></math> has a function <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>:</mo>\n <msup>\n <mi>R</mi>\n <mn>2</mn>\n </msup>\n <mo>→</mo>\n <mi>R</mi>\n </mrow></math> to evaluate the person’s own uncertain situation. For each <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math> and <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math>, <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mfenced>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n </mfenced>\n <mo>≥</mo>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mfenced>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n </mfenced>\n </mrow></math> means that <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math> is at least as good as <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math> for individual <math>\n <mi>i</mi></math>. <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math> is referred to as individual <math>\n <mi>i</mi></math>’s ex ante utility function. We assume that <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math> is continuous and strictly monotonic: for each <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math> and <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math>, if <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mi>is</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>≥</mo>\n <msub>\n <mi>y</mi>\n <mi>is</mi>\n </msub>\n </mrow></math> for all <math>\n <mi>s</mi></math>, then <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mfenced>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n </mfenced>\n <mo>≥</mo>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mfenced>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n </mfenced>\n </mrow></math>; in addition, if <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mrow>\n <mi>i</mi>\n <msup>\n <mi>s</mi>\n <mo>′</mo>\n </msup>\n </mrow>\n </msub>\n <mo>&gt;</mo>\n <msub>\n <mi>y</mi>\n <mrow>\n <mi>i</mi>\n <msup>\n <mi>s</mi>\n <mo>′</mo>\n </msup>\n </mrow>\n </msub>\n </mrow></math> for some <i>s</i>′, then <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mfenced>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n </mfenced>\n <mo>&gt;</mo>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mfenced>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n </mfenced>\n </mrow></math>. Moreover, for simplicity, we assume that, for <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math> such that <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mi>ir</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <msub>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mi>ib</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mi>x</mi>\n </mrow></math>, <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mfenced>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n </mfenced>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mrow>\n <mo>(</mo>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mo>,</mo>\n <mspace></mspace>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mo>)</mo>\n </mrow>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mi>x</mi>\n </mrow></math>. Although our setting is general, our main results hold even if ex ante utility functions are restricted to particular forms satisfying these conditions.</p><p>Our framework assumes that Amy and Bob may have different ex ante utility functions. A notable example is the case in which they have subjective expected utility functions with different probabilistic beliefs. The occurrence (or even mere possibility) of differences in probabilities like these leads us to address an important problem under severe uncertainty: namely, the problem that Philippe Mongin called “spurious unanimity.”7 As will become evident, this problem affects many cooperative projects, and thus needs to be taken seriously as a fundamental problem for a pluralist egalitarian view.</p><p>There are also problems associated with situations in which the social evaluator has access to more (relevant) information than the individuals. A pandemic is a paradigmatic example of this kind of problem. In situations like these, the evaluator can use her own probabilities based on the relevant information available to her. Although our main results still hold in cases where individuals’ situations are evaluated in terms of the social evaluator’s probabilities, for the sake of generality, we also consider the case in which the social evaluator uses the individuals’ probabilities, such as the problem of public goods provision discussed in Section IV.</p><p>This principle seems intuitively plausible. To see this, compare the following two situations: (1) both Amy and Bob can enjoy a reasonable quality of medical service; (2) Amy can enjoy a very high-quality medical service, while Bob has no access to medical services at all. Suppose that higher-quality medical service leads to higher well-being, because better health resulting from appropriate medical treatment in the high-quality medical service condition improves people’s quality of life. From an egalitarian point of view, it is reasonable to judge (1) to be at least as good as (2).</p><p>It might be objected that ex post egalitarianism is too strong because it requires excessive inequality aversion. Our response to this objection is twofold. First, this axiom can be applied without cardinal interpersonal comparisons of well-being. It is important to note that full cardinal interpersonal comparability is not assumed, but rather obtained as a <i>result</i> of characterizing the maximin criterion. Second, and more importantly, the conflicts between relevant principles of a pluralist egalitarian view revealed below still follow if ex post egalitarianism is replaced with the Pigou−Dalton condition, which is a much weaker principle. According to the Pigou−Dalton principle, the same value <math>\n <mi>t</mi></math> of well-being is “transferred” from the better off to the worse off. Conflicts arise between the Pigou−Dalton principle and other relevant principles, similar to those apparent between ex post egalitarianism and those principles.9 On a related note, we show a different way of expressing statewise maximin by replacing ex post egalitarianism with a weak version of the Pigou−Dalton condition, impartiality, and ordinal full comparability of well-being (see Appendix for details).</p><p>Table 2 illustrates what dominance requires.</p><p>Suppose that the social evaluator supports ex post equality. Then <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>r</mi>\n </msub></math> and <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>b</mi>\n </msub></math> are socially preferred to <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>r</mi>\n </msub></math> and <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>b</mi>\n </msub></math>, respectively. This implies that the final distributions of <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> are socially chosen over those of <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> in all states of the world. Dominance requires that, under this situation, <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> should be chosen over <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> ex ante. If this axiom is violated, society may choose a policy that results in the worse consequence, such as <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> in this example.</p><p>Impartiality is an essential requirement for theories of egalitarian justice. John Rawls emphasized it as the most important premise.10 From impartiality, together with other relevant premises, various key principles can reasonably be derived. They include Rawls’s principle that gives lexical priority to the improvement of the situation of the worst off, which would be unanimously selected by people in a society under the veil of ignorance—that is, by people who have no information about their congenital capacities and social status.</p><p>According to impartiality, these distributions are equally good, which is intuitively appealing. Consequently, we should consider impartiality as a central requirement for a pluralist theory of egalitarian justice.</p><p>Our version of pluralist egalitarianism does <i>not</i> include this principle. This requires some explanation. Ex ante egalitarianism is often considered to be one of the most important principles of pluralist egalitarianism. For example, Richard Arneson argues that the ideal of equality of opportunity for welfare would obtain if and only if all agents “face equivalent decision trees—the expected value of each person’s best (=most prudent) choice of options, second-best … nth-best is the same” in an effective sense, among other things.13 It follows that the less some situation deviates from the ideal, the more desirable it is from an egalitarian perspective. This idea is included in RV pluralist egalitarianism, according to which we should aim to reduce inequality in people’s prospects.</p><p>As stated above, our pluralist egalitarianism does not include ex ante egalitarianism, for three reasons. First, it conflicts with ex post egalitarianism under dominance.14 Consider the case described in Table 3.</p><p>On the one hand, the expected well-beings are more equal in <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math>. On the other hand, because the final well-beings are more equal in <math>\n <mrow>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mo>,</mo>\n </mrow></math> <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> is better according to ex post egalitarianism and dominance. This illustrates a conflict between ex ante egalitarianism and ex post egalitarianism under dominance.</p><p>Second, ex ante egalitarianism is also in conflict with dominance and impartiality, which are intuitive and compelling requirements in egalitarian justice. This conflict can be shown by using an example summarized in Table 4.</p><p>By reflexivity15 and impartiality, <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>r</mi>\n </msub></math> and <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>b</mi>\n </msub></math> are as good as <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>r</mi>\n </msub></math> and <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>Y</mi>\n <mi>b</mi>\n </msub></math>, respectively. Then, dominance implies that <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> is as good as <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> ex ante. However, ex ante egalitarianism claims that <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> is better than <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> ex ante, which comes into conflict with dominance and impartiality. Note that this conflict does not depend on the two people’s probabilities, because we use dominance only.</p><p>It might seem counterintuitive to evaluate <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> and <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> as equally good. However, from the perspective of an impartial evaluator, these distributions could be considered equivalent in the sense that their final distributions of well-being are equally good in each state of the world. This is a reasonable evaluation because, even if the evaluator does not know which state will occur, s/he knows (and thus can evaluate) the final distributions in each state and can combine the evaluations by dominance. This implication supports our focus on distributions of final well-being.16</p><p>Third, it is not clear precisely what equality of ex ante utility means. John Broome’s critique of the notion is relevant here.17 While well-being may be valuable in and of itself, the same is not necessarily true for ex ante utility—the latter is valuable simply because achieving ex ante utility is a way of promoting well-being. Hence, it is merely instrumentally valuable, while equality of final well-being may be inherently valuable; therefore, they are not valuable in the same way. It could still be claimed that ex ante equality can be justified on the basis of the notion of a fair process of choice by randomization: that is, by focusing on fairness. In Table 4, <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> has a fairer distribution of probabilities than <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math>, for example. However, such an argument from fairness cannot justify equality of ex ante utility, because fairness is satisfied by giving fair chances to the satisfaction of all individuals’ equal claims, not by promoting equality of ex ante utility.</p><p>To grasp this, consider the case where we can choose from two courses of action, A and B: A gives one indivisible medicine to either Amy or Bob, two ill persons, by lot, whereas B gives it to either Amy or Bob on the basis of a genealogical investigation into which of the two has the least African ancestry. Even when, as in A, B can equalize their expected utilities, it would be fair to choose A.18 We can conclude, thus, that there is no good reason to include a principle of ex ante egalitarianism that requires equality of ex ante utility.19</p><p>Why is ex ante Pareto so common? It is because it apparently prescribes that a society respect individual evaluations by their own ex ante utility functions.20 Ex ante Pareto could be taken to befit the liberal view of justice—this principle does not require a person to participate in a public insurance scheme if the person prefers not to do so. However, we argue that ex ante Pareto conflicts with the axioms introduced in Section III. We also insist that ex ante Pareto should not appeal to theorists of egalitarian justice, and introduce another Pareto principle that is more compelling under severe uncertainty.21</p><p>First, following Fleurbaey and Voorhoeve,22 we can demonstrate that, under dominance, ex ante Pareto is not compatible with ex post egalitarianism. We assume here that, for each <math>\n <mi>i</mi></math> and each <math>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub></math>, <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>U</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n <mfenced>\n <msub>\n <mi>X</mi>\n <mi>i</mi>\n </msub>\n </mfenced>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mn>0.5</mn>\n <mspace></mspace>\n <mrow>\n <mo>(</mo>\n <msub>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mi>ir</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>+</mo>\n <msub>\n <mi>x</mi>\n <mi>ib</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>)</mo>\n </mrow>\n </mrow></math>. However, conflicts of a similar kind can be obtained in broader sets of beliefs. Consider the following prospects in Table 5.</p><p>Similarly, we can show that under dominance, ex ante Pareto is not compatible with impartiality (Table 6).</p><p>Suppose that all individuals are subjective expected-utility maximizers and that <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>p</mi>\n <mi>Ar</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mn>0.8</mn>\n </mrow></math> and <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>p</mi>\n <mi>Br</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mn>0.2</mn>\n </mrow></math>. By impartiality, the final distributions in both states are indifferent between <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> and <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> and, therefore, <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> and <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> are indifferent ex ante. However, ex ante Pareto claims that <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> is better than <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math>, which shows a conflict with impartiality.</p><p>Given the above conflicts, we give three reasons why ex ante Pareto is not compelling, and will later introduce a weaker efficiency axiom. The first reason concerns the problem of “spurious unanimity” pointed out by Mongin: a unanimous agreement may not be compelling if the individuals reach agreement for different reasons: that is, when individuals have heterogeneous beliefs and distributions have different rankings of final well-being levels between individuals in different states.24</p><p>Mongin gives an example. Consider a plan to build a bridge between two countries, T (a developed country) and L (a developing country). In L, some people expect some economic benefits (for example, benefits from tourism), while others are concerned that they may lose their traditional culture and lifestyle under the influence of T. Suppose that people in L are divided into two groups, A and B. Those in A believe that the benefit is large enough and that their outdated traditions will (and should) be destroyed. Those in B think that the tradition at stake is important, but will not be damaged, because the influence from T will be moderate, and that the bridge will only bring some benefits. This situation is illustrated by Table 7, where if the bridge is constructed in <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math>, the influence from T is large in Red and not in Black. <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> is the distribution when the bridge is not constructed. Suppose that all individuals are subjective expected-utility maximizers and that <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>p</mi>\n <mi>Ar</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mn>0.8</mn>\n </mrow></math> and <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>p</mi>\n <mi>Br</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mn>0.2</mn>\n </mrow></math>. Both groups support the construction of the bridge, although one group is subsequently proved wrong. Such an ex ante agreement is not compelling.</p><p>The second reason is that, under severe uncertainty, it is difficult for individuals to make decisions in an accountable way, because they do not have exact information about the probabilities of the options they are choosing between. Because of this, their final well-being levels would depend on uncertain states. In such a situation, individuals cannot be held fully responsible for their decisions, because they cannot control fortune.25 Moreover, in our environment, individuals may have some heuristics and biases under uncertainty, making it more difficult for them to be responsible for the decisions; they do not have enough capacities to handle uncertain choices.26 These points show that ex ante Pareto is not a compelling principle.</p><p>Those points are also important for egalitarian justice with respect to the so-called “harshness objection” against luck egalitarianism.27 To see this, suppose that Amy did not take out health insurance because of her (overly) optimistic views about future events, whereas Bob purchased insurance to provide for the worst. Then, when both Amy and Bob contracted a serious disease and lost their jobs, only Bob is compensated for his unemployment, whereas Amy is on the verge of death because she cannot pay her expensive medical bills. In this case, even though Amy did not purchase the insurance through her own free choice, it seems too harsh to hold her fully responsible for her final situation due to her own decision (based on a mistaken assessment of probabilities) and leave her in severe poverty (or even dying). This argument may (at least partially) support a mandatory system of public insurance that covers Amy in advance, which would seemingly contradict ex ante Pareto.28</p><p>The third reason is that ex ante Pareto impels social criteria to focus only on each person’s prospects, as argued by Rowe and Voorhoeve.29 Under ex ante Pareto, social evaluations must be insensitive to the possible patterns of final well-being, which would be a reason for incompatibility between ex ante Pareto and dominance and ex post egalitarianism (or impartiality).</p><p>In the context of this axiom, to say that a prospect is “equal” means that all individuals have the same levels of well-being in each state, while a prospect is “riskless” if each individual has the same level of well-being in all states.</p><p>Table 8 illustrates that Pareto for equal or no risk is a plausible principle. Suppose Amy and Bob were to choose a ball from an urn where the number of red and black balls is arbitrary.</p><p>Note that <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> is equal and that <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> is riskless. Suppose that <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> provides higher ex ante utility values than <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> for all individuals. In this case, this axiom requires that <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> should be better than <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math>.</p><p>In cases like this, Pareto for equal or no risk is a compelling principle because, under severe uncertainty, individuals reach a unanimous agreement <i>for the same reason</i>. That is, they have the same levels of final well-being and thus agree on the improvement they achieve. As explained above, spurious unanimity can occur when individuals prefer the same prospect <i>for different reasons</i>.31 Ex ante Pareto allows spurious unanimity in cases like this, where, as a consequence, some individuals benefit while others lose. In contrast, Pareto for equal or no risk can fend off the problem of spurious unanimity because, under uncertain prospects (for example, <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> in Table 8), different individuals have the same level of final well-being in each state. This is also relevant to Rowe and Voorhoeve’s argument,32 because Pareto for equal or no risk allows social criteria to favor possible patterns of final well-being, and is thus compatible with both ex post egalitarianism and dominance.</p><p>In light of our pluralist framework, it is imperative to choose a final distribution in which all agents would reach higher well-being levels.</p><p>As an illustration of how the criterion evaluates an uncertain distribution, consider a case with distribution <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> (Table 9), in which individuals have <math>\n <mi>α</mi></math>-maxmin expected utility functions with <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>C</mi>\n <mi>A</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mfenced>\n <mn>0.2</mn>\n <mo>,</mo>\n <mspace></mspace>\n <mn>0.6</mn>\n </mfenced>\n </mrow></math> and <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>C</mi>\n <mi>B</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>=</mo>\n <mrow>\n <mo>[</mo>\n <mn>0.5</mn>\n <mo>,</mo>\n <mspace></mspace>\n <mn>0.8</mn>\n <mo>]</mo>\n </mrow>\n </mrow></math>.</p><p>Amy’s value is taken by the criterion if and only if <math>\n <mrow>\n <mn>72</mn>\n <mo>-</mo>\n <mn>16</mn>\n <msub>\n <mi>α</mi>\n <mi>A</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>≤</mo>\n <mn>60</mn>\n <mo>-</mo>\n <mn>12</mn>\n <msub>\n <mi>α</mi>\n <mi>B</mi>\n </msub>\n </mrow></math>: that is, 3<math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>α</mi>\n <mi>B</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>≤</mo>\n <mn>4</mn>\n <msub>\n <mi>α</mi>\n <mi>A</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>-</mo>\n <mn>3</mn>\n </mrow></math>.</p><p>According to this theorem, statewise maximin, as a social evaluation criterion, can be fully derived from the relevant principles for egalitarian justice. This could be considered a remarkable result because it is often assumed in debates about egalitarianism that a principle that is applicable to one kind of case or circumstance may have counterintuitive implications in another and, therefore, it is common to appeal to a variety of different principles in different kinds of situations. In Derek Parfit’s pluralist construal of telic egalitarianism, for example, it is better if there is more equality and utility, but the two may come into conflict. Supposedly, to solve such conflicts, weights are assigned.35 However, because these weights are not well defined, it is insufficiently clear how to resolve conflicts between the two goals or principles. In contrast, in our pluralist egalitarianism the relevant principles are fully compatible and, therefore, such conflicts between competing principles are avoided and we can appeal to a single and simple criterion to evaluate uncertain prospects. In other words, we present a non-conflicting pluralist egalitarian view characterized by statewise maximin (which is based on ex post egalitarianism, dominance, impartiality, and Pareto for equal or no risk). Our view is further supported by (a set of) <i>general</i> intuitions that reflect multiple values and/or principles. By utilizing statewise maximin, we can reasonably determine which public policy should be employed without recourse to <i>particular</i> historically formed intuitions, such as liberal egalitarian intuitions.36</p><p>It is important to note that we assume only ordinal interpersonal comparisons of well-being. In particular, ex post egalitarianism can be applied even when cardinal interpersonal comparisons are not possible. As discussed in the Appendix, statewise maximin satisfies cardinal full comparability; in other words, cardinal full comparability derives from the combination of our axioms. This entails that statewise maximin can be used even when cardinal interpersonal comparisons are impossible. To see the importance of this entailment, note that even in situations with population-level uncertainty, such as a global pandemic (discussed in detail below), each person’s life is too complex and subtly different to allow for interpersonal comparisons in a cardinal manner.37 According to statewise maximin, we can reasonably claim that what policy-makers should do in terms of interpersonal comparability is to compare people’s well-being ordinally in the context of public policy.</p><p>Statewise maximin has some properties that are worth paying some attention to. First, when individuals have different probabilities, the criterion aggregates well-beings and probabilities separately. The combination of the lowest levels of well-beings is evaluated by individuals’ ex ante utility functions. This is due to the violation of ex ante Pareto, which enables us to avoid spurious unanimity and the impossibility result. There is no separation between individuals’ probabilities and social prospects when ex ante Pareto is satisfied, on the other hand, simply because under ex ante Pareto their prospects are evaluated in terms of their ex ante utilities.38</p><p>Second, we discuss the evaluator’s uncertainty-aversion under statewise maximin when individuals are uncertainty-averse. This is in a way analogous to Rowe and Voorhoeve’s discussion of uncertainty-aversion.39 For simplicity, we assume here that Amy and Bob have the same maxmin expected utility functions. Illustrative examples are given in Tables 10 and 11.</p><p><math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> is an uncertain situation and Amy and Bob have the same probability set <math>\n <mfenced>\n <mrow>\n <mn>0</mn>\n <mo>,</mo>\n <mn>1</mn>\n </mrow>\n </mfenced></math> (and hence <math>\n <mrow>\n <msub>\n <mi>p</mi>\n <mi>b</mi>\n </msub>\n <mo>∈</mo>\n <mfenced>\n <mrow>\n <mn>0</mn>\n <mo>,</mo>\n <mn>1</mn>\n </mrow>\n </mfenced>\n </mrow></math>). <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> is a risky situation where the final distributions are the same as <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> and the states are equiprobable. In this case, statewise maximin is indifferent between <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> and <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> because the worst off stand at the same level of well-being (that is, <math>\n <mn>50</mn></math>) with certainty in the two distributions. That is, there is no risk for society on the levels of worst-off well-being in the two distributions. In this case, the maxmin expected values of the worst-off are also <math>\n <mn>50</mn></math>. Thus, statewise maximin does not take the differential degree of uncertainty into consideration when the final distributions are the same in all states of the world.</p><p>Next, let us consider the prospects in Table 11, one of which contains population-level uncertainty.</p><p>Thus, <i>Y</i>′ is better than <i>X</i>′ according to statewise maximin. This evaluation comes from Pareto for equal or no risk. Thanks to this efficiency axiom, statewise maximin respects individuals’ uncertainty-aversion and chooses risky <i>Y</i>′ over uncertain <i>X</i>′. The ex ante utility values of both Amy and Bob are higher in <i>Y</i>′. Moreover, both <i>X</i>′ and <i>Y</i>′ are equal. Therefore, <i>Y</i>′ is socially better than <i>X</i>′ by Pareto for equal or no risk.</p><p>It could be considered a problem that statewise maximin, or any other criterion that satisfies Pareto for equal or no risk, violates some famous rationality conditions such as <i>eventwise dominance</i>, because of its uncertainty-aversion.40 Admittedly, this is a cost of respecting individuals’ attitudes toward uncertainty. However, for statewise maximin, uncertainty-aversion is a desirable property for egalitarianism under severe uncertainty, because it is likely to allow us to avoid <i>uncertainty of the worst-off individuals</i>. Put differently, for two social prospects, <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> (riskless) and <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> (uncertain), giving the same ex ante utility to the worst-off individual, statewise maximin prefers <math>\n <mi>X</mi></math> to <math>\n <mi>Y</mi></math> so as not to expose the worst-off individual to uncertainty. This is because statewise maximin evaluates the worst-off well-being levels by the most uncertainty-averse preference. Consequently, it can be argued that violations of some rationality conditions stronger than dominance are not just unavoidable, but are a legitimate or even necessary cost. Statewise maximin chooses an uncertain distribution over a certain one only when the former guarantees a sufficiently larger benefit to the worst-off individuals than the latter, according to the most uncertainty-averse evaluation in society.</p><p>Statewise maximin provides reasonable guidelines for public policies under severe uncertainty. The social evaluation criterion justifies mandatory vaccination for COVID-19 if it is beneficial for the worst-off people, for example. A global pandemic like COVID-19 spreads throughout populations, disregarding socioeconomic background or status. Now suppose that highly effective vaccines with excellent safety records have been developed and are available. Then, according to statewise maximin, vaccination should be made compulsory, provided that the worst-off individuals enjoy a greater benefit from getting vaccinated. While, admittedly, cases of this kind do not always hold under severe uncertainty, statewise maximin as such provides reasonable guidance for policy-makers considering mandatory vaccination in the face of a global pandemic.</p><p>It could be objected, of course, that mandatory vaccination conflicts with the widespread liberal principle that the interest of an individual should not be violated unless the interest-based action is harmful to other individuals. This liberal principle is based on the notion of the separateness of persons, according to which people are separate, autonomous individuals, all leading different, separate lives, whose interests cannot be sacrificed for the interests of others or for the greater good.41 Because this liberal principle also applies in the context of public health, the objector may continue, it seems to preclude mandatory vaccination, and, therefore, this example fails as a confirmation of the strength of our pluralist egalitarianism.</p><p>It should be noted, however, that the suggested vaccination scheme in light of statewise maximin does not conflict with individual claims based on the separateness of persons, because all agents would have the same outcomes in each state under population-level uncertainty. The separateness of persons requires policy-makers to respect the interest-based claims of each person in cases where their outcomes are different in different states of the world. However, the notion of the separateness of persons is irrelevant in case of decisions in situations with population-level uncertainty, and this has important implications, not just in the context of public health, but also for egalitarianism itself. The guideline for public policy advocated by our pluralist egalitarianism does not imply a conflict between the liberal principle and statewise maximin in cases under population-level uncertainty, which hints at the salience of the principles of <i>justice in general</i>. In other words, our pluralist framework maintains the inviolability of key principles—including the liberal principle—that have gained wide support in debates about justice in a global pandemic.</p><p>Arguably, this point also makes our pluralist egalitarianism more appealing than RV pluralist egalitarianism, the view that includes both ex ante egalitarianism and ex post egalitarianism, while declining ex ante Pareto. Furthermore, RV pluralist egalitarianism does not clearly show how ex ante egalitarianism and ex post egalitarianism are compatible, nor how they are related to other principles of egalitarian justice, such as impartiality and dominance. This may lead to indeterminacy with regard to the relevance of fairness and final distributions of well-being in the process of drafting and implementing public policy in the face of a global pandemic. As a guideline for policy-makers, RV pluralist egalitarianism lacks a comprehensive standard and, thus, allows a significant role for decision-makers’ intuitions; but intuitions do not necessarily agree; consequently, RV pluralist egalitarianism fails to provide a method to adjudicate between competing claims.</p><p>In contrast, our pluralist proposal includes a social evaluation criterion that stems from the relevant principles of justice: an egalitarian requirement (ex post egalitarianism), impartiality (impartiality), social rationality (dominance), and efficiency (Pareto for equal or no risk). Therefore, our pluralist egalitarian view can provide comprehensive guidance for policy-makers in their choice of (or between) public policies. Such a view is exactly what is needed as a comprehensive theory of egalitarian justice when we are confronting a global pandemic.</p><p>We have argued that the social evaluation criterion, statewise maximin, is characterized by the axioms of efficiency, ex post egalitarianism, impartiality, and rationality. Our argument shows that statewise maximin is the only criterion of pluralist egalitarianism that meets the relevant axioms (that is, the principles of egalitarian theories). This can be considered to be a solution to the crucial (but often overlooked) issue of the (in)compatibility of the relevant principles. Furthermore, through this study, we have shown that axiomatization is a useful approach in philosophical debates about egalitarianism.</p>","PeriodicalId":47624,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Political Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9000,"publicationDate":"2022-03-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jopp.12276","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Political Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jopp.12276","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Severe uncertainty plays a critical role in many problems of distributive justice, such as social security, public health, public projects, budget deficits, and climate change. Under severe uncertainty, available information does not allow us to assign precise probabilities to possible states of affairs. A recent example of severe uncertainty is the impact of COVID-19. How policy-makers should evaluate different distributions of well-being in such a situation of severe uncertainty is of vital importance to society. Indeed, the COVID-19 pandemic has induced a need to ration medical resources, such as vaccines, using relevant principles of distribution. Such principles have been hotly debated by egalitarians, many of whom are pluralists.1 This article addresses the problem of the distribution of well-being by using an axiomatic approach to pluralist egalitarianism.

Rowe and Voorhoeve’s view can be interpreted as an axiomatic approach to pluralist egalitarianism; it helps to clarify competing claims of a relevant kind and thereby enables policy-makers to evaluate uncertain social situations. They illustrate this by showing how RV pluralist egalitarianism works in particular examples.

There is a need to articulate the axioms involved more explicitly, however, as well as to analyze more rigorously whether and to what extent those axioms are compatible with each other. Furthermore, to assess and choose between competing claims, it would be useful to have a criterion for social evaluation that satisfies the relevant axioms and that orders all possible distributions in a consistent manner. In this article, we introduce axioms of impartiality, efficiency, ex post egalitarianism, and social rationality under severe uncertainty, and address the issue of their compatibility. We then characterize a social evaluation criterion, statewise maximin, by those axioms.3

Although we focus on cases of severe uncertainty, our results show that axiomatization is invaluable in determining what kind of value pluralism is promising as an egalitarian theory. As Iwao Hirose has argued in a different but related context, pluralist theories are often unclear about how many principles they include and/or to what extent those principles are (in)compatible with each other.4 An axiomatic analysis can address these issues—through axiomatic characterization, we can spell out a normative criterion of pluralist egalitarianism.

The argument in this article proceeds as follows. Section II presents our basic framework. Section III specifies the principles of egalitarianism, impartiality, and social rationality. Section IV argues that a standard efficiency axiom under uncertainty, ex ante Pareto, is not compelling, and substitutes another axiom, Pareto for equal or no risk. Section V addresses statewise maximin and its axiomatic representation. Section VI presents some brief concluding remarks. The Appendix lays out a formal analysis.

In this section, we introduce the framework used for our analysis. Following Rowe and Voorhoeve, we use an Ellsberg-type example to epitomize the situation in which decision-makers cannot assign precise probabilities to the possible outcomes of their choice. Suppose that two individuals, Amy and Bob, choose a ball from an urn that contains an unknown number of red and black balls. This represents severe uncertainty. Suppose further that the final distribution of levels of well-being depends on the color of the ball drawn. Thus, the color refers to a state of the world. A social evaluator is expected to compare prospects by appealing to social preferences to evaluate uncertain social situations in terms of their relative desirability.

Let R be the set of real numbers. X R 4 denotes a social prospect (or distribution) in question, which is described in Table 1.

Here, we assume that i = A , B denotes Amy and Bob, and s = r , b denotes the state of the world described by the color of a drawn ball, respectively. x is represents individual i’s well-being in X in state s. For each individual i, X i = x ir , x ib . Moreover, let X r (resp. X b ) be a final distribution of X when a red (resp. black) ball is drawn: that is,

Well-being levels are represented by real numbers that are fully measurable and ordinally interpersonally comparable.5 We assume that, although individuals do not ex ante know their final well-being levels, a social evaluator precisely estimates the final distributions in each state.

Each individual i has a function U i : R 2 R to evaluate the person’s own uncertain situation. For each X i and Y i , U i X i U i Y i means that X i is at least as good as Y i for individual i. U i is referred to as individual i’s ex ante utility function. We assume that U i is continuous and strictly monotonic: for each X i and Y i , if x is y is for all s, then U i X i U i Y i ; in addition, if x i s > y i s for some s′, then U i X i > U i Y i . Moreover, for simplicity, we assume that, for X i such that x ir = x ib = x , U i X i = U i ( x , x ) = x . Although our setting is general, our main results hold even if ex ante utility functions are restricted to particular forms satisfying these conditions.

Our framework assumes that Amy and Bob may have different ex ante utility functions. A notable example is the case in which they have subjective expected utility functions with different probabilistic beliefs. The occurrence (or even mere possibility) of differences in probabilities like these leads us to address an important problem under severe uncertainty: namely, the problem that Philippe Mongin called “spurious unanimity.”7 As will become evident, this problem affects many cooperative projects, and thus needs to be taken seriously as a fundamental problem for a pluralist egalitarian view.

There are also problems associated with situations in which the social evaluator has access to more (relevant) information than the individuals. A pandemic is a paradigmatic example of this kind of problem. In situations like these, the evaluator can use her own probabilities based on the relevant information available to her. Although our main results still hold in cases where individuals’ situations are evaluated in terms of the social evaluator’s probabilities, for the sake of generality, we also consider the case in which the social evaluator uses the individuals’ probabilities, such as the problem of public goods provision discussed in Section IV.

This principle seems intuitively plausible. To see this, compare the following two situations: (1) both Amy and Bob can enjoy a reasonable quality of medical service; (2) Amy can enjoy a very high-quality medical service, while Bob has no access to medical services at all. Suppose that higher-quality medical service leads to higher well-being, because better health resulting from appropriate medical treatment in the high-quality medical service condition improves people’s quality of life. From an egalitarian point of view, it is reasonable to judge (1) to be at least as good as (2).

It might be objected that ex post egalitarianism is too strong because it requires excessive inequality aversion. Our response to this objection is twofold. First, this axiom can be applied without cardinal interpersonal comparisons of well-being. It is important to note that full cardinal interpersonal comparability is not assumed, but rather obtained as a result of characterizing the maximin criterion. Second, and more importantly, the conflicts between relevant principles of a pluralist egalitarian view revealed below still follow if ex post egalitarianism is replaced with the Pigou−Dalton condition, which is a much weaker principle. According to the Pigou−Dalton principle, the same value t of well-being is “transferred” from the better off to the worse off. Conflicts arise between the Pigou−Dalton principle and other relevant principles, similar to those apparent between ex post egalitarianism and those principles.9 On a related note, we show a different way of expressing statewise maximin by replacing ex post egalitarianism with a weak version of the Pigou−Dalton condition, impartiality, and ordinal full comparability of well-being (see Appendix for details).

Table 2 illustrates what dominance requires.

Suppose that the social evaluator supports ex post equality. Then Y r and Y b are socially preferred to X r and X b , respectively. This implies that the final distributions of Y are socially chosen over those of X in all states of the world. Dominance requires that, under this situation, Y should be chosen over X ex ante. If this axiom is violated, society may choose a policy that results in the worse consequence, such as X in this example.

Impartiality is an essential requirement for theories of egalitarian justice. John Rawls emphasized it as the most important premise.10 From impartiality, together with other relevant premises, various key principles can reasonably be derived. They include Rawls’s principle that gives lexical priority to the improvement of the situation of the worst off, which would be unanimously selected by people in a society under the veil of ignorance—that is, by people who have no information about their congenital capacities and social status.

According to impartiality, these distributions are equally good, which is intuitively appealing. Consequently, we should consider impartiality as a central requirement for a pluralist theory of egalitarian justice.

Our version of pluralist egalitarianism does not include this principle. This requires some explanation. Ex ante egalitarianism is often considered to be one of the most important principles of pluralist egalitarianism. For example, Richard Arneson argues that the ideal of equality of opportunity for welfare would obtain if and only if all agents “face equivalent decision trees—the expected value of each person’s best (=most prudent) choice of options, second-best … nth-best is the same” in an effective sense, among other things.13 It follows that the less some situation deviates from the ideal, the more desirable it is from an egalitarian perspective. This idea is included in RV pluralist egalitarianism, according to which we should aim to reduce inequality in people’s prospects.

As stated above, our pluralist egalitarianism does not include ex ante egalitarianism, for three reasons. First, it conflicts with ex post egalitarianism under dominance.14 Consider the case described in Table 3.

On the one hand, the expected well-beings are more equal in X. On the other hand, because the final well-beings are more equal in Y , Y is better according to ex post egalitarianism and dominance. This illustrates a conflict between ex ante egalitarianism and ex post egalitarianism under dominance.

Second, ex ante egalitarianism is also in conflict with dominance and impartiality, which are intuitive and compelling requirements in egalitarian justice. This conflict can be shown by using an example summarized in Table 4.

By reflexivity15 and impartiality, X r and X b are as good as Y r and Y b , respectively. Then, dominance implies that X is as good as Y ex ante. However, ex ante egalitarianism claims that X is better than Y ex ante, which comes into conflict with dominance and impartiality. Note that this conflict does not depend on the two people’s probabilities, because we use dominance only.

It might seem counterintuitive to evaluate X and Y as equally good. However, from the perspective of an impartial evaluator, these distributions could be considered equivalent in the sense that their final distributions of well-being are equally good in each state of the world. This is a reasonable evaluation because, even if the evaluator does not know which state will occur, s/he knows (and thus can evaluate) the final distributions in each state and can combine the evaluations by dominance. This implication supports our focus on distributions of final well-being.16

Third, it is not clear precisely what equality of ex ante utility means. John Broome’s critique of the notion is relevant here.17 While well-being may be valuable in and of itself, the same is not necessarily true for ex ante utility—the latter is valuable simply because achieving ex ante utility is a way of promoting well-being. Hence, it is merely instrumentally valuable, while equality of final well-being may be inherently valuable; therefore, they are not valuable in the same way. It could still be claimed that ex ante equality can be justified on the basis of the notion of a fair process of choice by randomization: that is, by focusing on fairness. In Table 4, X has a fairer distribution of probabilities than Y, for example. However, such an argument from fairness cannot justify equality of ex ante utility, because fairness is satisfied by giving fair chances to the satisfaction of all individuals’ equal claims, not by promoting equality of ex ante utility.

To grasp this, consider the case where we can choose from two courses of action, A and B: A gives one indivisible medicine to either Amy or Bob, two ill persons, by lot, whereas B gives it to either Amy or Bob on the basis of a genealogical investigation into which of the two has the least African ancestry. Even when, as in A, B can equalize their expected utilities, it would be fair to choose A.18 We can conclude, thus, that there is no good reason to include a principle of ex ante egalitarianism that requires equality of ex ante utility.19

Why is ex ante Pareto so common? It is because it apparently prescribes that a society respect individual evaluations by their own ex ante utility functions.20 Ex ante Pareto could be taken to befit the liberal view of justice—this principle does not require a person to participate in a public insurance scheme if the person prefers not to do so. However, we argue that ex ante Pareto conflicts with the axioms introduced in Section III. We also insist that ex ante Pareto should not appeal to theorists of egalitarian justice, and introduce another Pareto principle that is more compelling under severe uncertainty.21

First, following Fleurbaey and Voorhoeve,22 we can demonstrate that, under dominance, ex ante Pareto is not compatible with ex post egalitarianism. We assume here that, for each i and each X i , U i X i = 0.5 ( x ir + x ib ) . However, conflicts of a similar kind can be obtained in broader sets of beliefs. Consider the following prospects in Table 5.

Similarly, we can show that under dominance, ex ante Pareto is not compatible with impartiality (Table 6).

Suppose that all individuals are subjective expected-utility maximizers and that p Ar = 0.8 and p Br = 0.2 . By impartiality, the final distributions in both states are indifferent between X and Y and, therefore, X and Y are indifferent ex ante. However, ex ante Pareto claims that X is better than Y, which shows a conflict with impartiality.

Given the above conflicts, we give three reasons why ex ante Pareto is not compelling, and will later introduce a weaker efficiency axiom. The first reason concerns the problem of “spurious unanimity” pointed out by Mongin: a unanimous agreement may not be compelling if the individuals reach agreement for different reasons: that is, when individuals have heterogeneous beliefs and distributions have different rankings of final well-being levels between individuals in different states.24

Mongin gives an example. Consider a plan to build a bridge between two countries, T (a developed country) and L (a developing country). In L, some people expect some economic benefits (for example, benefits from tourism), while others are concerned that they may lose their traditional culture and lifestyle under the influence of T. Suppose that people in L are divided into two groups, A and B. Those in A believe that the benefit is large enough and that their outdated traditions will (and should) be destroyed. Those in B think that the tradition at stake is important, but will not be damaged, because the influence from T will be moderate, and that the bridge will only bring some benefits. This situation is illustrated by Table 7, where if the bridge is constructed in X, the influence from T is large in Red and not in Black. Y is the distribution when the bridge is not constructed. Suppose that all individuals are subjective expected-utility maximizers and that p Ar = 0.8 and p Br = 0.2 . Both groups support the construction of the bridge, although one group is subsequently proved wrong. Such an ex ante agreement is not compelling.

The second reason is that, under severe uncertainty, it is difficult for individuals to make decisions in an accountable way, because they do not have exact information about the probabilities of the options they are choosing between. Because of this, their final well-being levels would depend on uncertain states. In such a situation, individuals cannot be held fully responsible for their decisions, because they cannot control fortune.25 Moreover, in our environment, individuals may have some heuristics and biases under uncertainty, making it more difficult for them to be responsible for the decisions; they do not have enough capacities to handle uncertain choices.26 These points show that ex ante Pareto is not a compelling principle.

Those points are also important for egalitarian justice with respect to the so-called “harshness objection” against luck egalitarianism.27 To see this, suppose that Amy did not take out health insurance because of her (overly) optimistic views about future events, whereas Bob purchased insurance to provide for the worst. Then, when both Amy and Bob contracted a serious disease and lost their jobs, only Bob is compensated for his unemployment, whereas Amy is on the verge of death because she cannot pay her expensive medical bills. In this case, even though Amy did not purchase the insurance through her own free choice, it seems too harsh to hold her fully responsible for her final situation due to her own decision (based on a mistaken assessment of probabilities) and leave her in severe poverty (or even dying). This argument may (at least partially) support a mandatory system of public insurance that covers Amy in advance, which would seemingly contradict ex ante Pareto.28

The third reason is that ex ante Pareto impels social criteria to focus only on each person’s prospects, as argued by Rowe and Voorhoeve.29 Under ex ante Pareto, social evaluations must be insensitive to the possible patterns of final well-being, which would be a reason for incompatibility between ex ante Pareto and dominance and ex post egalitarianism (or impartiality).

In the context of this axiom, to say that a prospect is “equal” means that all individuals have the same levels of well-being in each state, while a prospect is “riskless” if each individual has the same level of well-being in all states.

Table 8 illustrates that Pareto for equal or no risk is a plausible principle. Suppose Amy and Bob were to choose a ball from an urn where the number of red and black balls is arbitrary.

Note that X is equal and that Y is riskless. Suppose that X provides higher ex ante utility values than Y for all individuals. In this case, this axiom requires that X should be better than Y.

In cases like this, Pareto for equal or no risk is a compelling principle because, under severe uncertainty, individuals reach a unanimous agreement for the same reason. That is, they have the same levels of final well-being and thus agree on the improvement they achieve. As explained above, spurious unanimity can occur when individuals prefer the same prospect for different reasons.31 Ex ante Pareto allows spurious unanimity in cases like this, where, as a consequence, some individuals benefit while others lose. In contrast, Pareto for equal or no risk can fend off the problem of spurious unanimity because, under uncertain prospects (for example, X in Table 8), different individuals have the same level of final well-being in each state. This is also relevant to Rowe and Voorhoeve’s argument,32 because Pareto for equal or no risk allows social criteria to favor possible patterns of final well-being, and is thus compatible with both ex post egalitarianism and dominance.

In light of our pluralist framework, it is imperative to choose a final distribution in which all agents would reach higher well-being levels.

As an illustration of how the criterion evaluates an uncertain distribution, consider a case with distribution X (Table 9), in which individuals have α-maxmin expected utility functions with C A = 0.2 , 0.6 and C B = [ 0.5 , 0.8 ] .

Amy’s value is taken by the criterion if and only if 72 - 16 α A 60 - 12 α B : that is, 3 α B 4 α A - 3 .

According to this theorem, statewise maximin, as a social evaluation criterion, can be fully derived from the relevant principles for egalitarian justice. This could be considered a remarkable result because it is often assumed in debates about egalitarianism that a principle that is applicable to one kind of case or circumstance may have counterintuitive implications in another and, therefore, it is common to appeal to a variety of different principles in different kinds of situations. In Derek Parfit’s pluralist construal of telic egalitarianism, for example, it is better if there is more equality and utility, but the two may come into conflict. Supposedly, to solve such conflicts, weights are assigned.35 However, because these weights are not well defined, it is insufficiently clear how to resolve conflicts between the two goals or principles. In contrast, in our pluralist egalitarianism the relevant principles are fully compatible and, therefore, such conflicts between competing principles are avoided and we can appeal to a single and simple criterion to evaluate uncertain prospects. In other words, we present a non-conflicting pluralist egalitarian view characterized by statewise maximin (which is based on ex post egalitarianism, dominance, impartiality, and Pareto for equal or no risk). Our view is further supported by (a set of) general intuitions that reflect multiple values and/or principles. By utilizing statewise maximin, we can reasonably determine which public policy should be employed without recourse to particular historically formed intuitions, such as liberal egalitarian intuitions.36

It is important to note that we assume only ordinal interpersonal comparisons of well-being. In particular, ex post egalitarianism can be applied even when cardinal interpersonal comparisons are not possible. As discussed in the Appendix, statewise maximin satisfies cardinal full comparability; in other words, cardinal full comparability derives from the combination of our axioms. This entails that statewise maximin can be used even when cardinal interpersonal comparisons are impossible. To see the importance of this entailment, note that even in situations with population-level uncertainty, such as a global pandemic (discussed in detail below), each person’s life is too complex and subtly different to allow for interpersonal comparisons in a cardinal manner.37 According to statewise maximin, we can reasonably claim that what policy-makers should do in terms of interpersonal comparability is to compare people’s well-being ordinally in the context of public policy.

Statewise maximin has some properties that are worth paying some attention to. First, when individuals have different probabilities, the criterion aggregates well-beings and probabilities separately. The combination of the lowest levels of well-beings is evaluated by individuals’ ex ante utility functions. This is due to the violation of ex ante Pareto, which enables us to avoid spurious unanimity and the impossibility result. There is no separation between individuals’ probabilities and social prospects when ex ante Pareto is satisfied, on the other hand, simply because under ex ante Pareto their prospects are evaluated in terms of their ex ante utilities.38

Second, we discuss the evaluator’s uncertainty-aversion under statewise maximin when individuals are uncertainty-averse. This is in a way analogous to Rowe and Voorhoeve’s discussion of uncertainty-aversion.39 For simplicity, we assume here that Amy and Bob have the same maxmin expected utility functions. Illustrative examples are given in Tables 10 and 11.

X is an uncertain situation and Amy and Bob have the same probability set 0 , 1 (and hence p b 0 , 1 ). Y is a risky situation where the final distributions are the same as X and the states are equiprobable. In this case, statewise maximin is indifferent between X and Y because the worst off stand at the same level of well-being (that is, 50) with certainty in the two distributions. That is, there is no risk for society on the levels of worst-off well-being in the two distributions. In this case, the maxmin expected values of the worst-off are also 50. Thus, statewise maximin does not take the differential degree of uncertainty into consideration when the final distributions are the same in all states of the world.

Next, let us consider the prospects in Table 11, one of which contains population-level uncertainty.

Thus, Y′ is better than X′ according to statewise maximin. This evaluation comes from Pareto for equal or no risk. Thanks to this efficiency axiom, statewise maximin respects individuals’ uncertainty-aversion and chooses risky Y′ over uncertain X′. The ex ante utility values of both Amy and Bob are higher in Y′. Moreover, both X′ and Y′ are equal. Therefore, Y′ is socially better than X′ by Pareto for equal or no risk.

It could be considered a problem that statewise maximin, or any other criterion that satisfies Pareto for equal or no risk, violates some famous rationality conditions such as eventwise dominance, because of its uncertainty-aversion.40 Admittedly, this is a cost of respecting individuals’ attitudes toward uncertainty. However, for statewise maximin, uncertainty-aversion is a desirable property for egalitarianism under severe uncertainty, because it is likely to allow us to avoid uncertainty of the worst-off individuals. Put differently, for two social prospects, X (riskless) and Y (uncertain), giving the same ex ante utility to the worst-off individual, statewise maximin prefers X to Y so as not to expose the worst-off individual to uncertainty. This is because statewise maximin evaluates the worst-off well-being levels by the most uncertainty-averse preference. Consequently, it can be argued that violations of some rationality conditions stronger than dominance are not just unavoidable, but are a legitimate or even necessary cost. Statewise maximin chooses an uncertain distribution over a certain one only when the former guarantees a sufficiently larger benefit to the worst-off individuals than the latter, according to the most uncertainty-averse evaluation in society.

Statewise maximin provides reasonable guidelines for public policies under severe uncertainty. The social evaluation criterion justifies mandatory vaccination for COVID-19 if it is beneficial for the worst-off people, for example. A global pandemic like COVID-19 spreads throughout populations, disregarding socioeconomic background or status. Now suppose that highly effective vaccines with excellent safety records have been developed and are available. Then, according to statewise maximin, vaccination should be made compulsory, provided that the worst-off individuals enjoy a greater benefit from getting vaccinated. While, admittedly, cases of this kind do not always hold under severe uncertainty, statewise maximin as such provides reasonable guidance for policy-makers considering mandatory vaccination in the face of a global pandemic.

It could be objected, of course, that mandatory vaccination conflicts with the widespread liberal principle that the interest of an individual should not be violated unless the interest-based action is harmful to other individuals. This liberal principle is based on the notion of the separateness of persons, according to which people are separate, autonomous individuals, all leading different, separate lives, whose interests cannot be sacrificed for the interests of others or for the greater good.41 Because this liberal principle also applies in the context of public health, the objector may continue, it seems to preclude mandatory vaccination, and, therefore, this example fails as a confirmation of the strength of our pluralist egalitarianism.

It should be noted, however, that the suggested vaccination scheme in light of statewise maximin does not conflict with individual claims based on the separateness of persons, because all agents would have the same outcomes in each state under population-level uncertainty. The separateness of persons requires policy-makers to respect the interest-based claims of each person in cases where their outcomes are different in different states of the world. However, the notion of the separateness of persons is irrelevant in case of decisions in situations with population-level uncertainty, and this has important implications, not just in the context of public health, but also for egalitarianism itself. The guideline for public policy advocated by our pluralist egalitarianism does not imply a conflict between the liberal principle and statewise maximin in cases under population-level uncertainty, which hints at the salience of the principles of justice in general. In other words, our pluralist framework maintains the inviolability of key principles—including the liberal principle—that have gained wide support in debates about justice in a global pandemic.

Arguably, this point also makes our pluralist egalitarianism more appealing than RV pluralist egalitarianism, the view that includes both ex ante egalitarianism and ex post egalitarianism, while declining ex ante Pareto. Furthermore, RV pluralist egalitarianism does not clearly show how ex ante egalitarianism and ex post egalitarianism are compatible, nor how they are related to other principles of egalitarian justice, such as impartiality and dominance. This may lead to indeterminacy with regard to the relevance of fairness and final distributions of well-being in the process of drafting and implementing public policy in the face of a global pandemic. As a guideline for policy-makers, RV pluralist egalitarianism lacks a comprehensive standard and, thus, allows a significant role for decision-makers’ intuitions; but intuitions do not necessarily agree; consequently, RV pluralist egalitarianism fails to provide a method to adjudicate between competing claims.

In contrast, our pluralist proposal includes a social evaluation criterion that stems from the relevant principles of justice: an egalitarian requirement (ex post egalitarianism), impartiality (impartiality), social rationality (dominance), and efficiency (Pareto for equal or no risk). Therefore, our pluralist egalitarian view can provide comprehensive guidance for policy-makers in their choice of (or between) public policies. Such a view is exactly what is needed as a comprehensive theory of egalitarian justice when we are confronting a global pandemic.

We have argued that the social evaluation criterion, statewise maximin, is characterized by the axioms of efficiency, ex post egalitarianism, impartiality, and rationality. Our argument shows that statewise maximin is the only criterion of pluralist egalitarianism that meets the relevant axioms (that is, the principles of egalitarian theories). This can be considered to be a solution to the crucial (but often overlooked) issue of the (in)compatibility of the relevant principles. Furthermore, through this study, we have shown that axiomatization is a useful approach in philosophical debates about egalitarianism.

严重不确定性下多元平均主义的辩护:公理化表征*
我们的框架假设Amy和Bob可能有不同的事前效用函数。一个显著的例子是,它们具有不同概率信念的主观期望效用函数。像这样的概率差异的发生(或者仅仅是可能性)让我们在严重不确定性下解决一个重要问题:即菲利普·蒙金(Philippe Mongin)所说的“虚假一致”问题。“7 .很明显,这个问题影响到许多合作项目,因此需要作为多元平等主义观点的一个基本问题加以认真对待。在社会评估者比个人获得更多(相关)信息的情况下,也会出现问题。大流行是这类问题的典型例子。在这样的情况下,评估者可以根据可获得的相关信息使用自己的概率。虽然我们的主要结果仍然适用于根据社会评估者的概率来评估个人情况的情况,但为了一般性起见,我们也考虑了社会评估者使用个人概率的情况,例如第四节讨论的公共产品提供问题。这一原则在直觉上似乎是合理的。为了了解这一点,对比以下两种情况:(1)Amy和Bob都能享受到合理的医疗服务质量;(2) Amy可以享受到非常高质量的医疗服务,而Bob则完全无法享受到医疗服务。假设更高质量的医疗服务带来更高的幸福感,因为在高质量的医疗服务条件下,适当的医疗带来的更好的健康,提高了人们的生活质量。从平等主义的观点来看,判断(1)至少与(2)一样好是合理的。可能有人反对说,后平均主义过于强烈,因为它要求过度厌恶不平等。我们对这一反对意见的回应是双重的。首先,这个公理可以在没有基本的人际幸福比较的情况下应用。重要的是要注意,完全的基本人际可比性不是假设的,而是作为表征最大标准的结果而获得的。其次,更重要的是,如果用庇古-道尔顿条件(这是一个弱得多的原则)取代后平均主义,下文揭示的多元平等主义观点的相关原则之间的冲突仍然存在。根据庇古-道尔顿原理,同样的幸福价值会从较富裕的人身上“转移”给较贫穷的人。庇古-道尔顿原则与其他相关原则之间产生了冲突,类似于后平均主义与这些原则之间的明显冲突在相关的说明中,我们展示了一种不同的表达状态最大化的方式,即用弱版本的庇古-道尔顿条件、公正性和福祉的有序完全可比性取代事后平均主义(详见附录)。表2说明了主导地位需要什么。假设社会评估者支持事后平等。那么Y r和Y b分别比X r和X b更受社会青睐。这意味着在世界上所有状态下,Y的最终分布都是社会选择的,而不是X的最终分布。优势要求,在这种情况下,应该事先选择Y而不是X。如果违反了这个公理,社会可能会选择导致更坏后果的政策,比如这个例子中的X。公正是平等正义理论的基本要求。约翰·罗尔斯强调它是最重要的前提从公正性出发,结合其他相关前提,可以合理地推导出各种关键原则。其中包括罗尔斯的原则,即在词汇上优先考虑改善最穷的人的处境,这将由一个处于无知面纱下的社会中的人们一致选择,也就是说,那些对自己的先天能力和社会地位一无所知的人。根据公正性,这些分布都同样好,这在直觉上很有吸引力。因此,我们应该把公正视为平等正义的多元主义理论的核心要求。我们的多元平均主义版本不包括这一原则。这需要一些解释。事前平均主义通常被认为是多元平均主义最重要的原则之一。 例如,理查德·阿内森(Richard Arneson)认为,当且仅当所有的行为者“面对相同的决策树——每个人的最佳(=最谨慎的)选择、次优选择、次优选择的期望值在有效意义上是相同的”时,福利机会平等的理想才会实现因此,从平等主义的角度来看,某些情况与理想的偏差越小,它就越令人满意。这一思想包含在RV多元平均主义中,根据多元平均主义,我们应该致力于减少人们前景中的不平等。如上所述,我们的多元平均主义不包括事前平均主义,原因有三。首先,它与统治下的后平均主义相冲突考虑表3中描述的情况。一方面,期望幸福感在x上更平等;另一方面,由于最终幸福感在Y上更平等,因此根据后平均主义和优势主义,Y更好。这说明了统治下的事前平均主义和事后平均主义之间的冲突。其次,事前平均主义也与支配性和公正性相冲突,而支配性和公正性是平等主义正义的直观和迫切的要求。这种冲突可以通过使用表4中总结的一个示例来显示。在反身性和公正性方面,X r和X b分别与Y r和Y b一样好。那么,优势意味着X事前和Y一样好。但是事前平均主义主张X事前比Y好,这与支配性和公正性相冲突。请注意,这种冲突并不取决于两个人的概率,因为我们只使用优势。将X和Y评价为同样好似乎是违反直觉的。然而,从一个公正的评估者的角度来看,这些分布可以被认为是相等的,因为它们的最终福祉分布在世界上的每个国家都同样好。这是一种合理的评估,因为即使评估者不知道将发生哪种状态,他/她也知道(并因此可以评估)每种状态的最终分布,并可以通过优势组合评估。这一暗示支持了我们对最终幸福感分布的关注。第三,事先效用平等的确切含义并不清楚。约翰·布鲁姆对这一概念的批判与此相关虽然幸福本身可能是有价值的,但对事前效用来说却未必如此——后者之所以有价值,仅仅是因为实现事前效用是促进幸福的一种方式。因此,它仅具有工具价值,而最终福祉的平等可能具有内在价值;因此,它们的价值并不相同。我们仍然可以声称,基于随机选择的公平过程的概念,事前平等是合理的:也就是说,通过关注公平。例如,在表4中,X的概率分布比Y更公平。然而,这种来自公平的论证并不能证明事前效用的平等,因为公平是通过给予公平的机会来满足所有个体的平等要求来实现的,而不是通过促进事前效用的平等来实现的。为了理解这一点,考虑这样一个情况,我们可以从两个行动方案A和B中做出选择:A通过抽签将一种不可分割的药物给艾米或鲍勃,两个病人,而B根据家谱调查将药物给艾米或鲍勃,这两个人中谁的非洲血统最少。即使在A中,B可以使他们的预期效用相等,选择A也是公平的。因此,我们可以得出结论,没有很好的理由包括要求事前效用相等的事前平均主义原则。为什么事前帕累托如此普遍?这是因为它显然规定,一个社会尊重个人对其事前效用函数的评价事前帕累托可以被认为符合自由主义的正义观——如果一个人不愿意参加公共保险计划,这一原则并不要求他参加。然而,我们认为事前帕累托与第三节中引入的公理相冲突。我们还坚持认为,事前帕累托不应该吸引平等正义的理论家,并引入另一个在严重不确定性下更具说服力的帕累托原则。 相比之下,我们的多元主义建议包括一个源于正义相关原则的社会评价标准:平等主义的要求(事后平等主义)、公正(公正)、社会理性(支配)和效率(帕累托为相等或无风险)。因此,我们的多元平等主义观点可以为决策者在公共政策的选择(或公共政策之间的选择)提供全面的指导。这种观点正是我们在面对全球性流行病时所需要的,作为一种全面的平等正义理论。我们认为,社会评价标准,即状态最大化,其特点是效率、事后平均主义、公正和理性的公理。我们的论证表明,状态最大化是多元平均主义满足相关公理(即平等主义理论的原则)的唯一标准。这可以被认为是解决关键(但经常被忽视)的问题,即有关原则的(不)兼容性。此外,通过这项研究,我们已经表明,公理化是一个有用的方法,在哲学辩论平均主义。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
4.10
自引率
5.60%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: The Journal of Political Philosophy is an international journal devoted to the study of theoretical issues arising out of moral, legal and political life. It welcomes, and hopes to foster, work cutting across a variety of disciplinary concerns, among them philosophy, sociology, history, economics and political science. The journal encourages new approaches, including (but not limited to): feminism; environmentalism; critical theory, post-modernism and analytical Marxism; social and public choice theory; law and economics, critical legal studies and critical race studies; and game theoretic, socio-biological and anthropological approaches to politics. It also welcomes work in the history of political thought which builds to a larger philosophical point and work in the philosophy of the social sciences and applied ethics with broader political implications. Featuring a distinguished editorial board from major centres of thought from around the globe, the journal draws equally upon the work of non-philosophers and philosophers and provides a forum of debate between disparate factions who usually keep to their own separate journals.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信