Debate: Legitimate injustice: A response to Wellman

IF 2.9 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS
Jonathan Quong
{"title":"Debate: Legitimate injustice: A response to Wellman","authors":"Jonathan Quong","doi":"10.1111/jopp.12293","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>In his article, “The Space between Justice and Legitimacy”, Kit Wellman offers a novel account of the relationship between political philosophy's two central concepts.1 He argues that states can be legitimate yet impose many unjust laws and policies. This is true, he suggests, because political legitimacy should be understood as a claim about <i>wide proportionality</i>.2 Just as a country's war can be widely proportionate overall, and yet contain many instances of injustice, states can be proportionate (that is, legitimate) overall, yet contain a fair amount of injustice. But although Wellman thinks legitimate injustice is, in this sense, a real and pervasive phenomenon, he goes on to argue that legitimacy doesn't have much practical relevance with regard to unjust laws and policies. It doesn't make it permissible to impose and enforce unjust laws, nor does it generate an obligation to comply with unjust laws.</p><p>Like Wellman, I think legitimate injustice is real and pervasive. But I don't share his view of this phenomenon and, as a result, I also don't agree with him about the practical implications of legitimate injustice. Contra Wellman, I think state officials can act permissibly when they enforce unjust but legitimate law, and I think they have claim rights against being interfered with when they do so.</p><p>Before we begin, it will help to clarify what's at stake in labeling a state legitimate. There are many competing conceptions of political legitimacy in the literature, but, as Wellman says, “virtually everyone agrees that legitimacy at least entitles a state to coerce its constituents”.3 Following Wellman, I will assume this is, at a minimum, what's at stake in determining whether a state is legitimate. Other things being equal, a legitimate political authority is presumptively permitted to coerce its constituents in at least some ways that illegitimate authorities are not permitted to do.</p><p>Wellman believes legitimate states can act unjustly, and he defends this view by appeal to a particular notion of proportionality. Just as it can be morally permissible to launch a war even when we can foresee that some of our troops will commit unjust crimes during its course, a state can be legitimate even though we know it sometimes commits injustice. In both cases, we weigh the good things that will be achieved if we proceed against all the harms or costs that will be caused. Provided the goods are sufficiently great to outweigh the harms or costs, the proposed course of action or the institution can be defended on the basis that the benefits are proportionate relative to the costs.4 As Wellman puts it, “Because states perform such incredibly valuable functions … they are worth at least some moral costs”.5 This is, on Wellman's view, simply what it is for a state to be legitimate. When the benefits the state provides are proportionate relative to the costs (including the injustices the state commits), the state is morally legitimate.</p><p>This is an innovative way of thinking about the relationship between justice and political legitimacy. But I do not think it can be correct. In the ethics of self-defense and war, the standard way to determine whether some act is proportionate is to weigh the costs and benefits that will be caused by our action against the alternative of doing nothing.6 Suppose the only way to defend one innocent person from having her legs unjustly broken is by throwing a grenade that will kill two innocent bystanders. The act of throwing the grenade is not proportionate, because the costs of doing so (two innocent people are killed) are much worse than the alternative of doing nothing (one innocent person's legs get broken). If, however, these costs were reversed—if doing nothing meant two innocent people get killed, whereas throwing the grenade meant only one innocent person's legs get broken—then we might conclude throwing the grenade is proportionate.</p><p>If we are to use wide proportionality to assess a state's legitimacy, we need to engage in a similar comparison. The difficulty, however, is that the state is unlike a harmful act that we contemplate performing, and so it's less clear what it might mean to ask, “are the costs created by the state proportionate relative to the alternative of doing nothing?”. How should we understand the benchmark of “doing nothing”?</p><p>But this doesn't look like a good test. First, it's not clear what we are supposed to imagine occurs if the government or the state is dismantled. Maybe we should consider what would realistically occur in this particular country if its government or state apparatus suddenly ceased to exist. In many cases, what would occur might be terrible. In some places, civil war or ethnic cleansing might be the consequence of suddenly dismantling a government. In these cases, we would not be morally required to disband the government even if it were very, very bad. Even a brutal authoritarian regime might be preferable to civil war or ethnic cleansing, but surely that does not make a brutal authoritarian regime morally legitimate; it does not give that regime the moral permission to coerce its citizens to do things that they are not independently required to do. A regime is not morally legitimate merely because it is preferable to some of the worst conditions on earth.8</p><p>One problem with trying to conceptualize political legitimacy as a species of proportionality is that we almost never face a binary choice between our current political institutions as they are or else the total absence of those political institutions. Consider the Southern United States during the Jim Crow era. If the only two options were (1) retain the existing racist laws and institutions, or (2) a descent into an extremely dangerous form of anarchy, it's at least possible that option (1) might be widely proportionate relative to the benchmark of (2). But, of course, those weren't the only two options. Radically reforming the existing laws and institutions to make them less racist and unjust was a feasible option, and the very fact that it was a feasible option is surely part of the explanation as to why the racist political institutions might not have been morally legitimate.</p><p>But Wellman's statement here is puzzling for two reasons. First, this isn't how proportionality has standardly been conceptualized in the ethics of self-defense and war. As I've already explained, proportionality judgments are typically made by comparing a given act of harm-imposition relative to the benchmark of doing nothing. The entire set of feasible alternatives, however, is relevant with regard to a different moral judgment, namely, <i>necessity</i>. Philosophers working on self-defense and war typically claim that for an instance of harm-imposition to be morally permissible it must meet the condition of being necessary. Although there is a great deal of disagreement about how exactly to conceptualize the necessity condition, there is widespread agreement that judgments of necessity are made by comparing the potential act of harm-imposition to all the feasible alternatives.10 Killing a wrongful aggressor, for example, is not necessary if one of the defender's feasible alternatives is painlessly rendering the aggressor unconscious. Thus, although it's a matter of some dispute, on the most widely accepted picture, wide proportionality and necessity are two separate constraints on the permissible use of force. To be morally permissible, it's generally believed a harmful act must, among other things, satisfy both these constraints.</p><p>This test isn't helpful if we seek to explain how any existing state could ever be legitimate. It's surely true that every existing state has at least some unjust laws or unjust institutions which could be reformed to eliminate the injustice without becoming more unjust in other ways. It's thus true that, for every existing state, the status quo is not proportionate relative to a feasible alternative, and thus every existing state is illegitimate. The problem is even more stark, since this view has the implication that even hypothetical states that are far more just than any existing state would still be illegitimate so long as they contain even a single unjust law or institution that could feasibly be reformed. I think it's clear that these are not the conclusions Wellman seeks to defend.</p><p>Wellman might reply that it's not feasible for a state to be entirely devoid of unjust laws or institutions; realistically, our best efforts to design and sustain political institutions will always contain some unjust features. But this reply involves shifting from the standard of “feasible” to the standard of “probable” or “likely”. Although the term feasible is contested,11 I suspect it's most commonly used to refer to whether achieving a given outcome is possible given our resources and technological limitations. In this sense, changing the laws regulating gun ownership in the US is clearly feasible. Of course, it is extremely unlikely that robust gun control legislation will be enacted in the US for reasons of ideology and political self-interest.</p><p>Suppose, then, we take All Alternatives to refer only to those alternatives that are sufficiently likely to obtain. This would then vastly lower the bar for legitimacy. Even highly unjust states can be legitimate so long as it is sufficiently unlikely that they will become more just.</p><p>The problem with this interpretation, however, is fairly obvious. It's often the case that laws or institutions are unlikely to be reformed because those who hold power don't want to reform them. It might, for example, be very unlikely that we can reform the unjust institutions in a country because the country is ruled by a tyrant who refuses to relinquish power and rules by violently suppressing dissent. On this interpretation, the tyrant can render his rule legitimate by forming a settled disposition to hang on to power through unjust means. I take this result to be a reductio of the proposed interpretation of the proportionality test.</p><p>In sum, I don't see how the idea of wide proportionality can be made to work as an account of political legitimacy. One test for proportionality that Wellman seems to suggest—Dismantle—is far too weak a standard. It's too weak, in part, because it ignores the fact that we never face a binary choice between the status quo and dismantling the state. We always have many other feasible alternatives, which include reforming the unjust laws and institutions of our state. But the other test that Wellman floats—All Alternatives—creates either an unacceptably high standard or an unacceptably low one. If we focus on all feasible alternatives, then the bar for legitimacy is far too high—no existing state meets it and no hypothetical state with even a single unjust law meets it. But if we focus on likely or probable alternatives, then the bar is too low: very bad actors can render themselves legitimate by refusing to meet minimal moral standards they could meet if they wanted to.</p><p>In each case Wellman argues that the answer is “no”. So, although legitimate states act unjustly, the fact that these injustices are perpetrated by legitimate states doesn't have many interesting practical consequences for the unjust laws the state attempts to impose. The state's legitimacy doesn't give it a special permission to act unjustly, it doesn't ground a duty to obey unjust laws, and it doesn't give the state a protected right to act unjustly.</p><p>I disagree with Wellman on all three questions, but here I will focus only on the first. I think we should expect there to be a great deal of reasonable disagreement about justice. By that I mean that smart, sensible people, thinking clearly, who aren't driven by self-interest or prejudice, and who are committed to trying to treat others fairly, can and will disagree about many matters of justice, including difficult questions such as “What rates of income tax are required as a matter of justice?” or “Should freedom of expression extend to protect those who deny the Holocaust in order to promote anti-Semitism?”. But the fact that such people will disagree about the requirements of justice doesn't imply that there are no correct answers to these questions or that the answers are indeterminate—there may sometimes be correct answers in cases of reasonable disagreement.</p><p>I also think that in cases of reasonable disagreement about what justice requires, a legitimate state should have some sort of democratic process to resolve the reasonable disagreement. Indeed, I think people have a claim of justice to an equal (and positive) say in resolving reasonable disagreements about justice. To disregard democratic decisions whenever one thinks they are unjust is a refusal to participate on equal terms in the political process with other reasonable people. To be clear: I'm not suggesting that <i>unreasonable</i> views about justice—those that are, in some sense, beyond the pale, such as the violations of core liberal rights and freedoms—have a claim to be implemented if selected by a democratic process. I'm only suggesting that some disagreements about justice are reasonable—all the competing views represent plausible interpretations of what justice requires—and that in disagreements of this type, there is a claim of justice to have an egalitarian democratic process for resolving the disagreements.</p><p>Obviously, what I've just said is only the briefest sketch, and many details need to be filled in. But here is one way in which the view that I have sketched is inconsistent with Wellman's answers to the three questions above, in particular the first question: do legitimate states act permissibly when they act unjustly? Suppose, for the sake of argument, that the correct theory of justice includes a very expansive principle of free speech, one that provides a protected claim right against interference to people who engage in hate speech—for example, Nazis who wish to march and chant anti-Semitic slurs in Jewish neighborhoods. But the issue is one over which reasonable people disagree, and after a fair democratic process, our political community enacts a law that prohibits certain forms of hate speech, including the Nazis' anti-Semitic march.</p><p>I think justice requires giving people equal opportunity to exercise political power in cases of reasonable disagreement. If the government doesn't do what it has been directed to do by a fair democratic process (within the boundaries of the reasonable), it will be acting unjustly—failing to respect what justice requires regarding the distribution of political power. So if state officials decline to enforce the prohibition against the Nazis' march, they will be acting unjustly. However, if the state officials enforce the democratically enacted law prohibiting the march, they act contrary to the principle of free speech, another requirement of justice. So the state will act unjustly whatever it does. If we assume that at least one option from an agent's feasible set must be permissible, then it must be possible for the state to act permissibly and yet unjustly.</p><p>I'm not sure which premises of this argument Wellman would reject. He might reject P1, but denying it is implausible. It's not credible to suppose that all our disagreements about justice are driven by self-interest, prejudice, or irrationality. I also do not think it is plausible to suppose, as some contemporary Kantians do, that almost all substantive issues of social or distributive justice are largely indeterminate.14 I am sure that many specific questions about the requirements of justice are indeterminate, but this fact is perfectly consistent with P1. P1 makes only the very modest claim that reasonable disagreement is <i>possible</i> even when there are determinate answers about the requirements of justice.</p><p>This statement could be taken as a rejection of P2, though Wellman is not explicitly considering P2, so we should tread carefully. In one sense, Wellman is surely correct. The mere fact that reasonable people disagree about whether Φ-ing is permissible surely does not, on its own, affect the deontic status of Φ-ing. But the argument that I've given doesn't move from the mere fact of disagreement to permissibility. Instead it claims that reasonable disagreements about justice require, as a matter of justice, some fair democratic mechanism of resolution. It then moves from this claim to a claim about the permissibility of injustice, via the assumption (P4) that at least one option from an agent's set must be permissible. My argument thus provides the answer to Wellman's rhetorical question: the beliefs of the majority might have this moral power because justice requires a democratic resolution of some of our reasonable disagreements.</p><p>In this passage Wellman points out something that egalitarian democrats sometimes ignore—the mere fact that there is something valuable about democratic procedures does not suffice, on its own, to show that the scope of the right to democratic governance extends to cover substantively unjust decisions.</p><p>But the idea that claims of justice operate as side-constraints is notoriously tricky. Most obviously, what happens when two claims of justice conflict? Some proponents of the side-constraint view argue that this is conceptually impossible. Claims of justice, by their very nature, can never come into conflict.18 But this is very difficult to accept; it is sharply at odds with commonsense morality. This view requires either (a) that the content of justice be extremely sparse, so as to eliminate the possibility of conflicts arising, or else (b) a kind of specificationism about justice, such that whenever we have an apparent conflict of claims, we must conclude that in those specific circumstances, only one of the claims turns out to be a valid claim of justice. I think there are compelling reasons to reject both of these options, though I lack the space to lay those out here.</p><p>It's also worth noting that Wellman doesn't give us any reasons to doubt that claims of justice might sometimes conflict—he just asserts the side-constraint view. But if we accept the commonsense view that claims of justice can sometimes conflict, then we can easily accept P2. And it's worth emphasizing how revisionary and counterintuitive it would be to deny P2. To deny P2 would mean that there need be nothing unjust about stuffing ballot boxes or suppressing other people's votes, provided doing so is a way of ensuring that only truly just policies are enacted.</p><p>P3 seems uncontroversial if P2 has been accepted. P4 is not uncontroversial: a minority of philosophers claims that in some situations an agent will act wrongly regardless of what she does. Entering this debate is beyond the scope of this article, so I'll simply say that, along with many others, I think P4 is true: there must be a permissible option in an agent's set of choices.19 And P5 does not seem controversial if P1 is accepted.</p><p>And so I disagree with Wellman: I think a legitimate state and its officials can sometimes act permissibly even though they act unjustly. I also disagree with Wellman about the second and third questions, but I won't pursue those disagreements here.</p><p>The phenomenon of legitimate injustice is deeply puzzling, and I share the skepticism that Wellman expresses about the capacity of some recent work in political philosophy to provide an adequate account of this phenomenon. But we can't, I have argued, understand legitimate injustice as an instance of harms that are proportionate in light of all the good consequences that a state delivers.</p><p>We should instead understand legitimate injustice as something that arises as a result of the complex and multi-dimensional nature of justice itself. There are principles of justice that apply to the distribution of political power in cases of reasonable disagreement. When these principles conflict with other substantive principles of justice, the phenomenon of legitimate injustice arises. This is because, in such situations, the state and its officials cannot avoid injustice. This fact, contra Wellman, has significant practical implications for permissible conduct in politics. On my view, unlike Wellman's, the moral legitimacy of a law does real practical work—it can render permissible conduct that would otherwise be impermissible, and it can explain why public officials have claim rights against interference even in some cases where they threaten to infringe claims of justice.</p><p>Nothing I've said here constitutes an argument for the view that a principle of justice concerning the distribution of political power should ever take precedence over more substantive claims of justice. I do think this view is correct, but this isn't the place to present that argument.</p><p>For comments and discussion, I am very grateful to Peter de Marneffe, Rebecca Stone, Paul Weithman, Kit Wellman, Leif Wenar, and an anonymous referee.</p><p>None relevant.</p><p>There are no potential conflicts of interest relevant to this article.</p><p>All relevant data are included in the article.</p><p>The author declares human ethics approval was not needed for this study.</p>","PeriodicalId":47624,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Political Philosophy","volume":"31 2","pages":"222-232"},"PeriodicalIF":2.9000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jopp.12293","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Political Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jopp.12293","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

In his article, “The Space between Justice and Legitimacy”, Kit Wellman offers a novel account of the relationship between political philosophy's two central concepts.1 He argues that states can be legitimate yet impose many unjust laws and policies. This is true, he suggests, because political legitimacy should be understood as a claim about wide proportionality.2 Just as a country's war can be widely proportionate overall, and yet contain many instances of injustice, states can be proportionate (that is, legitimate) overall, yet contain a fair amount of injustice. But although Wellman thinks legitimate injustice is, in this sense, a real and pervasive phenomenon, he goes on to argue that legitimacy doesn't have much practical relevance with regard to unjust laws and policies. It doesn't make it permissible to impose and enforce unjust laws, nor does it generate an obligation to comply with unjust laws.

Like Wellman, I think legitimate injustice is real and pervasive. But I don't share his view of this phenomenon and, as a result, I also don't agree with him about the practical implications of legitimate injustice. Contra Wellman, I think state officials can act permissibly when they enforce unjust but legitimate law, and I think they have claim rights against being interfered with when they do so.

Before we begin, it will help to clarify what's at stake in labeling a state legitimate. There are many competing conceptions of political legitimacy in the literature, but, as Wellman says, “virtually everyone agrees that legitimacy at least entitles a state to coerce its constituents”.3 Following Wellman, I will assume this is, at a minimum, what's at stake in determining whether a state is legitimate. Other things being equal, a legitimate political authority is presumptively permitted to coerce its constituents in at least some ways that illegitimate authorities are not permitted to do.

Wellman believes legitimate states can act unjustly, and he defends this view by appeal to a particular notion of proportionality. Just as it can be morally permissible to launch a war even when we can foresee that some of our troops will commit unjust crimes during its course, a state can be legitimate even though we know it sometimes commits injustice. In both cases, we weigh the good things that will be achieved if we proceed against all the harms or costs that will be caused. Provided the goods are sufficiently great to outweigh the harms or costs, the proposed course of action or the institution can be defended on the basis that the benefits are proportionate relative to the costs.4 As Wellman puts it, “Because states perform such incredibly valuable functions … they are worth at least some moral costs”.5 This is, on Wellman's view, simply what it is for a state to be legitimate. When the benefits the state provides are proportionate relative to the costs (including the injustices the state commits), the state is morally legitimate.

This is an innovative way of thinking about the relationship between justice and political legitimacy. But I do not think it can be correct. In the ethics of self-defense and war, the standard way to determine whether some act is proportionate is to weigh the costs and benefits that will be caused by our action against the alternative of doing nothing.6 Suppose the only way to defend one innocent person from having her legs unjustly broken is by throwing a grenade that will kill two innocent bystanders. The act of throwing the grenade is not proportionate, because the costs of doing so (two innocent people are killed) are much worse than the alternative of doing nothing (one innocent person's legs get broken). If, however, these costs were reversed—if doing nothing meant two innocent people get killed, whereas throwing the grenade meant only one innocent person's legs get broken—then we might conclude throwing the grenade is proportionate.

If we are to use wide proportionality to assess a state's legitimacy, we need to engage in a similar comparison. The difficulty, however, is that the state is unlike a harmful act that we contemplate performing, and so it's less clear what it might mean to ask, “are the costs created by the state proportionate relative to the alternative of doing nothing?”. How should we understand the benchmark of “doing nothing”?

But this doesn't look like a good test. First, it's not clear what we are supposed to imagine occurs if the government or the state is dismantled. Maybe we should consider what would realistically occur in this particular country if its government or state apparatus suddenly ceased to exist. In many cases, what would occur might be terrible. In some places, civil war or ethnic cleansing might be the consequence of suddenly dismantling a government. In these cases, we would not be morally required to disband the government even if it were very, very bad. Even a brutal authoritarian regime might be preferable to civil war or ethnic cleansing, but surely that does not make a brutal authoritarian regime morally legitimate; it does not give that regime the moral permission to coerce its citizens to do things that they are not independently required to do. A regime is not morally legitimate merely because it is preferable to some of the worst conditions on earth.8

One problem with trying to conceptualize political legitimacy as a species of proportionality is that we almost never face a binary choice between our current political institutions as they are or else the total absence of those political institutions. Consider the Southern United States during the Jim Crow era. If the only two options were (1) retain the existing racist laws and institutions, or (2) a descent into an extremely dangerous form of anarchy, it's at least possible that option (1) might be widely proportionate relative to the benchmark of (2). But, of course, those weren't the only two options. Radically reforming the existing laws and institutions to make them less racist and unjust was a feasible option, and the very fact that it was a feasible option is surely part of the explanation as to why the racist political institutions might not have been morally legitimate.

But Wellman's statement here is puzzling for two reasons. First, this isn't how proportionality has standardly been conceptualized in the ethics of self-defense and war. As I've already explained, proportionality judgments are typically made by comparing a given act of harm-imposition relative to the benchmark of doing nothing. The entire set of feasible alternatives, however, is relevant with regard to a different moral judgment, namely, necessity. Philosophers working on self-defense and war typically claim that for an instance of harm-imposition to be morally permissible it must meet the condition of being necessary. Although there is a great deal of disagreement about how exactly to conceptualize the necessity condition, there is widespread agreement that judgments of necessity are made by comparing the potential act of harm-imposition to all the feasible alternatives.10 Killing a wrongful aggressor, for example, is not necessary if one of the defender's feasible alternatives is painlessly rendering the aggressor unconscious. Thus, although it's a matter of some dispute, on the most widely accepted picture, wide proportionality and necessity are two separate constraints on the permissible use of force. To be morally permissible, it's generally believed a harmful act must, among other things, satisfy both these constraints.

This test isn't helpful if we seek to explain how any existing state could ever be legitimate. It's surely true that every existing state has at least some unjust laws or unjust institutions which could be reformed to eliminate the injustice without becoming more unjust in other ways. It's thus true that, for every existing state, the status quo is not proportionate relative to a feasible alternative, and thus every existing state is illegitimate. The problem is even more stark, since this view has the implication that even hypothetical states that are far more just than any existing state would still be illegitimate so long as they contain even a single unjust law or institution that could feasibly be reformed. I think it's clear that these are not the conclusions Wellman seeks to defend.

Wellman might reply that it's not feasible for a state to be entirely devoid of unjust laws or institutions; realistically, our best efforts to design and sustain political institutions will always contain some unjust features. But this reply involves shifting from the standard of “feasible” to the standard of “probable” or “likely”. Although the term feasible is contested,11 I suspect it's most commonly used to refer to whether achieving a given outcome is possible given our resources and technological limitations. In this sense, changing the laws regulating gun ownership in the US is clearly feasible. Of course, it is extremely unlikely that robust gun control legislation will be enacted in the US for reasons of ideology and political self-interest.

Suppose, then, we take All Alternatives to refer only to those alternatives that are sufficiently likely to obtain. This would then vastly lower the bar for legitimacy. Even highly unjust states can be legitimate so long as it is sufficiently unlikely that they will become more just.

The problem with this interpretation, however, is fairly obvious. It's often the case that laws or institutions are unlikely to be reformed because those who hold power don't want to reform them. It might, for example, be very unlikely that we can reform the unjust institutions in a country because the country is ruled by a tyrant who refuses to relinquish power and rules by violently suppressing dissent. On this interpretation, the tyrant can render his rule legitimate by forming a settled disposition to hang on to power through unjust means. I take this result to be a reductio of the proposed interpretation of the proportionality test.

In sum, I don't see how the idea of wide proportionality can be made to work as an account of political legitimacy. One test for proportionality that Wellman seems to suggest—Dismantle—is far too weak a standard. It's too weak, in part, because it ignores the fact that we never face a binary choice between the status quo and dismantling the state. We always have many other feasible alternatives, which include reforming the unjust laws and institutions of our state. But the other test that Wellman floats—All Alternatives—creates either an unacceptably high standard or an unacceptably low one. If we focus on all feasible alternatives, then the bar for legitimacy is far too high—no existing state meets it and no hypothetical state with even a single unjust law meets it. But if we focus on likely or probable alternatives, then the bar is too low: very bad actors can render themselves legitimate by refusing to meet minimal moral standards they could meet if they wanted to.

In each case Wellman argues that the answer is “no”. So, although legitimate states act unjustly, the fact that these injustices are perpetrated by legitimate states doesn't have many interesting practical consequences for the unjust laws the state attempts to impose. The state's legitimacy doesn't give it a special permission to act unjustly, it doesn't ground a duty to obey unjust laws, and it doesn't give the state a protected right to act unjustly.

I disagree with Wellman on all three questions, but here I will focus only on the first. I think we should expect there to be a great deal of reasonable disagreement about justice. By that I mean that smart, sensible people, thinking clearly, who aren't driven by self-interest or prejudice, and who are committed to trying to treat others fairly, can and will disagree about many matters of justice, including difficult questions such as “What rates of income tax are required as a matter of justice?” or “Should freedom of expression extend to protect those who deny the Holocaust in order to promote anti-Semitism?”. But the fact that such people will disagree about the requirements of justice doesn't imply that there are no correct answers to these questions or that the answers are indeterminate—there may sometimes be correct answers in cases of reasonable disagreement.

I also think that in cases of reasonable disagreement about what justice requires, a legitimate state should have some sort of democratic process to resolve the reasonable disagreement. Indeed, I think people have a claim of justice to an equal (and positive) say in resolving reasonable disagreements about justice. To disregard democratic decisions whenever one thinks they are unjust is a refusal to participate on equal terms in the political process with other reasonable people. To be clear: I'm not suggesting that unreasonable views about justice—those that are, in some sense, beyond the pale, such as the violations of core liberal rights and freedoms—have a claim to be implemented if selected by a democratic process. I'm only suggesting that some disagreements about justice are reasonable—all the competing views represent plausible interpretations of what justice requires—and that in disagreements of this type, there is a claim of justice to have an egalitarian democratic process for resolving the disagreements.

Obviously, what I've just said is only the briefest sketch, and many details need to be filled in. But here is one way in which the view that I have sketched is inconsistent with Wellman's answers to the three questions above, in particular the first question: do legitimate states act permissibly when they act unjustly? Suppose, for the sake of argument, that the correct theory of justice includes a very expansive principle of free speech, one that provides a protected claim right against interference to people who engage in hate speech—for example, Nazis who wish to march and chant anti-Semitic slurs in Jewish neighborhoods. But the issue is one over which reasonable people disagree, and after a fair democratic process, our political community enacts a law that prohibits certain forms of hate speech, including the Nazis' anti-Semitic march.

I think justice requires giving people equal opportunity to exercise political power in cases of reasonable disagreement. If the government doesn't do what it has been directed to do by a fair democratic process (within the boundaries of the reasonable), it will be acting unjustly—failing to respect what justice requires regarding the distribution of political power. So if state officials decline to enforce the prohibition against the Nazis' march, they will be acting unjustly. However, if the state officials enforce the democratically enacted law prohibiting the march, they act contrary to the principle of free speech, another requirement of justice. So the state will act unjustly whatever it does. If we assume that at least one option from an agent's feasible set must be permissible, then it must be possible for the state to act permissibly and yet unjustly.

I'm not sure which premises of this argument Wellman would reject. He might reject P1, but denying it is implausible. It's not credible to suppose that all our disagreements about justice are driven by self-interest, prejudice, or irrationality. I also do not think it is plausible to suppose, as some contemporary Kantians do, that almost all substantive issues of social or distributive justice are largely indeterminate.14 I am sure that many specific questions about the requirements of justice are indeterminate, but this fact is perfectly consistent with P1. P1 makes only the very modest claim that reasonable disagreement is possible even when there are determinate answers about the requirements of justice.

This statement could be taken as a rejection of P2, though Wellman is not explicitly considering P2, so we should tread carefully. In one sense, Wellman is surely correct. The mere fact that reasonable people disagree about whether Φ-ing is permissible surely does not, on its own, affect the deontic status of Φ-ing. But the argument that I've given doesn't move from the mere fact of disagreement to permissibility. Instead it claims that reasonable disagreements about justice require, as a matter of justice, some fair democratic mechanism of resolution. It then moves from this claim to a claim about the permissibility of injustice, via the assumption (P4) that at least one option from an agent's set must be permissible. My argument thus provides the answer to Wellman's rhetorical question: the beliefs of the majority might have this moral power because justice requires a democratic resolution of some of our reasonable disagreements.

In this passage Wellman points out something that egalitarian democrats sometimes ignore—the mere fact that there is something valuable about democratic procedures does not suffice, on its own, to show that the scope of the right to democratic governance extends to cover substantively unjust decisions.

But the idea that claims of justice operate as side-constraints is notoriously tricky. Most obviously, what happens when two claims of justice conflict? Some proponents of the side-constraint view argue that this is conceptually impossible. Claims of justice, by their very nature, can never come into conflict.18 But this is very difficult to accept; it is sharply at odds with commonsense morality. This view requires either (a) that the content of justice be extremely sparse, so as to eliminate the possibility of conflicts arising, or else (b) a kind of specificationism about justice, such that whenever we have an apparent conflict of claims, we must conclude that in those specific circumstances, only one of the claims turns out to be a valid claim of justice. I think there are compelling reasons to reject both of these options, though I lack the space to lay those out here.

It's also worth noting that Wellman doesn't give us any reasons to doubt that claims of justice might sometimes conflict—he just asserts the side-constraint view. But if we accept the commonsense view that claims of justice can sometimes conflict, then we can easily accept P2. And it's worth emphasizing how revisionary and counterintuitive it would be to deny P2. To deny P2 would mean that there need be nothing unjust about stuffing ballot boxes or suppressing other people's votes, provided doing so is a way of ensuring that only truly just policies are enacted.

P3 seems uncontroversial if P2 has been accepted. P4 is not uncontroversial: a minority of philosophers claims that in some situations an agent will act wrongly regardless of what she does. Entering this debate is beyond the scope of this article, so I'll simply say that, along with many others, I think P4 is true: there must be a permissible option in an agent's set of choices.19 And P5 does not seem controversial if P1 is accepted.

And so I disagree with Wellman: I think a legitimate state and its officials can sometimes act permissibly even though they act unjustly. I also disagree with Wellman about the second and third questions, but I won't pursue those disagreements here.

The phenomenon of legitimate injustice is deeply puzzling, and I share the skepticism that Wellman expresses about the capacity of some recent work in political philosophy to provide an adequate account of this phenomenon. But we can't, I have argued, understand legitimate injustice as an instance of harms that are proportionate in light of all the good consequences that a state delivers.

We should instead understand legitimate injustice as something that arises as a result of the complex and multi-dimensional nature of justice itself. There are principles of justice that apply to the distribution of political power in cases of reasonable disagreement. When these principles conflict with other substantive principles of justice, the phenomenon of legitimate injustice arises. This is because, in such situations, the state and its officials cannot avoid injustice. This fact, contra Wellman, has significant practical implications for permissible conduct in politics. On my view, unlike Wellman's, the moral legitimacy of a law does real practical work—it can render permissible conduct that would otherwise be impermissible, and it can explain why public officials have claim rights against interference even in some cases where they threaten to infringe claims of justice.

Nothing I've said here constitutes an argument for the view that a principle of justice concerning the distribution of political power should ever take precedence over more substantive claims of justice. I do think this view is correct, but this isn't the place to present that argument.

For comments and discussion, I am very grateful to Peter de Marneffe, Rebecca Stone, Paul Weithman, Kit Wellman, Leif Wenar, and an anonymous referee.

None relevant.

There are no potential conflicts of interest relevant to this article.

All relevant data are included in the article.

The author declares human ethics approval was not needed for this study.

辩论:合法的不公正:对韦尔曼的回应
即使是一个残暴的独裁政权也可能比内战或种族清洗更可取,但这肯定不会使一个残酷的独裁政权在道德上合法;它没有给予该政权道德上的许可,迫使其公民做他们没有独立要求做的事情。一个政权在道德上是不合法的,仅仅因为它比地球上最糟糕的条件更可取。8试图将政治合法性概念化为一种相称性的问题是,我们几乎从来没有面临过在我们目前的政治体制和完全没有这些政治体制之间的二元选择。以吉姆·克劳时代的美国南部为例。如果只有两种选择是(1)保留现有的种族主义法律和制度,或者(2)陷入一种极其危险的无政府状态,那么至少有可能(1)相对于(2)的基准而言是广泛相称的。但是,当然,这并不是唯一的两种选择。彻底改革现有的法律和机构,使其不那么种族主义和不公正,这是一个可行的选择,而这一事实无疑是解释为什么种族主义政治机构在道德上可能不合法的部分原因。但韦尔曼在这里的说法令人费解,原因有二。首先,在自卫和战争的伦理中,相称性并不是标准概念。正如我已经解释过的,相称性判断通常是通过将特定的伤害行为与无所作为的基准进行比较来做出的。然而,整套可行的替代方案与不同的道德判断有关,即必要性。从事自卫和战争研究的哲学家通常声称,要想在道德上允许施加伤害,就必须满足必要的条件。尽管在如何准确概念化必要性条件的问题上存在很大分歧,但人们普遍认为,对必要性的判断是通过将潜在的伤害行为与所有可行的替代行为进行比较来做出的,如果辩护人的一个可行的选择是无痛地使侵犯者失去意识,那么这是不必要的。因此,尽管这是一个有争议的问题,但在最广泛接受的情况下,广泛的相称性和必要性是对允许使用武力的两个单独限制。为了在道德上得到允许,人们普遍认为有害行为必须同时满足这两个约束。如果我们试图解释任何现有的州是如何合法的,那么这个测试是没有帮助的。诚然,每个现有的州都至少有一些不公正的法律或不公正的机构,这些法律或机构可以进行改革,以消除不公正,而不会在其他方面变得更加不公正。因此,对于每一个现有的州来说,现状与可行的替代方案是不相称的,因此每一个现存的州都是非法的。这个问题更为严峻,因为这种观点意味着,即使是比任何现有国家都公正得多的假设国家,只要包含哪怕是一个可以改革的不公正法律或制度,也仍然是非法的。我认为很明显,这些并不是韦尔曼想要捍卫的结论。韦尔曼可能会回答说,一个国家完全没有不公正的法律或制度是不可行的;现实地说,我们设计和维持政治制度的最大努力总是包含一些不公正的特征。但这一答复涉及从“可行”的标准转向“可能”或“可能”的标准。尽管“可行”一词存在争议,11但我怀疑,鉴于我们的资源和技术限制,它最常用于指是否有可能实现给定的结果。从这个意义上说,改变美国枪支所有权的法律显然是可行的。当然,出于意识形态和政治自我利益的原因,美国极不可能制定强有力的枪支管制立法。因此,我们认为“所有替代方案”只指那些有可能获得的替代方案。这将大大降低合法性的门槛。即使是高度不公正的国家也可以是合法的,只要它们变得更加公正的可能性足够小。然而,这种解释的问题是相当明显的。通常情况下,法律或机构不太可能改革,因为掌权者不想改革它们。例如,我们可能不太可能改革一个国家的不公正制度,因为这个国家是由一个暴君统治的,他拒绝通过暴力镇压异见来放弃权力和统治。 根据这一解释,暴君可以通过形成一种通过不公正手段坚持权力的既定倾向,使其统治合法化。我认为这一结果是对比例检验的拟议解释的简化。总之,我看不出如何将广泛比例的概念作为政治合法性的一种解释。韦尔曼似乎建议的一个相称性测试——拆除——是一个太弱的标准。它太弱了,部分原因是它忽略了一个事实,即我们从未面临过在现状和解散国家之间的二元选择。我们总是有许多其他可行的选择,包括改革我们国家不公正的法律和制度。但韦尔曼提出的另一项测试——所有替代方案——要么产生了不可接受的高标准,要么产生了令人无法接受的低标准。如果我们关注所有可行的替代方案,那么合法性的门槛就太高了——没有一个现有的州能满足它,也没有一个假设的州能符合它,即使是一个不公正的法律。但如果我们关注可能或可能的替代方案,那么标准就太低了:非常糟糕的演员可以通过拒绝达到他们想要达到的最低道德标准来证明自己的合法性。在每一种情况下,韦尔曼都认为答案是“不”。因此,尽管合法国家的行为是不公正的,但这些不公正行为是由合法国家犯下的,这一事实并没有对国家试图实施的不公正法律产生太多有趣的实际后果。国家的合法性并没有赋予其不公正行为的特殊许可,也没有赋予其遵守不公正法律的义务,也没有给予国家不公正行为受保护的权利。我在这三个问题上都不同意韦尔曼的观点,但在这里我只关注第一个问题。我认为我们应该预料到在正义问题上会有很多合理的分歧。我的意思是,聪明、理智、思维清晰、不受私利或偏见驱使、致力于公平对待他人的人,可以也会在许多正义问题上存在分歧,包括一些棘手的问题,如“为了正义,需要什么税率的所得税?”或“言论自由是否应该扩大到保护那些否认大屠杀以宣扬反犹太主义的人?”。但是,这些人会对正义的要求产生分歧,这并不意味着这些问题没有正确的答案,也不意味着答案是不确定的——在合理分歧的情况下,有时可能会有正确的答案。我还认为,在对正义要求存在合理分歧的情况下,一个合法的国家应该有某种民主程序来解决合理的分歧。事实上,我认为人们有正义的主张,在解决关于正义的合理分歧方面有平等(积极)的发言权。只要一个人认为民主决定是不公正的,就无视这些决定,这就是拒绝与其他理智的人平等参与政治进程。需要明确的是:我并不是说,关于正义的不合理观点——在某种意义上,这些观点是超越苍白的,比如侵犯核心自由主义权利和自由——如果由民主程序选择,就有权得到实施。我只是想说,关于正义的一些分歧是合理的——所有相互竞争的观点都代表了对正义要求的合理解释——在这种分歧中,有人声称正义需要一个平等的民主程序来解决分歧。显然,我刚才所说的只是最简短的草图,还有很多细节需要填写。但有一点与韦尔曼对上述三个问题的回答不一致,尤其是第一个问题:合法国家在不公正的情况下是否可以采取行动?为了便于论证,假设正确的正义理论包括一个非常广泛的言论自由原则,该原则为从事仇恨言论的人——例如,希望在犹太社区游行并高呼反犹太主义诽谤的纳粹——提供了一种受保护的申索权。但这个问题是理性的人不同意的,经过公平的民主程序,我们的政治团体颁布了一项法律,禁止某些形式的仇恨言论,包括纳粹的反犹太主义游行。我认为正义需要在合理分歧的情况下给予人们行使政治权力的平等机会。如果政府不按照公平民主程序的指示行事(在合理的范围内),那就是不公正的行为——不尊重政治权力分配的正义要求。因此,如果国家官员拒绝执行禁止纳粹游行的禁令,他们的行为将是不公正的。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
4.10
自引率
5.60%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: The Journal of Political Philosophy is an international journal devoted to the study of theoretical issues arising out of moral, legal and political life. It welcomes, and hopes to foster, work cutting across a variety of disciplinary concerns, among them philosophy, sociology, history, economics and political science. The journal encourages new approaches, including (but not limited to): feminism; environmentalism; critical theory, post-modernism and analytical Marxism; social and public choice theory; law and economics, critical legal studies and critical race studies; and game theoretic, socio-biological and anthropological approaches to politics. It also welcomes work in the history of political thought which builds to a larger philosophical point and work in the philosophy of the social sciences and applied ethics with broader political implications. Featuring a distinguished editorial board from major centres of thought from around the globe, the journal draws equally upon the work of non-philosophers and philosophers and provides a forum of debate between disparate factions who usually keep to their own separate journals.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信