The Role of Philosophy After the Empirical Turn in Bioethics.

Suzanne Metselaar, Guy Widdershoven
{"title":"The Role of Philosophy After the Empirical Turn in Bioethics.","authors":"Suzanne Metselaar, Guy Widdershoven","doi":"10.1080/15265161.2022.2134493","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In “The Place of Philosophy in Bioethics Today,” Blumenthal-Barby and colleagues argue that philosophy is indispensable to the field of bioethics (Blumenthal-Barby et al. 2022). Nonetheless, they identify an underrepresentation of philosophers in funded bioethics projects. They contrast “more foundational normative and conceptual work” with “typically funded empirical bioethics and preference surveys,” and quote a report that identifies the focus on empirical studies to be a weakness of funding organizations, as it disregards the importance of philosophical work. We do not deny the importance of more foundational normative and conceptual projects, and agree that not all bioethicists need to be doing practice-focused work. However, we argue that the empirical turn in bioethics as such does not make philosophy obsolete; rather, it implies a specific and indispensable role of philosophy. This only adds to the three arguments of Blumenthal-Barby et al.: The important role of philosophy in empirical bioethics is a fourth way in which philosophers remain highly relevant to the interdisciplinary domain that is bioethics. Empirical ethics is a general term for “methodologies that seek to use empirical data about stakeholder values, attitudes, beliefs and experiences to inform normative ethical theorizing” (Davies, Ives, and Dunn 2015). It departs from the assumption that exploring stakeholders’ views and experiences informs and enhances ethical analysis, as it makes ethicists more contextually aware and more grounded in the realities of lived experience, and provides better, more workable solutions for ethical problems (Leget and Borry 2010). In our view, the role of philosophy in empirical ethics is twofold. First, philosophical analysis can provide much-needed reflection on the methodological and epistemological presuppositions of empirical ethics. Second, philosophical work is needed in order to interpret empirical results and to come to normative conclusions. Let us first go into the role of philosophy regarding reflection on the presuppositions of empirical ethics. It has been argued that the very notion of empirical ethics is problematic, as it seems to be at odds with the is–ought distinction. How can factual statements about, for instance, stakeholder beliefs result in conclusions with normative force? Various ways have been proposed for taking into account stakeholder views in normative bioethics work (Musschenga 2005). One is the reflective equilibrium approach, in which the ethicist weighs the normative intuitions of stakeholders against other relevant normative considerations (Van Thiel and Van Delden 2009). Another is the dialogical approach, in which the ethicist organizes a process of deliberation with stakeholders in order to come to joint normative conclusions that are primarily consensus based (Widdershoven, Abma, and Molewijk 2009). However, methodologies in empirical ethics are diverse and evolving (Davies, Ives, and Dunn 2015). Thus, there is still a lack of reflection on what justifies, both theoretically and methodologically, going from empirical data of stakeholders’ intuitions and judgments to normative conclusions in a certain way, and whether there is one approach to be preferred, in general or in specific situations. Such philosophical scrutiny is and remains important, as empirical ethics is a further developing field. The second role of philosophy in empirical ethics pertains to the contribution of philosophers to actual empirical ethics work. Empirical ethics is not necessarily antagonistic to theoretical normative ethics. Although some approaches to empirical bioethics marginalize the role of philosophical theory, prioritize","PeriodicalId":145777,"journal":{"name":"The American journal of bioethics : AJOB","volume":" ","pages":"49-51"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2022-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The American journal of bioethics : AJOB","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2022.2134493","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

In “The Place of Philosophy in Bioethics Today,” Blumenthal-Barby and colleagues argue that philosophy is indispensable to the field of bioethics (Blumenthal-Barby et al. 2022). Nonetheless, they identify an underrepresentation of philosophers in funded bioethics projects. They contrast “more foundational normative and conceptual work” with “typically funded empirical bioethics and preference surveys,” and quote a report that identifies the focus on empirical studies to be a weakness of funding organizations, as it disregards the importance of philosophical work. We do not deny the importance of more foundational normative and conceptual projects, and agree that not all bioethicists need to be doing practice-focused work. However, we argue that the empirical turn in bioethics as such does not make philosophy obsolete; rather, it implies a specific and indispensable role of philosophy. This only adds to the three arguments of Blumenthal-Barby et al.: The important role of philosophy in empirical bioethics is a fourth way in which philosophers remain highly relevant to the interdisciplinary domain that is bioethics. Empirical ethics is a general term for “methodologies that seek to use empirical data about stakeholder values, attitudes, beliefs and experiences to inform normative ethical theorizing” (Davies, Ives, and Dunn 2015). It departs from the assumption that exploring stakeholders’ views and experiences informs and enhances ethical analysis, as it makes ethicists more contextually aware and more grounded in the realities of lived experience, and provides better, more workable solutions for ethical problems (Leget and Borry 2010). In our view, the role of philosophy in empirical ethics is twofold. First, philosophical analysis can provide much-needed reflection on the methodological and epistemological presuppositions of empirical ethics. Second, philosophical work is needed in order to interpret empirical results and to come to normative conclusions. Let us first go into the role of philosophy regarding reflection on the presuppositions of empirical ethics. It has been argued that the very notion of empirical ethics is problematic, as it seems to be at odds with the is–ought distinction. How can factual statements about, for instance, stakeholder beliefs result in conclusions with normative force? Various ways have been proposed for taking into account stakeholder views in normative bioethics work (Musschenga 2005). One is the reflective equilibrium approach, in which the ethicist weighs the normative intuitions of stakeholders against other relevant normative considerations (Van Thiel and Van Delden 2009). Another is the dialogical approach, in which the ethicist organizes a process of deliberation with stakeholders in order to come to joint normative conclusions that are primarily consensus based (Widdershoven, Abma, and Molewijk 2009). However, methodologies in empirical ethics are diverse and evolving (Davies, Ives, and Dunn 2015). Thus, there is still a lack of reflection on what justifies, both theoretically and methodologically, going from empirical data of stakeholders’ intuitions and judgments to normative conclusions in a certain way, and whether there is one approach to be preferred, in general or in specific situations. Such philosophical scrutiny is and remains important, as empirical ethics is a further developing field. The second role of philosophy in empirical ethics pertains to the contribution of philosophers to actual empirical ethics work. Empirical ethics is not necessarily antagonistic to theoretical normative ethics. Although some approaches to empirical bioethics marginalize the role of philosophical theory, prioritize
经验主义转向后哲学在生命伦理学中的作用。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信