Refuge and Aid†

IF 2.9 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS
Victor Tadros
{"title":"Refuge and Aid†","authors":"Victor Tadros","doi":"10.1111/jopp.12286","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Horrific scenes of needy migrants attempting to enter wealthy countries, often after expensive, arduous, and dangerous journeys, move many to believe that more such migrants should be permitted to enter and reside. But there are also horrific scenes of desperately needy people at a distance from wealthy countries—the distant needy—who are persecuted by their states, internally displaced due to armed conflict, or who suffer from preventable disease, insecurity, malnutrition, homelessness, and poor education. Wealthy countries could use resources under their control to assist these people. Just migration policies are part of a more general scheme of international justice owed to needy migrants and the distant needy.</p><p>One question concerns the overall stringency and source of duties of the duties wealthy countries owe to the needy. Many will agree that they do too little. These obligations arise because wealthy countries exploit poorer countries by misusing economic and military power; or they have benefited from the historic unjust exercise of colonial power and economic exploitation; or the norms of distributive justice that apply due to (or independently of) global economic or institutional integration; or simply because of the general duty to assist those in need.</p><p>I explore the distinct issue of the comparison between duties owed to needy migrants and the distant needy. International law prioritizes at least some needy migrants over the distant needy. Some needy migrants have refugee status, resulting in legal obligations to protect them. But states owe no general legal obligations to assist the distant needy, even those facing identical threats to needy migrants. Needy migrants also figure more vividly in the popular imagination than the distant needy, leading people to fight more vociferously for improving immigration rights than for increased international aid.</p><p>I focus on cases where it is costly to assist needy people. I assume that wealthy countries have duties to impose costs on their citizens to assist needy people, and that particular wealthy countries are not required to assist all the needy people they can assist. Given this, who should be prioritized?</p><p>Section I briefly explores three factors that might seem relevant: distance, identity, and risk. Without exploring these issues in depth, I argue that they are unlikely to justify systematic prioritization of needy migrants over the distant needy. Section II explores whether needy migrants should be prioritized either because they are easier to assist or because the threats of wrongdoing that they face are especially grave. Neither factor typically supports assisting needy migrants over the distant needy. Sections III and IV consider whether duties to needy migrants are more stringent than duties to the distant needy because, unlike the distant needy, needy migrants will be harmed (or its moral equivalent) if they are prevented from making themselves safe by being excluded from territory controlled by wealthy states. This idea is forceful, but applies only to those needy migrants who do not rely on resources generated either by the wealthy state or by others. Section V explores whether wealthy states violate the rights of needy migrants because they fail to fulfil their duties to the distant needy. They do violate those rights, and this justifies fighting for more expansive immigration rights in non-ideal circumstances such as ours.</p><p>One argument for prioritizing needy migrants is that they have made costly efforts to get to wealthy countries. This can make a derivative difference. For example, prioritarians plausibly believe that duties to assist those who are worse off are stronger than duties to assist those who are better off. The fact that migrants have borne costs makes them worse off than some of the distant needy, so prioritarianism favours assisting them.</p><p>Some might argue that their being badly off is less significant because they chose to migrate. But many needy migrants act with inadequate information in the face of pressure and threats. Given that, their choices have relatively little importance in limiting duties owed to them. Nevertheless, this consideration does not typically favour prioritizing needy migrants. Even given migration costs, many needy migrants are no worse off than many of the distant needy.1</p><p>Some might argue we have more stringent duties to assist those who are striving to escape threats than those who passively accept those threats. We should reward their effort or help them to complete their valuable plans. Here are two reasons to doubt the significance of this. First, many of the distant needy are also strivers. They just don't strive to get to the shores of wealthy countries (or fail to get there). Furthermore, it is doubtful that striving is very significant in the real world, even if it matters in some ideal circumstances. Strivers often strive due to advantages that they have over non-strivers. People often don't strive because they find their circumstances hopeless, or because their confidence in success has been undermined by social injustice. When the contrast between strivers and non-strivers is explained in that way, it is at best much less important.</p><p>Here are three more arguments for prioritizing needy migrants. First, we have stronger duties to assist those near to us, and needy migrants are nearer than the distant needy. Second, we have stronger reasons to assist identified individuals than anonymous individuals, and needy migrants are identified individuals whereas the distant needy are not. Finally, because they have been identified, officials are aware that particular needy migrants face high risks of being harmed if nothing is done, whereas officials are not aware of particular needy non-migrants facing high risks of being harmed.</p><p>I cannot tackle the deeper issues involved in these arguments here. I am at least tempted by the view that none of these things is very significant. I doubt that considerations of distance and identity are morally important. And even if they are, it is questionable that they have political significance—any relevance they have might be more important in interpersonal moral relations than the relationship between states and individuals. And although I think that risk distribution is morally significant in itself, it is typically dwarfed by the significance of the outcomes that different risk profiles will bring about.</p><p>Rather than defend these views, I argue that these factors do little to support prioritizing needy migrants in practice, even if they are important in principle. One general reason is to do with the structure of political assistance for needy migrants and the distant needy. The ability of ground-level officials to assist different people depends on resource allocation at the policy level. When policy-makers decide how to allocate resources between the distant needy and needy migrants, though, the three factors under consideration do not favour needy migrants over the distant needy. The allocation of resources occurs in advance of conflicts between identifiable needy people without knowledge of different levels of risk faced by different people.</p><p>It might be objected that decisions of high-level policy-makers should depend on the duties officials on the ground will have given the circumstances they will face. Suppose that we have stronger duties to assist those who are nearby, for example, and that officials will be nearer to needy migrants than to the distant needy. Policy-makers who are equally distant from both groups should divert resources to assist needy migrants so that officials on the ground can satisfy their duties.</p><p>Even if this is right—and it is contentious—it doesn't normally favour needy migrants. Where officials and needy people will meet, who the officials are, and who the needy people are, depend on high-level policy decisions. For example, diverting resources to assist needy migrants rather than the distant needy results in the recruitment of many more people to assist needy migrants. These policies determine who is recruited. Furthermore, policies to assist needy migrants determine who will travel where: people are more likely to attempt to migrate to countries with more relaxed immigration policies. So, there will be more immigration officials near to more needy migrants.</p><p>But diverting resources to assist the distant needy will result in recruiting officials who will travel abroad to assist the distant needy. They will be nearer to the distant needy than to needy migrants, they will be more likely to be acquainted with the former, and the latter will be at significant risk from the epistemic perspective of these officials. So, overall, how resources are allocated determines who are identified, nearby, and (from the epistemic perspective of officials) at high risk. It is then hard to see how any more stringent duties owed based on these facts can have a profound effect on how resources must be allocated. Perhaps distance, identity, and risk matter. But they do not support policies prioritizing needy migrants.</p><p>Perhaps needy migrants should be prioritized because it is easy to help a person at the border, much more difficult to help those far away. One countervailing reason is that needy people might prefer to be assisted in their home country rather than having to migrate.2 This consideration, while significant, is only relevant when we are concerned with two different ways of assisting the same people. Normally, though, the choice is between helping some needy migrants or helping other distant needy people.</p><p>It is sometimes argued that restrictions on migration are less significant, and need not be justified on a democratic basis, because these restrictions prevent a person from securing a benefit rather than coercing them.16 This view treats coercion as especially hard to justify.17 The more important contrast, though, is between harming and failing to benefit.</p><p>We have seen that the origins of resources that assist different needy people make a significant difference to whom to prioritize.</p><p>It may seem from my discussion that many needy migrants are not wronged by wealthy states who prevent them from entering their territory. Particular wealthy states need not help everyone, let us assume. No particular needy migrant has a right to assistance, because no needy migrant has priority over other needy people. As no needy migrant has a right to be saved, wealthy states do not wrong any particular needy migrant by failing to save that migrant. It might also seem that the range of legal protections that wealthy countries should offer to needy migrants should be narrow—it should restrict the right to protection to those for whom access to territory is sufficient to avert the threats they face, or of whom that would be true if the territory had not been altered by the wealthy country. My arguments, therefore, might seem to support restrictive migration policies that are typically adopted and endorsed by right-wing political parties in wealthy countries. Here is why this is not so.</p><p>The view outlined only implies that wealthy countries do not wrong migrants if they fulfil duties to assist the distant needy. If wealthy countries do not do enough to assist the distant needy, they violate the rights of needy migrants by excluding them. That has implications for how we should understand the ethics of migration, and our duty to fight for justice for needy migrants. The issue is especially important because wealthy states surely do not do enough to assist those in need, and right-wing political parties are especially inclined to this wrongdoing.28</p><p>Begin with the general problem where an individual or state lacks an obligation to assist all members of a large group in need, which we are assuming of particular wealthy states. Suppose that there is some large class of people {X1–X<i>n</i>} who are identically placed. X1 claims a right to assistance against some individual or state, Y, where assistance is costly. The argument we are considering is:</p><p>The action is in premise 2). Is it true that if Y lacks a duty to assist all members of some group, she lacks a duty to assist each member of that group?</p><p>Here is how we might bolster that premise. Y owes X1 a duty to perform some act, <i>v</i>, only if Y would wrong X1 by not performing <i>v</i> (at least pro tanto). Where rescuing all is too costly for Y to be required to do this, Y could assist other members of {X1–X<i>n</i>} without wronging X1. Therefore, Y does not owe X1 a duty to rescue her. This argument rests on a relatively uncontroversial view about duties—a person owes another a duty to <i>v</i> iff that person would necessarily wrong the other were she not to <i>v</i>.</p><p>Still, the argument can be resisted. Here is one way. Perhaps Y has a pro tanto duty to rescue each member of {X1–X<i>n</i>} that is owed to each member of that group. Y violates each pro tanto duty unless she is justified in breaching it. But she is justified in breaching it only if she <i>in fact</i> saves some other members of {X1–X<i>n</i>}. Thus, X1 has a pro tanto right to be saved that is violated if Y rescues no one. Thus, Y wrongs X1 by not saving her unless Y saves sufficient members of the group so that her not bearing costs to save X1 is justified. Indeed, she wrongs all members of {X1–X<i>n</i>}.</p><p>Following my suggestion earlier, Matt lacks a right to be saved simpliciter. Matt has a right to be saved iff my failing to save him necessarily wrongs him. If I save Nat, I don't wrong him. Therefore, he lacks a right to be saved. But as our analysis of <i>Matt or Cat</i> shows, this does not imply that Matt lacks a right to be saved <i>if I save no one</i>. Compare <i>Matt or Cat</i>: Matt lacked a right to be saved simpliciter, in that my failing to save him does not necessarily wrong him, but he has a right to be saved <i>if I bear the cost of death</i>. Similarly, Matt lacks a right to be saved in <i>Matt or Nat</i> simpliciter, but has a right to be saved <i>if I don't save Nat</i>. The option of saving Nat makes it true that Matt lacks a right to be saved simpliciter. If I don't take this option, I violate Matt's right—his right to be saved <i>if I don't save Nat</i>.</p><p>Similarly, many needy migrants lack rights to be saved simpliciter. Wealthy countries would not wrong them were they to devote sufficient resources to assist the distant needy. But they have rights to be saved if wealthy countries do not use sufficient resources to assist the distant needy.</p><p>Some may think things are different where the distant needy have priority over needy migrants. In <i>Matt or Nat</i>, I was permitted to save either Matt or Nat. But wealthy countries are often required to spend their resources on international development aid. Does this make a difference? I think not.</p><p>Thus, even if many needy migrants lack rights to be saved simpliciter, because wealthy countries need not assist everyone, and they lack priority over the distant needy, their rights may nevertheless be violated. In the real world, where wealthy countries do too little in general to fulfil their duties of assistance, all needy people are wronged, even those who are at the back of the queue.</p><p>Suppose that this argument is resisted, perhaps because it proliferates rights violations too far. We might then retreat to a narrower view about cases where a person can help themselves to resources that are under the control of the wealthy, which the wealthy will retain, but which they are required use to help others.</p><p>Needy migrants are in a similar position to Y in <i>Selfish Prevention</i>. They sometimes seek to escape harm in circumstances where wealthy countries could permissibly exclude them and help the distant needy. But wealthy countries will not do this, and these migrants are normally in no position to ensure that the distant needy are helped. They can only help themselves. Wealthy countries are permitted to prevent them from helping themselves in order to assist the distant needy. But they are not permitted to prevent them from helping themselves without doing this.</p><p>On this basis we might also justify campaigns to expand assistance to refugees. We know that wealthy countries are very unlikely to fulfil their obligations to assist needy people by providing sufficient development aid. So, we also know that they will violate the rights of needy migrants; even those who need access to resources developed by wealthy countries. If the prospects of securing sufficient development aid look dim, and if there are better prospects of securing assistance for needy migrants, we should fight to expand legal immigration rights, even though this will result in states acting unjustly.</p><p>There is often little reason to prioritize assisting needy migrants over the distant needy, and sometimes a strong reason to prioritize the latter group. This does not imply that we should accept the status quo in refugee and migration policy where only a narrow range of needy migrants is legally entitled to secure access to wealthy countries through restrictive refugee laws. Fighting to expand those laws is justified, if doing so will secure better protection for needy migrants, given how unlikely it is that wealthy states will fulfil their obligation to the distant needy. In doing so, we ensure that wealthy countries do not violate the conditional rights of needy migrants.</p><p>Often, there will be no conflict in our ambitions to ensure that the needy receive the assistance they are entitled to—we can support both expanded migration policies and international aid, confident that we will have made a positive contribution if we achieve anything at all. But we do sometimes face choices about what to promote—which charities to support, which policies NGOs should adopt, which questions to ask of our governments, and which injustices to highlight in our media outlets. In general, where such conflicts arise, our priority should be compelling our governments to fulfil their duties to provide international aid.</p>","PeriodicalId":47624,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Political Philosophy","volume":"31 1","pages":"102-125"},"PeriodicalIF":2.9000,"publicationDate":"2022-11-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jopp.12286","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Political Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jopp.12286","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Horrific scenes of needy migrants attempting to enter wealthy countries, often after expensive, arduous, and dangerous journeys, move many to believe that more such migrants should be permitted to enter and reside. But there are also horrific scenes of desperately needy people at a distance from wealthy countries—the distant needy—who are persecuted by their states, internally displaced due to armed conflict, or who suffer from preventable disease, insecurity, malnutrition, homelessness, and poor education. Wealthy countries could use resources under their control to assist these people. Just migration policies are part of a more general scheme of international justice owed to needy migrants and the distant needy.

One question concerns the overall stringency and source of duties of the duties wealthy countries owe to the needy. Many will agree that they do too little. These obligations arise because wealthy countries exploit poorer countries by misusing economic and military power; or they have benefited from the historic unjust exercise of colonial power and economic exploitation; or the norms of distributive justice that apply due to (or independently of) global economic or institutional integration; or simply because of the general duty to assist those in need.

I explore the distinct issue of the comparison between duties owed to needy migrants and the distant needy. International law prioritizes at least some needy migrants over the distant needy. Some needy migrants have refugee status, resulting in legal obligations to protect them. But states owe no general legal obligations to assist the distant needy, even those facing identical threats to needy migrants. Needy migrants also figure more vividly in the popular imagination than the distant needy, leading people to fight more vociferously for improving immigration rights than for increased international aid.

I focus on cases where it is costly to assist needy people. I assume that wealthy countries have duties to impose costs on their citizens to assist needy people, and that particular wealthy countries are not required to assist all the needy people they can assist. Given this, who should be prioritized?

Section I briefly explores three factors that might seem relevant: distance, identity, and risk. Without exploring these issues in depth, I argue that they are unlikely to justify systematic prioritization of needy migrants over the distant needy. Section II explores whether needy migrants should be prioritized either because they are easier to assist or because the threats of wrongdoing that they face are especially grave. Neither factor typically supports assisting needy migrants over the distant needy. Sections III and IV consider whether duties to needy migrants are more stringent than duties to the distant needy because, unlike the distant needy, needy migrants will be harmed (or its moral equivalent) if they are prevented from making themselves safe by being excluded from territory controlled by wealthy states. This idea is forceful, but applies only to those needy migrants who do not rely on resources generated either by the wealthy state or by others. Section V explores whether wealthy states violate the rights of needy migrants because they fail to fulfil their duties to the distant needy. They do violate those rights, and this justifies fighting for more expansive immigration rights in non-ideal circumstances such as ours.

One argument for prioritizing needy migrants is that they have made costly efforts to get to wealthy countries. This can make a derivative difference. For example, prioritarians plausibly believe that duties to assist those who are worse off are stronger than duties to assist those who are better off. The fact that migrants have borne costs makes them worse off than some of the distant needy, so prioritarianism favours assisting them.

Some might argue that their being badly off is less significant because they chose to migrate. But many needy migrants act with inadequate information in the face of pressure and threats. Given that, their choices have relatively little importance in limiting duties owed to them. Nevertheless, this consideration does not typically favour prioritizing needy migrants. Even given migration costs, many needy migrants are no worse off than many of the distant needy.1

Some might argue we have more stringent duties to assist those who are striving to escape threats than those who passively accept those threats. We should reward their effort or help them to complete their valuable plans. Here are two reasons to doubt the significance of this. First, many of the distant needy are also strivers. They just don't strive to get to the shores of wealthy countries (or fail to get there). Furthermore, it is doubtful that striving is very significant in the real world, even if it matters in some ideal circumstances. Strivers often strive due to advantages that they have over non-strivers. People often don't strive because they find their circumstances hopeless, or because their confidence in success has been undermined by social injustice. When the contrast between strivers and non-strivers is explained in that way, it is at best much less important.

Here are three more arguments for prioritizing needy migrants. First, we have stronger duties to assist those near to us, and needy migrants are nearer than the distant needy. Second, we have stronger reasons to assist identified individuals than anonymous individuals, and needy migrants are identified individuals whereas the distant needy are not. Finally, because they have been identified, officials are aware that particular needy migrants face high risks of being harmed if nothing is done, whereas officials are not aware of particular needy non-migrants facing high risks of being harmed.

I cannot tackle the deeper issues involved in these arguments here. I am at least tempted by the view that none of these things is very significant. I doubt that considerations of distance and identity are morally important. And even if they are, it is questionable that they have political significance—any relevance they have might be more important in interpersonal moral relations than the relationship between states and individuals. And although I think that risk distribution is morally significant in itself, it is typically dwarfed by the significance of the outcomes that different risk profiles will bring about.

Rather than defend these views, I argue that these factors do little to support prioritizing needy migrants in practice, even if they are important in principle. One general reason is to do with the structure of political assistance for needy migrants and the distant needy. The ability of ground-level officials to assist different people depends on resource allocation at the policy level. When policy-makers decide how to allocate resources between the distant needy and needy migrants, though, the three factors under consideration do not favour needy migrants over the distant needy. The allocation of resources occurs in advance of conflicts between identifiable needy people without knowledge of different levels of risk faced by different people.

It might be objected that decisions of high-level policy-makers should depend on the duties officials on the ground will have given the circumstances they will face. Suppose that we have stronger duties to assist those who are nearby, for example, and that officials will be nearer to needy migrants than to the distant needy. Policy-makers who are equally distant from both groups should divert resources to assist needy migrants so that officials on the ground can satisfy their duties.

Even if this is right—and it is contentious—it doesn't normally favour needy migrants. Where officials and needy people will meet, who the officials are, and who the needy people are, depend on high-level policy decisions. For example, diverting resources to assist needy migrants rather than the distant needy results in the recruitment of many more people to assist needy migrants. These policies determine who is recruited. Furthermore, policies to assist needy migrants determine who will travel where: people are more likely to attempt to migrate to countries with more relaxed immigration policies. So, there will be more immigration officials near to more needy migrants.

But diverting resources to assist the distant needy will result in recruiting officials who will travel abroad to assist the distant needy. They will be nearer to the distant needy than to needy migrants, they will be more likely to be acquainted with the former, and the latter will be at significant risk from the epistemic perspective of these officials. So, overall, how resources are allocated determines who are identified, nearby, and (from the epistemic perspective of officials) at high risk. It is then hard to see how any more stringent duties owed based on these facts can have a profound effect on how resources must be allocated. Perhaps distance, identity, and risk matter. But they do not support policies prioritizing needy migrants.

Perhaps needy migrants should be prioritized because it is easy to help a person at the border, much more difficult to help those far away. One countervailing reason is that needy people might prefer to be assisted in their home country rather than having to migrate.2 This consideration, while significant, is only relevant when we are concerned with two different ways of assisting the same people. Normally, though, the choice is between helping some needy migrants or helping other distant needy people.

It is sometimes argued that restrictions on migration are less significant, and need not be justified on a democratic basis, because these restrictions prevent a person from securing a benefit rather than coercing them.16 This view treats coercion as especially hard to justify.17 The more important contrast, though, is between harming and failing to benefit.

We have seen that the origins of resources that assist different needy people make a significant difference to whom to prioritize.

It may seem from my discussion that many needy migrants are not wronged by wealthy states who prevent them from entering their territory. Particular wealthy states need not help everyone, let us assume. No particular needy migrant has a right to assistance, because no needy migrant has priority over other needy people. As no needy migrant has a right to be saved, wealthy states do not wrong any particular needy migrant by failing to save that migrant. It might also seem that the range of legal protections that wealthy countries should offer to needy migrants should be narrow—it should restrict the right to protection to those for whom access to territory is sufficient to avert the threats they face, or of whom that would be true if the territory had not been altered by the wealthy country. My arguments, therefore, might seem to support restrictive migration policies that are typically adopted and endorsed by right-wing political parties in wealthy countries. Here is why this is not so.

The view outlined only implies that wealthy countries do not wrong migrants if they fulfil duties to assist the distant needy. If wealthy countries do not do enough to assist the distant needy, they violate the rights of needy migrants by excluding them. That has implications for how we should understand the ethics of migration, and our duty to fight for justice for needy migrants. The issue is especially important because wealthy states surely do not do enough to assist those in need, and right-wing political parties are especially inclined to this wrongdoing.28

Begin with the general problem where an individual or state lacks an obligation to assist all members of a large group in need, which we are assuming of particular wealthy states. Suppose that there is some large class of people {X1–Xn} who are identically placed. X1 claims a right to assistance against some individual or state, Y, where assistance is costly. The argument we are considering is:

The action is in premise 2). Is it true that if Y lacks a duty to assist all members of some group, she lacks a duty to assist each member of that group?

Here is how we might bolster that premise. Y owes X1 a duty to perform some act, v, only if Y would wrong X1 by not performing v (at least pro tanto). Where rescuing all is too costly for Y to be required to do this, Y could assist other members of {X1–Xn} without wronging X1. Therefore, Y does not owe X1 a duty to rescue her. This argument rests on a relatively uncontroversial view about duties—a person owes another a duty to v iff that person would necessarily wrong the other were she not to v.

Still, the argument can be resisted. Here is one way. Perhaps Y has a pro tanto duty to rescue each member of {X1–Xn} that is owed to each member of that group. Y violates each pro tanto duty unless she is justified in breaching it. But she is justified in breaching it only if she in fact saves some other members of {X1–Xn}. Thus, X1 has a pro tanto right to be saved that is violated if Y rescues no one. Thus, Y wrongs X1 by not saving her unless Y saves sufficient members of the group so that her not bearing costs to save X1 is justified. Indeed, she wrongs all members of {X1–Xn}.

Following my suggestion earlier, Matt lacks a right to be saved simpliciter. Matt has a right to be saved iff my failing to save him necessarily wrongs him. If I save Nat, I don't wrong him. Therefore, he lacks a right to be saved. But as our analysis of Matt or Cat shows, this does not imply that Matt lacks a right to be saved if I save no one. Compare Matt or Cat: Matt lacked a right to be saved simpliciter, in that my failing to save him does not necessarily wrong him, but he has a right to be saved if I bear the cost of death. Similarly, Matt lacks a right to be saved in Matt or Nat simpliciter, but has a right to be saved if I don't save Nat. The option of saving Nat makes it true that Matt lacks a right to be saved simpliciter. If I don't take this option, I violate Matt's right—his right to be saved if I don't save Nat.

Similarly, many needy migrants lack rights to be saved simpliciter. Wealthy countries would not wrong them were they to devote sufficient resources to assist the distant needy. But they have rights to be saved if wealthy countries do not use sufficient resources to assist the distant needy.

Some may think things are different where the distant needy have priority over needy migrants. In Matt or Nat, I was permitted to save either Matt or Nat. But wealthy countries are often required to spend their resources on international development aid. Does this make a difference? I think not.

Thus, even if many needy migrants lack rights to be saved simpliciter, because wealthy countries need not assist everyone, and they lack priority over the distant needy, their rights may nevertheless be violated. In the real world, where wealthy countries do too little in general to fulfil their duties of assistance, all needy people are wronged, even those who are at the back of the queue.

Suppose that this argument is resisted, perhaps because it proliferates rights violations too far. We might then retreat to a narrower view about cases where a person can help themselves to resources that are under the control of the wealthy, which the wealthy will retain, but which they are required use to help others.

Needy migrants are in a similar position to Y in Selfish Prevention. They sometimes seek to escape harm in circumstances where wealthy countries could permissibly exclude them and help the distant needy. But wealthy countries will not do this, and these migrants are normally in no position to ensure that the distant needy are helped. They can only help themselves. Wealthy countries are permitted to prevent them from helping themselves in order to assist the distant needy. But they are not permitted to prevent them from helping themselves without doing this.

On this basis we might also justify campaigns to expand assistance to refugees. We know that wealthy countries are very unlikely to fulfil their obligations to assist needy people by providing sufficient development aid. So, we also know that they will violate the rights of needy migrants; even those who need access to resources developed by wealthy countries. If the prospects of securing sufficient development aid look dim, and if there are better prospects of securing assistance for needy migrants, we should fight to expand legal immigration rights, even though this will result in states acting unjustly.

There is often little reason to prioritize assisting needy migrants over the distant needy, and sometimes a strong reason to prioritize the latter group. This does not imply that we should accept the status quo in refugee and migration policy where only a narrow range of needy migrants is legally entitled to secure access to wealthy countries through restrictive refugee laws. Fighting to expand those laws is justified, if doing so will secure better protection for needy migrants, given how unlikely it is that wealthy states will fulfil their obligation to the distant needy. In doing so, we ensure that wealthy countries do not violate the conditional rights of needy migrants.

Often, there will be no conflict in our ambitions to ensure that the needy receive the assistance they are entitled to—we can support both expanded migration policies and international aid, confident that we will have made a positive contribution if we achieve anything at all. But we do sometimes face choices about what to promote—which charities to support, which policies NGOs should adopt, which questions to ask of our governments, and which injustices to highlight in our media outlets. In general, where such conflicts arise, our priority should be compelling our governments to fulfil their duties to provide international aid.

避难和援助†
贫困移民试图进入富裕国家的可怕场景,通常是在昂贵、艰苦和危险的旅程之后,让许多人相信应该允许更多这样的移民进入和居住。但也有一些可怕的场景,那些与富裕国家相距甚远的极度贫困的人——那些遥远的贫困者——他们受到国家迫害,因武装冲突而在国内流离失所,或者患有可预防的疾病、不安全、营养不良、无家可归和教育水平低下。富裕国家可以利用其控制下的资源来帮助这些人。公正的移民政策是欠贫困移民和遥远贫困者的更普遍的国际正义计划的一部分。一个问题涉及富裕国家对贫困者的义务的总体严格性和来源。许多人会同意他们做得太少。这些义务的产生是因为富裕国家滥用经济和军事力量剥削贫穷国家;或者他们从历史上不公正地行使殖民权力和经济剥削中获益;或由于(或独立于)全球经济或体制一体化而适用的分配正义规范;或者仅仅是因为帮助那些需要帮助的人的一般义务。我探讨了对贫困移民和远方贫困者的义务之间的比较这一独特问题。国际法至少优先考虑一些有需要的移民,而不是遥远的有需要的人。一些有需要的移民具有难民身份,因此有法律义务保护他们。但各州没有一般的法律义务来帮助远方的穷人,即使是那些面临与贫困移民相同威胁的人。贫困的移民在大众的想象中也比遥远的贫困者更形象,这导致人们为改善移民权利而非增加国际援助而更加激烈地斗争。我关注的是那些援助贫困人口成本高昂的案例。我认为,富裕国家有义务向其公民征收费用,以帮助有需要的人,而特定的富裕国家不需要帮助他们所能帮助的所有有困难的人。鉴于此,谁应该被优先考虑?第一节简要探讨了三个看似相关的因素:距离、身份和风险。如果不深入探讨这些问题,我认为它们不太可能证明有系统地优先考虑贫困移民而不是遥远的贫困人口。第二节探讨了贫困移民是否应该被优先考虑,要么是因为他们更容易得到帮助,要么是由于他们面临的不法行为威胁特别严重。这两个因素通常都不支持帮助贫困移民,而不是遥远的贫困人口。第三节和第四节考虑了对贫困移民的义务是否比对遥远贫困者的义务更严格,因为与遥远贫困者不同,如果贫困移民被排除在富裕国家控制的领土之外,无法确保自己的安全,他们将受到伤害(或道德上的同等伤害)。这一想法很有说服力,但只适用于那些不依赖富裕国家或其他国家产生的资源的贫困移民。第五节探讨富裕国家是否因为未能履行对遥远贫困者的义务而侵犯了贫困移民的权利。他们确实侵犯了这些权利,这证明了在像我们这样的非理想情况下争取更广泛的移民权利是正当的。优先考虑贫困移民的一个论点是,他们为前往富裕国家付出了代价高昂的努力。这可能会产生衍生差异。例如,优先主义者似乎认为,帮助那些境况较差的人的责任比帮助那些境况较好的人的义务更大。移民承担了成本,这一事实使他们的境况比一些遥远的穷人更糟,因此优先主义倾向于帮助他们。有些人可能会说,由于他们选择了移民,他们的经济状况并不那么严重。但许多有需要的移民在面对压力和威胁时信息不足。考虑到这一点,他们的选择在限制对他们的责任方面相对没有什么重要性。然而,这种考虑通常不赞成优先考虑有需要的移民。即使考虑到移民成本,许多贫困移民的境况也不比许多遥远的贫困者差。1有些人可能会说,我们有更严格的职责来帮助那些努力逃避威胁的人,而不是那些被动接受这些威胁的人。我们应该奖励他们的努力或帮助他们完成有价值的计划。有两个理由怀疑这一点的重要性。首先,许多遥远的穷人也是奋斗者。他们只是不努力到达富裕国家的海岸(或者没能到达那里)。此外,即使在某些理想的情况下,努力在现实世界中是否意义重大,也是值得怀疑的。奋斗者的奋斗往往是因为他们比非奋斗者有优势。 17然而,更重要的对比是伤害和未能从中受益。我们已经看到,帮助不同贫困人群的资源的来源对优先考虑谁产生了重大影响。从我的讨论中可以看出,许多贫困的移民并没有因为富裕国家阻止他们进入自己的领土而受到委屈。让我们假设,特定的富裕国家不需要帮助所有人。没有一个特定的贫困移民有权获得援助,因为没有一个贫困移民优先于其他贫困人口。由于没有一个有需要的移民有被拯救的权利,富裕国家不会因为没有拯救移民而责怪任何特定的有需要的人。富裕国家应该为贫困移民提供的法律保护范围似乎也应该很窄——它应该将获得保护的权利限制在那些进入领土足以避免他们面临威胁的人,或者如果富裕国家没有改变领土,他们的权利也会是真的。因此,我的论点似乎支持富裕国家右翼政党通常采用和支持的限制性移民政策。这就是为什么情况并非如此。所概述的观点只意味着,如果富裕国家履行了帮助远方贫困者的职责,他们就不会冤枉移民。如果富裕国家在帮助遥远的穷人方面做得不够,他们就会将贫困移民排除在外,从而侵犯他们的权利。这对我们应该如何理解移民的道德以及我们为贫困移民争取正义的义务产生了影响。这个问题尤其重要,因为富裕国家在帮助那些需要帮助的人方面肯定做得不够,而右翼政党尤其倾向于这种错误。28从一个普遍的问题开始,一个个人或国家没有义务帮助一个大群体中所有需要帮助的成员,这是我们对特定富裕国家的假设。假设有一大类人{X1–Xn}的位置相同。X1主张对某些个人或州Y享有援助权利,在那里援助费用高昂。我们正在考虑的论点是:行动是在前提2中进行的。如果Y没有义务帮助某个群体的所有成员,那么她真的没有义务帮助该群体的每个成员吗?以下是我们如何支持这一前提。只有当Y不执行某个动作v(至少是protanto)会使X1出错时,Y才有义务执行某个行为v。如果拯救所有人的成本太高,Y不需要这样做,Y可以在不冤枉X1的情况下帮助{X1–Xn}的其他成员。因此,Y没有义务营救X1。这一论点基于一种相对没有争议的关于义务的观点——一个人对另一个人负有义务,如果她不这样做,那么这个人必然会错。这里有一种方法。也许Y有义务拯救{X1–Xn}中的每一个成员,这是对该群体每一位成员的亏欠。Y违反了每一项义务,除非她有正当理由违反义务。但只有当她实际上拯救了{X1–Xn}的其他成员时,她才有正当理由违背义务。因此,如果Y没有营救任何人,X1就有被营救的权利。因此,Y不救X1是错误的,除非Y救了足够的组成员,这样她就有理由不承担救X1的费用。事实上,她冤枉了{X1–Xn}的所有成员。根据我之前的建议,马特缺乏被简化的权利。马特有被救的权利,如果我没能救他一定会冤枉他。如果我救了纳特,我不会错的。因此,他缺乏被拯救的权利。但正如我们对马特或猫的分析所表明的那样,这并不意味着如果我不救任何人,马特就没有被救的权利。比较马特或猫:马特缺乏被救的权利,因为我没能救他并不一定是错的,但如果我承担死亡的代价,他有权被救。同样,Matt在Matt或Nat simpliciter中没有被救的权利,但如果我不救Nat,他就有被救的权力。救Nat的选择使Matt确实没有被救Simplicitter的权利。如果我不选择这个选项,我就侵犯了马特的权利——如果我不救纳特,他就有权被救。同样,许多贫困的移民也缺乏被救的权利。如果富裕国家投入足够的资源来帮助遥远的穷人,他们不会错的。但是,如果富裕国家不使用足够的资源来帮助遥远的穷人,他们就有权得到拯救。有些人可能认为情况有所不同,遥远的穷人优先于贫困的移民。在马特或纳特,我被允许拯救马特或纳特。但富裕国家经常被要求将资源用于国际发展援助。这有什么不同吗?我想不是。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
4.10
自引率
5.60%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: The Journal of Political Philosophy is an international journal devoted to the study of theoretical issues arising out of moral, legal and political life. It welcomes, and hopes to foster, work cutting across a variety of disciplinary concerns, among them philosophy, sociology, history, economics and political science. The journal encourages new approaches, including (but not limited to): feminism; environmentalism; critical theory, post-modernism and analytical Marxism; social and public choice theory; law and economics, critical legal studies and critical race studies; and game theoretic, socio-biological and anthropological approaches to politics. It also welcomes work in the history of political thought which builds to a larger philosophical point and work in the philosophy of the social sciences and applied ethics with broader political implications. Featuring a distinguished editorial board from major centres of thought from around the globe, the journal draws equally upon the work of non-philosophers and philosophers and provides a forum of debate between disparate factions who usually keep to their own separate journals.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信