Shared Decision Making: The Prerequisite for Substantial Autonomy in Evidence-Based Practice

IF 2.1 4区 医学 Q3 HEALTH CARE SCIENCES & SERVICES
André Demambre Bacchi
{"title":"Shared Decision Making: The Prerequisite for Substantial Autonomy in Evidence-Based Practice","authors":"André Demambre Bacchi","doi":"10.1111/jep.70171","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Evidence-Based Practice (EBP) has been widely accepted as the dominant paradigm in contemporary healthcare, traditionally grounded in a triad of principles: the best available scientific evidence, the clinician's expertise, and the patient's values and preferences [<span>1</span>]. However, a critical gap persists in the implementation of this model: the third pillar, patient values and preferences, often remains a theoretical ideal rather than a tangible component of routine care [<span>2</span>]. To address this disconnection, EBP requires conceptual refinement. Shared decision making (SDM) must be understood not as a discretionary tool but as the fundamental mechanism through which substantial patient autonomy is operationalized, thereby transforming the third pillar from an aspirational statement into a clinical reality [<span>3</span>].</p><p>Contemporary bioethics positions autonomy as a foundational principle. However, it is crucial to distinguish between <i>formal autonomy</i> - the abstract legal right to choose—and <i>substantial autonomy</i>, the actual capacity to make informed, deliberate and value-congruent decisions [<span>4</span>]. Although traditional informed consent satisfies the conditions of formal autonomy, it often falls short of enabling substantial autonomy. A patient may formally consent to a proposed intervention without genuinely understanding its implications or viable alternatives, ultimately making choices that do not authentically reflect their values [<span>5</span>].</p><p>Table 1 outlines the essential distinctions between formal and substantial autonomy within the EBP framework. Formal autonomy corresponds to the baseline recognition of patient rights, which is typically enacted through standard informed consent procedures. By contrast, substantial autonomy facilitated by SDM embodies the patient's effective ability to make informed, reflective and value-oriented decisions.</p><p>Within this framework, SDM emerges as the mechanism that truly operationalizes the third pillar of EBP, translating ‘values and preferences’ from abstract concepts into concrete elements of clinical decision-making. SDM entails a structured process comprising bidirectional communication about the clinical condition, presentation of evidence-based options, elicitation of patient values and preferences, collaborative deliberation and implementation of a consensual decision. This approach markedly transcends the conventional informed consent process, which is often reduced to unidirectional transfer of information followed by formal approval [<span>6</span>].</p><p>Despite the growing recognition of SDM's relevance, its implementation remains hindered by substantial challenges across multiple levels. At the individual level, barriers include limited communication skills among clinicians, reluctance to relinquish traditional medical paternalism and low health literacy among patients. At the organizational level, key obstacles include time constraints during consultations, a lack of institutional incentives and an organizational culture that undervalues patient participation. Systemically, the absence of health policies promoting SDM and curricular gaps in the training of healthcare professionals further limit its integration into practice [<span>7</span>].</p><p>Recognizing SDM as a cornerstone for the exercise of substantial patient autonomy within EBP carries significant implications across healthcare domains. In clinical practice, this necessitates the integration of decision support tools into routine workflows, the development of clinician competencies in value-sensitive communication and the adoption of metrics that evaluate decision quality beyond traditional clinical outcomes [<span>8</span>]. In research, attention must be expanded beyond efficacy and effectiveness to include the alignment of interventions with patient values and the creation of methodologies that capture the patient's experience in the decision-making process [<span>9</span>]. In the realm of health policy, structural incentives to promote SDM, the inclusion of decision quality indicators in performance metrics and curricular reforms in health professional education are imperative steps forward [<span>10</span>].</p><p>The effective implementation of SDM is also an ethical imperative grounded in the principle of distributive justice. While formal autonomy establishes a universal right to choose, it operates under the principle of equality, treating all individuals the same regardless of their actual capacity to exercise that right. Paradoxically, this approach may perpetuate inequities by failing to account for differential needs and capabilities. In contrast, substantial autonomy rests on the principle of equity, recognizing that individuals require differing forms and levels of support to achieve meaningful decision-making capacity. The absence of such support disproportionately affects marginalized populations, reinforcing a social gradient of autonomy that mirrors and sustains existing health inequities.</p><p>Therefore, we propose a recalibration of the EBP model, wherein SDM is no longer treated as an ancillary methodology but rather acknowledged explicitly as the operational mechanism upon which the third pillar, patient values and preferences, depends. The concept of substantial autonomy provides a compelling theoretical framework to explain why SDM is not merely desirable, but essential in truly patient-centred EBP. This reframing offers a pathway to reconcile the perceived tension between the standardization inherent in EBP and the personalization required for compassionate individualized care. SDM does not stand in opposition to any of EBP's components. In contrast, it ensures that the application of scientific knowledge is meaningfully modulated by each patient's unique values, thereby fulfilling EBP's original promise as a paradigm that integrates science with humanism.</p><p>Without the formal recognition and practical enactment of SDM, the third pillar of EBP will remain a rhetorical abstraction, reducing patient autonomy to a merely legalistic formality devoid of substantive impact on clinical care. A coordinated effort is urgently needed across all levels of the healthcare system to elevate SDM to the status of a non-negotiable element of EBP, thereby ensuring that patient autonomy transcends legal recognition and is realized as a lived experience within healthcare delivery.</p><p>The author declares no conflicts of interest.</p>","PeriodicalId":15997,"journal":{"name":"Journal of evaluation in clinical practice","volume":"31 4","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":2.1000,"publicationDate":"2025-06-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jep.70171","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of evaluation in clinical practice","FirstCategoryId":"3","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jep.70171","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"HEALTH CARE SCIENCES & SERVICES","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Evidence-Based Practice (EBP) has been widely accepted as the dominant paradigm in contemporary healthcare, traditionally grounded in a triad of principles: the best available scientific evidence, the clinician's expertise, and the patient's values and preferences [1]. However, a critical gap persists in the implementation of this model: the third pillar, patient values and preferences, often remains a theoretical ideal rather than a tangible component of routine care [2]. To address this disconnection, EBP requires conceptual refinement. Shared decision making (SDM) must be understood not as a discretionary tool but as the fundamental mechanism through which substantial patient autonomy is operationalized, thereby transforming the third pillar from an aspirational statement into a clinical reality [3].

Contemporary bioethics positions autonomy as a foundational principle. However, it is crucial to distinguish between formal autonomy - the abstract legal right to choose—and substantial autonomy, the actual capacity to make informed, deliberate and value-congruent decisions [4]. Although traditional informed consent satisfies the conditions of formal autonomy, it often falls short of enabling substantial autonomy. A patient may formally consent to a proposed intervention without genuinely understanding its implications or viable alternatives, ultimately making choices that do not authentically reflect their values [5].

Table 1 outlines the essential distinctions between formal and substantial autonomy within the EBP framework. Formal autonomy corresponds to the baseline recognition of patient rights, which is typically enacted through standard informed consent procedures. By contrast, substantial autonomy facilitated by SDM embodies the patient's effective ability to make informed, reflective and value-oriented decisions.

Within this framework, SDM emerges as the mechanism that truly operationalizes the third pillar of EBP, translating ‘values and preferences’ from abstract concepts into concrete elements of clinical decision-making. SDM entails a structured process comprising bidirectional communication about the clinical condition, presentation of evidence-based options, elicitation of patient values and preferences, collaborative deliberation and implementation of a consensual decision. This approach markedly transcends the conventional informed consent process, which is often reduced to unidirectional transfer of information followed by formal approval [6].

Despite the growing recognition of SDM's relevance, its implementation remains hindered by substantial challenges across multiple levels. At the individual level, barriers include limited communication skills among clinicians, reluctance to relinquish traditional medical paternalism and low health literacy among patients. At the organizational level, key obstacles include time constraints during consultations, a lack of institutional incentives and an organizational culture that undervalues patient participation. Systemically, the absence of health policies promoting SDM and curricular gaps in the training of healthcare professionals further limit its integration into practice [7].

Recognizing SDM as a cornerstone for the exercise of substantial patient autonomy within EBP carries significant implications across healthcare domains. In clinical practice, this necessitates the integration of decision support tools into routine workflows, the development of clinician competencies in value-sensitive communication and the adoption of metrics that evaluate decision quality beyond traditional clinical outcomes [8]. In research, attention must be expanded beyond efficacy and effectiveness to include the alignment of interventions with patient values and the creation of methodologies that capture the patient's experience in the decision-making process [9]. In the realm of health policy, structural incentives to promote SDM, the inclusion of decision quality indicators in performance metrics and curricular reforms in health professional education are imperative steps forward [10].

The effective implementation of SDM is also an ethical imperative grounded in the principle of distributive justice. While formal autonomy establishes a universal right to choose, it operates under the principle of equality, treating all individuals the same regardless of their actual capacity to exercise that right. Paradoxically, this approach may perpetuate inequities by failing to account for differential needs and capabilities. In contrast, substantial autonomy rests on the principle of equity, recognizing that individuals require differing forms and levels of support to achieve meaningful decision-making capacity. The absence of such support disproportionately affects marginalized populations, reinforcing a social gradient of autonomy that mirrors and sustains existing health inequities.

Therefore, we propose a recalibration of the EBP model, wherein SDM is no longer treated as an ancillary methodology but rather acknowledged explicitly as the operational mechanism upon which the third pillar, patient values and preferences, depends. The concept of substantial autonomy provides a compelling theoretical framework to explain why SDM is not merely desirable, but essential in truly patient-centred EBP. This reframing offers a pathway to reconcile the perceived tension between the standardization inherent in EBP and the personalization required for compassionate individualized care. SDM does not stand in opposition to any of EBP's components. In contrast, it ensures that the application of scientific knowledge is meaningfully modulated by each patient's unique values, thereby fulfilling EBP's original promise as a paradigm that integrates science with humanism.

Without the formal recognition and practical enactment of SDM, the third pillar of EBP will remain a rhetorical abstraction, reducing patient autonomy to a merely legalistic formality devoid of substantive impact on clinical care. A coordinated effort is urgently needed across all levels of the healthcare system to elevate SDM to the status of a non-negotiable element of EBP, thereby ensuring that patient autonomy transcends legal recognition and is realized as a lived experience within healthcare delivery.

The author declares no conflicts of interest.

共同决策:实证实践中实质自治的前提
循证实践(EBP)已被广泛接受为当代医疗保健的主导范式,传统上以三个原则为基础:最佳可用的科学证据、临床医生的专业知识以及患者的价值观和偏好bb0。然而,在这一模式的实施中仍然存在一个关键的差距:第三个支柱,患者的价值观和偏好,往往仍然是一个理论上的理想,而不是常规护理的有形组成部分。为了解决这种脱节,EBP需要对概念进行细化。共同决策(SDM)不应被理解为一种自由裁量的工具,而应被理解为一种基本机制,通过这种机制,实质性的患者自主权得以实现,从而将第三个支柱从一个理想的声明转变为临床现实bb0。当代生命伦理学将自主定位为基本原则。然而,区分形式自治(抽象的合法选择权利)和实质自治(做出知情、深思熟虑和价值一致决策的实际能力)是至关重要的。虽然传统的知情同意满足了正式自治的条件,但它往往不能实现实质性的自治。患者可能在没有真正理解其含义或可行的替代方案的情况下正式同意拟议的干预措施,最终做出的选择并不能真正反映他们的价值观。表1概述了EBP框架中正式自治和实质自治之间的本质区别。正式的自主权对应于对患者权利的基本承认,这通常是通过标准的知情同意程序制定的。相比之下,SDM促进的实质性自主权体现了患者做出知情、反思和价值导向决策的有效能力。在这个框架内,SDM成为真正实现EBP第三支柱的机制,将“价值观和偏好”从抽象概念转化为临床决策的具体要素。SDM需要一个结构化的过程,包括关于临床状况的双向沟通,以证据为基础的选择的呈现,患者价值观和偏好的启发,协作审议和实施共识决定。这种方法明显超越了传统的知情同意过程,后者通常被简化为在正式批准之后单向传递信息。尽管越来越多的人认识到SDM的相关性,但它的实施仍然受到多个层面的重大挑战的阻碍。在个人层面上,障碍包括临床医生之间的沟通技巧有限,不愿放弃传统的医疗家长式作风,以及患者的卫生素养较低。在组织层面,主要障碍包括会诊期间的时间限制、缺乏制度性激励以及低估患者参与的组织文化。从系统上讲,缺乏促进可持续发展管理的卫生政策和培训卫生保健专业人员的课程差距进一步限制了将可持续发展管理纳入实践。认识到SDM是在EBP中行使大量患者自主权的基石,在医疗保健领域具有重要意义。在临床实践中,这需要将决策支持工具整合到日常工作流程中,发展临床医生在价值敏感沟通方面的能力,并采用超越传统临床结果的评估决策质量的指标。在研究中,必须将注意力扩展到功效和有效性之外,包括使干预措施与患者的价值观保持一致,并创造在决策过程中捕捉患者经验的方法[b]。在卫生政策领域,促进可持续发展机制的结构性激励、在绩效指标中纳入决策质量指标以及卫生专业教育的课程改革是必不可少的步骤。可持续发展机制的有效实施也是基于公平分配原则的道德要求。虽然正式自治确立了一项普遍的选择权,但它是在平等原则下运作的,对所有个人一视同仁,不论其实际行使这项权利的能力如何。矛盾的是,这种方法可能会因为没有考虑到不同的需求和能力而使不平等永久化。相比之下,实质性的自主则以公平原则为基础,认识到个人需要不同形式和程度的支持才能获得有意义的决策能力。缺乏这种支持对边缘人口的影响尤为严重,加剧了反映和维持现有卫生不平等的社会自主梯度。 因此,我们建议重新校准EBP模型,其中SDM不再被视为辅助方法,而是明确承认为第三支柱(患者价值和偏好)所依赖的操作机制。实质性自主权的概念提供了一个令人信服的理论框架来解释为什么SDM不仅是可取的,而且在真正以患者为中心的EBP中是必不可少的。这种重构为调和EBP固有的标准化和富有同情心的个性化护理所需的个性化之间的紧张关系提供了一条途径。SDM并不反对EBP的任何组成部分。相反,它确保科学知识的应用根据每个患者的独特价值观进行有意义的调整,从而实现EBP作为将科学与人文主义相结合的范例的最初承诺。如果没有SDM的正式认可和实际制定,EBP的第三个支柱将仍然是一个修辞上的抽象,将患者的自主权降低到仅仅是一种法律形式,对临床护理没有实质性影响。迫切需要在各级医疗保健系统中协调努力,将SDM提升为EBP中不可协商的要素,从而确保患者的自主权超越法律认可,并在医疗保健服务中作为一种生活体验实现。作者声明无利益冲突。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
4.80
自引率
4.20%
发文量
143
审稿时长
3-8 weeks
期刊介绍: The Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice aims to promote the evaluation and development of clinical practice across medicine, nursing and the allied health professions. All aspects of health services research and public health policy analysis and debate are of interest to the Journal whether studied from a population-based or individual patient-centred perspective. Of particular interest to the Journal are submissions on all aspects of clinical effectiveness and efficiency including evidence-based medicine, clinical practice guidelines, clinical decision making, clinical services organisation, implementation and delivery, health economic evaluation, health process and outcome measurement and new or improved methods (conceptual and statistical) for systematic inquiry into clinical practice. Papers may take a classical quantitative or qualitative approach to investigation (or may utilise both techniques) or may take the form of learned essays, structured/systematic reviews and critiques.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信