The interpretation of Hesiod, ‘Theogony’ 736ff

IF 0.5 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS
G. Kirk
{"title":"The interpretation of Hesiod, ‘Theogony’ 736ff","authors":"G. Kirk","doi":"10.1017/S1750270500012161","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Gregory Vlastos, in his interesting review of Cornford's Principium Sapientiae , in Gnomon , XXVII (1955), pp. 65ff., gives a particularly bald statement (p. 74 and n. 2) of a theory advanced in an article by Friedrich Solmsen, ‘Chaos and Apeiron’, Studi Italiani di Filologia Classica , n.s. XXIV (1950), pp. 235ff., and by Hermann Frankel in his Dichtung und Philosophie des fruhen Griechentums (New York, 1951), pp. 148–9. The theory is that Theogony 736–45 has a profound cosmogonical significance, and that it was probably from there that Anaximander derived and developed his idea of an originative ἄπeιρον. Now the Hesiodic passage is one of a group of variant descriptions of Tartaros that extend, as an appendix to the Titanomachy, from 726 to 819. Many of these descriptions are mutually inconsistent, and, although I would not go quite so far as Jacoby ( Hesiodi Carmina: pars I, Theogonia (Berlin, 1930), pp. 22 ff.) in asserting that they are certainly all later additions, most of them by different authors, it seems manifest that they cannot all be by the author of the Theogony as a whole—even accepting that this poem is to some extent a synthesis, not always elegant or consistent, of previous accounts. At all events no other part of the poem, including the cosmogony and theogony of 116 ff., manifests the piecemeal, repetitive and contradictory qualities of this series of descriptions of Tartaros. For example, 726–45 describes the underworld, and it is there that the halls of Night are located; but at 746 ff. there is a sudden transition to the far west, the region where Atlas stands and where Night exchanges with Day. Solmsen ( op. cit. p. 243, n. 2) tries to defend this unaccountable and irrelevant switch by showing that Night, earlier in the poem, is associated with the western parts of the earth, but is also a product of Chaos in the cosmogony of 116 ff. Yet this consideration, although it provides a sufficient motive for an irrelevant rhapsodic elaboration of the kind that Jacoby posited, really does nothing to support unity of authorship for the two adjacent passages. I agree with Jacoby, then, that what we are presented with in this part of the Theogony is a farrago of rhapsodic variants, juxtaposed inconsistently (for the most part) by the most mechanical principles, on the central theme of Tartaros.","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"4 1","pages":"10-12"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5000,"publicationDate":"1957-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S1750270500012161","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Cambridge Classical Journal","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1750270500012161","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"CLASSICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

Gregory Vlastos, in his interesting review of Cornford's Principium Sapientiae , in Gnomon , XXVII (1955), pp. 65ff., gives a particularly bald statement (p. 74 and n. 2) of a theory advanced in an article by Friedrich Solmsen, ‘Chaos and Apeiron’, Studi Italiani di Filologia Classica , n.s. XXIV (1950), pp. 235ff., and by Hermann Frankel in his Dichtung und Philosophie des fruhen Griechentums (New York, 1951), pp. 148–9. The theory is that Theogony 736–45 has a profound cosmogonical significance, and that it was probably from there that Anaximander derived and developed his idea of an originative ἄπeιρον. Now the Hesiodic passage is one of a group of variant descriptions of Tartaros that extend, as an appendix to the Titanomachy, from 726 to 819. Many of these descriptions are mutually inconsistent, and, although I would not go quite so far as Jacoby ( Hesiodi Carmina: pars I, Theogonia (Berlin, 1930), pp. 22 ff.) in asserting that they are certainly all later additions, most of them by different authors, it seems manifest that they cannot all be by the author of the Theogony as a whole—even accepting that this poem is to some extent a synthesis, not always elegant or consistent, of previous accounts. At all events no other part of the poem, including the cosmogony and theogony of 116 ff., manifests the piecemeal, repetitive and contradictory qualities of this series of descriptions of Tartaros. For example, 726–45 describes the underworld, and it is there that the halls of Night are located; but at 746 ff. there is a sudden transition to the far west, the region where Atlas stands and where Night exchanges with Day. Solmsen ( op. cit. p. 243, n. 2) tries to defend this unaccountable and irrelevant switch by showing that Night, earlier in the poem, is associated with the western parts of the earth, but is also a product of Chaos in the cosmogony of 116 ff. Yet this consideration, although it provides a sufficient motive for an irrelevant rhapsodic elaboration of the kind that Jacoby posited, really does nothing to support unity of authorship for the two adjacent passages. I agree with Jacoby, then, that what we are presented with in this part of the Theogony is a farrago of rhapsodic variants, juxtaposed inconsistently (for the most part) by the most mechanical principles, on the central theme of Tartaros.
赫西奥德的解释,神学,736页
格雷戈里·弗拉斯托斯,在他对康福德的《智慧原理》的有趣评论中,《Gnomon》,XXVII(1955),第65页。对弗里德里希·索姆森(Friedrich Solmsen)在《混沌与Apeiron》(Studi Italiani di Filologia Classica, n.s XXIV (1950), pp. 235ff)一篇文章中提出的一个理论,给出了一个特别直白的陈述(第74页和第2页)。,赫尔曼·弗兰克尔(Hermann Frankel)的《哲学与哲学》(Dichtung and Philosophie des fruhen griechentum)(纽约,1951),第148-9页。该理论认为,《神权论》736-45年具有深刻的宇宙演化意义,阿那克西曼德很可能就是从那里推导并发展了他关于原创的ν πeιρον的思想。赫西代的段落是一组对鞑靼人的不同描述之一,作为《泰坦之神》的附录,从726年延伸到819年。许多这些描述是相互矛盾的,虽然我不会像雅各比(Hesiodi Carmina: pars I, Theogonia (Berlin, 1930), pp. 22 ff.)那样断言它们肯定都是后来添加的,其中大多数是由不同的作者写的,但很明显,它们不可能都是由Theogonia的作者作为一个整体写的——即使接受这首诗在某种程度上是一个综合,并不总是优雅或一致的,以前的叙述。无论如何,这首诗的其他部分,包括第116章的宇宙起源论和神权论。,体现了这一系列Tartaros描述的零碎、重复和矛盾的特质。例如,726-45页描述了地下世界,暗夜大厅就在那里;但是在第746页。有一个突然的过渡到遥远的西部,阿特拉斯所在的地区,黑夜与白昼交替的地方。索姆森(同前第243页,第2页)试图为这种不可解释和无关的转换辩护,他指出,在诗歌的早期,夜与地球的西部有关,但也是116页宇宙演化中混沌的产物。然而,这种考虑,尽管它为雅各比所假设的那种不相关的狂想式阐述提供了充分的动机,但实际上并不能支持相邻两段作者的统一。我同意雅各比的观点,在《神权论》的这一部分,我们看到的是狂想曲变体的大杂烩,在塔塔罗斯的中心主题上,以最机械的原则不一致地(在很大程度上)并在一起。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.90
自引率
0.00%
发文量
13
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信