Rejecting the Myth of Popular Sovereignty and Applying an Agency Model to Direct Democracy

IF 2.4 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW
G. Staszewski
{"title":"Rejecting the Myth of Popular Sovereignty and Applying an Agency Model to Direct Democracy","authors":"G. Staszewski","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.405520","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Successful ballot measures are commonly perceived as a pure reflection of \"the will of the people.\" Yet initiatives do not appear magically on election ballots or in statute books as a result of the electorate's wishes. Rather, such measures are conceived, drafted, and vigorously promoted by identifiable initiative proponents, who often represent particular special interests and may not even live in the communities in which their measures are proposed. The myth of popular sovereignty in direct democracy should be rejected. Instead, initiative measures should be characterized as lawmaking by initiative proponents, whose general objective is either ratified or rejected by the voters. Rejecting the myth of popular sovereignty in direct democracy would alleviate many of the problems of judicial review that commentators have identified. By treating the initiative proponents as the relevant lawmakers, courts would be able to identify impermissible motives underlying a measure's enactment and continue using an intentionalist methodology of statutory interpretation without resorting to a counterproductive fiction of \"voter intent.\" On the other hand, express recognition that direct democracy involves lawmaking by initiative proponents intensifies the tension between direct democracy and representative government, the problems associated with the delegation of lawmaking authority to unelected actors, and the absence of safeguards to encourage careful deliberation and reasoned decisionmaking in the initiative process. Initiative proponents are not the only unelected lawmakers in our democracy. Administrative agencies have freely enacted binding rules based on broad delegations of authority since the New Deal. This development has always been considered constitutionally suspect, but courts have allowed it to continue unabated largely because administrative law has developed alternative safeguards to replace those provided in the legislative process by representation and the requirements of Article I, Section 7. Specifically, administrative agencies must comply with the notice-and-comment procedures of the Administrative Procedure Act, and their final rules must withstand hard-look judicial review. Those safeguards ensure that agency officials engage in careful deliberation and reasoned decision-making and have thereby legitimized agency lawmaking. A similar model is needed to constrain the proponents of ballot measures and thereby legitimize the use of direct democracy. This Article therefore draws on the agency model to propose amending state laws that regulate direct democracy to subject the proponents of initiatives to the requirements of public deliberation and reasoned decisionmaking that presently constrain administrative agencies. The Article argues that unlike previous proposals, such reforms would promote careful deliberation, improve the legislative product, and provide a heightened standard of judicial review that is well established and directly responsive to the serious structural shortcomings of the current method of lawmaking by \"the people.\"","PeriodicalId":47503,"journal":{"name":"Vanderbilt Law Review","volume":"56 1","pages":"395"},"PeriodicalIF":2.4000,"publicationDate":"2003-06-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"6","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Vanderbilt Law Review","FirstCategoryId":"90","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.405520","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"LAW","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6

Abstract

Successful ballot measures are commonly perceived as a pure reflection of "the will of the people." Yet initiatives do not appear magically on election ballots or in statute books as a result of the electorate's wishes. Rather, such measures are conceived, drafted, and vigorously promoted by identifiable initiative proponents, who often represent particular special interests and may not even live in the communities in which their measures are proposed. The myth of popular sovereignty in direct democracy should be rejected. Instead, initiative measures should be characterized as lawmaking by initiative proponents, whose general objective is either ratified or rejected by the voters. Rejecting the myth of popular sovereignty in direct democracy would alleviate many of the problems of judicial review that commentators have identified. By treating the initiative proponents as the relevant lawmakers, courts would be able to identify impermissible motives underlying a measure's enactment and continue using an intentionalist methodology of statutory interpretation without resorting to a counterproductive fiction of "voter intent." On the other hand, express recognition that direct democracy involves lawmaking by initiative proponents intensifies the tension between direct democracy and representative government, the problems associated with the delegation of lawmaking authority to unelected actors, and the absence of safeguards to encourage careful deliberation and reasoned decisionmaking in the initiative process. Initiative proponents are not the only unelected lawmakers in our democracy. Administrative agencies have freely enacted binding rules based on broad delegations of authority since the New Deal. This development has always been considered constitutionally suspect, but courts have allowed it to continue unabated largely because administrative law has developed alternative safeguards to replace those provided in the legislative process by representation and the requirements of Article I, Section 7. Specifically, administrative agencies must comply with the notice-and-comment procedures of the Administrative Procedure Act, and their final rules must withstand hard-look judicial review. Those safeguards ensure that agency officials engage in careful deliberation and reasoned decision-making and have thereby legitimized agency lawmaking. A similar model is needed to constrain the proponents of ballot measures and thereby legitimize the use of direct democracy. This Article therefore draws on the agency model to propose amending state laws that regulate direct democracy to subject the proponents of initiatives to the requirements of public deliberation and reasoned decisionmaking that presently constrain administrative agencies. The Article argues that unlike previous proposals, such reforms would promote careful deliberation, improve the legislative product, and provide a heightened standard of judicial review that is well established and directly responsive to the serious structural shortcomings of the current method of lawmaking by "the people."
拒绝人民主权的神话,将代理模型应用于直接民主
成功的投票措施通常被认为是“人民意志”的纯粹反映。然而,倡议不会因为选民的意愿而神奇地出现在选举选票或法规书上。相反,这些措施是由可识别的倡议支持者构思、起草和大力推动的,他们通常代表着特定的特殊利益,甚至可能不住在提出这些措施的社区。直接民主中人民主权的神话应该被抛弃。相反,倡议措施应该被描述为倡议支持者的立法,他们的总体目标要么被选民批准,要么被选民拒绝。拒绝直接民主中人民主权的神话,将缓解评论家们所指出的司法审查的许多问题。通过将倡议的支持者视为相关的立法者,法院将能够确定一项措施制定背后的不允许动机,并继续使用意图主义的法律解释方法,而不诉诸于适得其反的“选民意图”的虚构。另一方面,明确承认直接民主涉及倡议支持者的立法,加剧了直接民主与代议制政府之间的紧张关系,以及将立法权委托给未经选举的行为者所带来的问题,以及在倡议过程中缺乏鼓励仔细审议和理性决策的保障措施。在我们的民主制度中,倡议的支持者并不是唯一未经选举的立法者。自罗斯福新政以来,行政机关在广泛授权的基础上自由制定了具有约束力的规则。这种发展在宪法上一直被认为是可疑的,但法院允许它继续有增无减,主要是因为行政法制定了其他保障措施,以代表权和第一条第7款的要求取代立法程序中提供的保障。具体而言,行政机关必须遵守《行政程序法》的通知和评论程序,其最终规则必须经得起严格的司法审查。这些保障措施确保机构官员进行认真审议和理性决策,从而使机构立法合法化。需要一个类似的模式来限制投票措施的支持者,从而使直接民主的使用合法化。因此,本文借鉴了机构模型,建议修改规范直接民主的州法律,使倡议的支持者服从目前限制行政机构的公共审议和理性决策的要求。文章认为,与以前的提议不同,这些改革将促进仔细审议,改善立法产品,并提供更高的司法审查标准,这种标准已经建立起来,并直接回应当前“人民”立法方法的严重结构性缺陷。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.30
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊介绍: Vanderbilt Law Review En Banc is an online forum designed to advance scholarly discussion. En Banc offers professors, practitioners, students, and others an opportunity to respond to articles printed in the Vanderbilt Law Review. En Banc permits extended discussion of our articles in a way that maintains academic integrity and provides authors with a quicker approach to publication. When reexamining a case “en banc” an appellate court operates at its highest level, with all judges present and participating “on the bench.” We chose the name “En Banc” to capture this spirit of focused review and provide a forum for further dialogue where all can be present and participate.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信