Of Brutal Murder and Transcendental Sovereignty: The Meaning of Vested Private Rights

IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW
A. MacLeod
{"title":"Of Brutal Murder and Transcendental Sovereignty: The Meaning of Vested Private Rights","authors":"A. MacLeod","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2810162","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The idea of vested private rights divides those who practice law from those who teach and think about law. On one side of the divide, practicing lawyers act as though (at least some) rights exist and exert binding obligation upon private persons and government officials. On the other side of the divide, scholars of law and jurisprudence have generally proceeded, since at least the rise of English positivism in the nineteenth century and the American legal realist movement in the early twentieth, as if the concept of vested right has little real meaning. This article attempts to explain the doctrine’s continued appeal and to discern some coherence in it while also accounting for the causes of skepticism.The approach is made by way of a central case study: the right of emancipation on free English soil. The study suggests a coherent, focal meaning of the vested private right as a norm that imposes a conclusive duty upon a duty-bearer or class of duty-bearers, and which constrains public officials’ powers to recognize, change, or adjudicate private rights and duties. This focal meaning suggests that central instances of vested rights are quite rare. This accounts for skepticism of the concept. Yet it also suggests that less-central instances of vested rights are rather common. This accounts for the concept’s practical appeal and enables one to distinguish weak or peripheral senses of vested private rights, which are not as conceptually interesting but are nevertheless significant for the practice of law, from strong or central senses, which are rare in practice but theoretically interesting.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6000,"publicationDate":"2016-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"2","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","FirstCategoryId":"90","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2810162","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"LAW","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2

Abstract

The idea of vested private rights divides those who practice law from those who teach and think about law. On one side of the divide, practicing lawyers act as though (at least some) rights exist and exert binding obligation upon private persons and government officials. On the other side of the divide, scholars of law and jurisprudence have generally proceeded, since at least the rise of English positivism in the nineteenth century and the American legal realist movement in the early twentieth, as if the concept of vested right has little real meaning. This article attempts to explain the doctrine’s continued appeal and to discern some coherence in it while also accounting for the causes of skepticism.The approach is made by way of a central case study: the right of emancipation on free English soil. The study suggests a coherent, focal meaning of the vested private right as a norm that imposes a conclusive duty upon a duty-bearer or class of duty-bearers, and which constrains public officials’ powers to recognize, change, or adjudicate private rights and duties. This focal meaning suggests that central instances of vested rights are quite rare. This accounts for skepticism of the concept. Yet it also suggests that less-central instances of vested rights are rather common. This accounts for the concept’s practical appeal and enables one to distinguish weak or peripheral senses of vested private rights, which are not as conceptually interesting but are nevertheless significant for the practice of law, from strong or central senses, which are rare in practice but theoretically interesting.
野蛮谋杀与先验主权:既得私权的意义
既得私人权利的概念将法律从业者与教授和思考法律的人区分开来。在分歧的一方,执业律师表现得好像(至少有些)权利是存在的,并对个人和政府官员施加有约束力的义务。在分歧的另一边,至少从19世纪英国实证主义的兴起和20世纪初美国法律现实主义运动开始,法律和法学学者就普遍认为既得权利的概念没有什么真正的意义。本文试图解释该学说的持续吸引力,并辨别出其中的一些一致性,同时也说明了怀疑主义的原因。这个方法是通过一个中心案例研究:在自由的英国土地上的解放权利。这项研究表明,既得的私人权利作为一种规范具有连贯的、集中的意义,它对义务承担者或义务承担者阶级施加了决定性的义务,并限制了公职人员承认、改变或裁决私人权利和义务的权力。这一中心意义表明既得权利的中心实例相当罕见。这说明人们对这一概念持怀疑态度。然而,它也表明,既得权利的不那么核心的例子相当普遍。这解释了这一概念的实际吸引力,并使人们能够区分既得私人权利的弱或外围感觉,这些感觉在概念上不那么有趣,但对法律实践却很重要,而强或中心感觉在实践中很少见,但在理论上很有趣。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.80
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊介绍: The Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy is published three times annually by the Harvard Society for Law & Public Policy, Inc., an organization of Harvard Law School students. The Journal is one of the most widely circulated student-edited law reviews and the nation’s leading forum for conservative and libertarian legal scholarship. The late Stephen Eberhard and former Senator and Secretary of Energy E. Spencer Abraham founded the journal twenty-eight years ago and many journal alumni have risen to prominent legal positions in the government and at the nation’s top law firms.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信