The mental health nurse as cyborg: Technology, a blessing or a curse?

IF 2.6 4区 医学 Q1 NURSING
Mick McKeown, Konstantina Poursanidou, Charley Baker
{"title":"The mental health nurse as cyborg: Technology, a blessing or a curse?","authors":"Mick McKeown,&nbsp;Konstantina Poursanidou,&nbsp;Charley Baker","doi":"10.1111/jpm.13080","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>The Luddites famously resisted the industrialisation of hand-loom weaving by wrecking the machinery that threatened to bring their livelihoods under the oppressive control of factory owners. The industrial revolution was relocating their workplaces from hearth to hades: a shift from homeworking into the dark satanic mills of William Blake. Far from being valorised as heroes, the Luddites have suffered abjectly under the ‘enormous condescension of posterity’ (Thompson, <span>1963</span>: 12). They are remembered, if at all, as hopeless vandals, with the term Luddism now reserved for unthinking or irrational opposition to technological advancement. To some extent this is surprising, as there cannot be many human beings who have not experienced a detrimental psychological impact from lacking control over their jobs. Indeed, the history of work under capitalism is arguably a history of the alienation of workers. The application of technologies to the work process is undisputedly a major aspect of this alienation, regardless of perceived benefits associated with new technologies.</p><p>The sociologist Harry Braverman (<span>1974</span>) notably pointed out the ways mechanisation of the labour process degrades the experience of work. This analysis has been applied to nursing work, where routinisation and task focused care can mimic the deleterious impact of production line technologies (McKeown, <span>1995</span>). In this sense, mental health nursing is an occupation that is as much subject to the vagaries and vicissitudes of how work is owned, controlled and organised as any other job. Despite professional rhetoric and exhortations, nurses are workers who neither completely control their work, the products of their work, nor the context in which they work. The substantial gap between an aspiration for a respected, professionally agentic role and the reality of prevailing, alienated impediments to fully-fledged autonomy is apparent wherever we care to look for it. That said, the alienation of nurses is relatively minor compared with the often-crushing alienation of patients within increasingly restrictive and coercive contemporary services. To rehash Erich Fromm's (<span>1968</span>) observation, psychiatric care might be best thought of as alienated people, being cared for by alienated practitioners, using alienated and alienating technologies. One optimistic insight that can be gleaned from such a negative situation, is that staff and patients may have a common interest in defeating alienation and taking a critical or resistive stance towards potentially oppressive technologies.</p><p>Right now, and increasingly for the future, the introduction of novel technologies into mental health care systems raise some pressing concerns for nurses and patients. Adapting the work of David Graeber, mental health nursing faces accelerating existential threats associated with (assumed) technological advances enmeshed in the organisation of healthcare work under neoliberalism (McKeown, <span>2023</span>). An insatiable thirst for metrics and defensive risk management practices have combined in a proliferation of time spent on record keeping as opposed to more relational care. Other technologies, such as body-worn cameras, CCTV and remote monitoring systems, arguably further dilute professional commitments to relational practice and care ethics. Moreover, from a patient perspective, these self-same technologies, are linked to exacerbations of psychiatric oppressions, and have been in the forefront of recent contestations of care (e.g. Stop Oxevision, <span>2023</span>).</p><p>The tensions between relational care and the proximal and affective distance of administering technologically driven practices pose a unique set of alienating circumstances for nurses and patients, and herald an encroaching corruption of nursing work in a process that Graeber named bullshitisation. We contend that such tendencies function to alienate nurses from both an idealised professional identity as authentic providers of care, and a somewhat deeper alienation from their own humanity and the concomitant need to be a positive force in the lives of others. The latter being what Karl Marx referred to, in a specifically humanist analysis, as alienation from species-being. Alternately, post-humanist theorising, exemplified in the work of Donna Haraway, decentres humans as a singular locus of interest and identifies interesting ways of thinking about technological developments. In this way, Haraway (<span>2000</span>) has explored the notion of the cyborg to illuminate the interactions between humans and technology but urges that binaries of good versus bad technology are unhelpful. Such a lens affords interesting observations on the practical and ontological melding of nurses and their machines. For instance, on psychiatric wards, where the (over)use of computers suggests a hybridity of human and technology: the nurse as cyborg arguably offers a spectrum of providential or dangerously detrimental consequences (McKeown, <span>2023</span>).</p><p>Just as the operators of drones responsible for killing other humans at great distances face injurious psychological consequences (Wilcox, <span>2017</span>), mental health nurses operating remote, impersonal observation technologies can experience alienating distress and long-term, cumulative upset as they come to perceive the actuality of being divorced and emotionally distanced from direct patient care. There is, indeed, a potential double whammy here, as this distancing, or the intrusions of the technology, raise the stakes for conflict with patients who understandably are aggrieved at invasions of privacy and affronts to autonomy.</p><p>It is crucial that a further dimension to any consideration of, and movement beyond, good–bad binaries of technology and mental health nursing depend upon the socio-economic context and questions of who is in control. We contend that as long as psychiatric services are enmeshed with societal governance systems operating under a neoliberal polity, then neither nurses nor patients can be considered in charge of decision making. Other ways of organising society, mental health care and nurses' work are available to us. These might include more egalitarian, cooperative and mutual forms suggested by notions of distributed democracy or co-production but not to date adequately realized in mental health care or wider society. Radical nurses are increasingly making vociferous calls for such reforms, transformations or abolitions (see Dillard-Wright et al., <span>2023</span>) and, of course, such demands are not new to the growing service user, survivor or service refuser movement (see Crossley, <span>2004</span>). Under more equitable, democratically organised care systems the alienation that stems from lack of control is immediately neutralised and the potential to fully realise a professional ideal of consensually provided care and support is arguably much more likely to be achieved; minimising alienation from species-being. In such circumstances, we may be better placed to negotiate an agreeable place for technology within the spaces of psychiatric care, better utilise currently available technologies for positive ends, or, indeed, reject those technologies which are legitimately seen as oppressive and contentious.</p><p>In conclusion, we stress the value and necessity of adopting a critically ambivalent approach to issues of technologies in mental health care. Taking care to avoid binary thinking around good/bad technology should allow us to engage with the full complexity, difficulty and messiness of this acutely contested territory. From a perspective of ambivalence, we can avoid being overinvested in certain standpoints regarding technology and move away from a ‘worrying politics of certainty’ (Breslow, <span>2022</span>). Even the Luddites might agree that if the industrialisation of textile production had occurred in the context of a socialised economic system, availability of welfare (or even universal basic income), with work organised into fully democratised cooperatives then a shift from home to factory working need not have motivated destruction of the new technology. We are proud to declare our own progressively Luddite tendencies and urge mental health nurses and allies to think critically about complicities with technological ‘advances’ and work hard to bring about the forms of democratic, relational care that could form the space for active dialogue about which technologies are preferable and how they are to be applied. Context is key, and we need to massively improve the context in which mental health technologies operate if we are to have any chance of exerting humane control.</p>","PeriodicalId":50076,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Psychiatric and Mental Health Nursing","volume":"31 6","pages":"1202-1204"},"PeriodicalIF":2.6000,"publicationDate":"2024-06-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jpm.13080","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Psychiatric and Mental Health Nursing","FirstCategoryId":"3","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jpm.13080","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"NURSING","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

The Luddites famously resisted the industrialisation of hand-loom weaving by wrecking the machinery that threatened to bring their livelihoods under the oppressive control of factory owners. The industrial revolution was relocating their workplaces from hearth to hades: a shift from homeworking into the dark satanic mills of William Blake. Far from being valorised as heroes, the Luddites have suffered abjectly under the ‘enormous condescension of posterity’ (Thompson, 1963: 12). They are remembered, if at all, as hopeless vandals, with the term Luddism now reserved for unthinking or irrational opposition to technological advancement. To some extent this is surprising, as there cannot be many human beings who have not experienced a detrimental psychological impact from lacking control over their jobs. Indeed, the history of work under capitalism is arguably a history of the alienation of workers. The application of technologies to the work process is undisputedly a major aspect of this alienation, regardless of perceived benefits associated with new technologies.

The sociologist Harry Braverman (1974) notably pointed out the ways mechanisation of the labour process degrades the experience of work. This analysis has been applied to nursing work, where routinisation and task focused care can mimic the deleterious impact of production line technologies (McKeown, 1995). In this sense, mental health nursing is an occupation that is as much subject to the vagaries and vicissitudes of how work is owned, controlled and organised as any other job. Despite professional rhetoric and exhortations, nurses are workers who neither completely control their work, the products of their work, nor the context in which they work. The substantial gap between an aspiration for a respected, professionally agentic role and the reality of prevailing, alienated impediments to fully-fledged autonomy is apparent wherever we care to look for it. That said, the alienation of nurses is relatively minor compared with the often-crushing alienation of patients within increasingly restrictive and coercive contemporary services. To rehash Erich Fromm's (1968) observation, psychiatric care might be best thought of as alienated people, being cared for by alienated practitioners, using alienated and alienating technologies. One optimistic insight that can be gleaned from such a negative situation, is that staff and patients may have a common interest in defeating alienation and taking a critical or resistive stance towards potentially oppressive technologies.

Right now, and increasingly for the future, the introduction of novel technologies into mental health care systems raise some pressing concerns for nurses and patients. Adapting the work of David Graeber, mental health nursing faces accelerating existential threats associated with (assumed) technological advances enmeshed in the organisation of healthcare work under neoliberalism (McKeown, 2023). An insatiable thirst for metrics and defensive risk management practices have combined in a proliferation of time spent on record keeping as opposed to more relational care. Other technologies, such as body-worn cameras, CCTV and remote monitoring systems, arguably further dilute professional commitments to relational practice and care ethics. Moreover, from a patient perspective, these self-same technologies, are linked to exacerbations of psychiatric oppressions, and have been in the forefront of recent contestations of care (e.g. Stop Oxevision, 2023).

The tensions between relational care and the proximal and affective distance of administering technologically driven practices pose a unique set of alienating circumstances for nurses and patients, and herald an encroaching corruption of nursing work in a process that Graeber named bullshitisation. We contend that such tendencies function to alienate nurses from both an idealised professional identity as authentic providers of care, and a somewhat deeper alienation from their own humanity and the concomitant need to be a positive force in the lives of others. The latter being what Karl Marx referred to, in a specifically humanist analysis, as alienation from species-being. Alternately, post-humanist theorising, exemplified in the work of Donna Haraway, decentres humans as a singular locus of interest and identifies interesting ways of thinking about technological developments. In this way, Haraway (2000) has explored the notion of the cyborg to illuminate the interactions between humans and technology but urges that binaries of good versus bad technology are unhelpful. Such a lens affords interesting observations on the practical and ontological melding of nurses and their machines. For instance, on psychiatric wards, where the (over)use of computers suggests a hybridity of human and technology: the nurse as cyborg arguably offers a spectrum of providential or dangerously detrimental consequences (McKeown, 2023).

Just as the operators of drones responsible for killing other humans at great distances face injurious psychological consequences (Wilcox, 2017), mental health nurses operating remote, impersonal observation technologies can experience alienating distress and long-term, cumulative upset as they come to perceive the actuality of being divorced and emotionally distanced from direct patient care. There is, indeed, a potential double whammy here, as this distancing, or the intrusions of the technology, raise the stakes for conflict with patients who understandably are aggrieved at invasions of privacy and affronts to autonomy.

It is crucial that a further dimension to any consideration of, and movement beyond, good–bad binaries of technology and mental health nursing depend upon the socio-economic context and questions of who is in control. We contend that as long as psychiatric services are enmeshed with societal governance systems operating under a neoliberal polity, then neither nurses nor patients can be considered in charge of decision making. Other ways of organising society, mental health care and nurses' work are available to us. These might include more egalitarian, cooperative and mutual forms suggested by notions of distributed democracy or co-production but not to date adequately realized in mental health care or wider society. Radical nurses are increasingly making vociferous calls for such reforms, transformations or abolitions (see Dillard-Wright et al., 2023) and, of course, such demands are not new to the growing service user, survivor or service refuser movement (see Crossley, 2004). Under more equitable, democratically organised care systems the alienation that stems from lack of control is immediately neutralised and the potential to fully realise a professional ideal of consensually provided care and support is arguably much more likely to be achieved; minimising alienation from species-being. In such circumstances, we may be better placed to negotiate an agreeable place for technology within the spaces of psychiatric care, better utilise currently available technologies for positive ends, or, indeed, reject those technologies which are legitimately seen as oppressive and contentious.

In conclusion, we stress the value and necessity of adopting a critically ambivalent approach to issues of technologies in mental health care. Taking care to avoid binary thinking around good/bad technology should allow us to engage with the full complexity, difficulty and messiness of this acutely contested territory. From a perspective of ambivalence, we can avoid being overinvested in certain standpoints regarding technology and move away from a ‘worrying politics of certainty’ (Breslow, 2022). Even the Luddites might agree that if the industrialisation of textile production had occurred in the context of a socialised economic system, availability of welfare (or even universal basic income), with work organised into fully democratised cooperatives then a shift from home to factory working need not have motivated destruction of the new technology. We are proud to declare our own progressively Luddite tendencies and urge mental health nurses and allies to think critically about complicities with technological ‘advances’ and work hard to bring about the forms of democratic, relational care that could form the space for active dialogue about which technologies are preferable and how they are to be applied. Context is key, and we need to massively improve the context in which mental health technologies operate if we are to have any chance of exerting humane control.

作为电子人的心理健康护士:技术,是福还是祸?
卢德分子通过破坏机器来抵制手工纺织业的工业化,因为机器可能会将他们的生计置于工厂主的压迫控制之下。工业革命将他们的工作场所从炉膛搬到了地狱:从在家工作变成了威廉-布莱克笔下黑暗的撒旦工厂。卢德分子非但没有被尊为英雄,反而在 "后人的巨大屈尊"(汤普森,1963 年:12)之下受尽折磨。在人们的记忆中,他们是毫无希望的破坏者,"卢德主义 "一词现在仅指不假思索或非理性地反对技术进步。这在某种程度上是令人惊讶的,因为不可能有多少人没有经历过因无法控制自己的工作而产生的有害心理影响。事实上,资本主义下的工作史可以说就是一部工人被异化的历史。社会学家哈里-布拉夫曼(Harry Braverman,1974 年)特别指出了劳动过程机械化降低工作体验的方式。这一分析也被应用到护理工作中,在护理工作中,常规化和以任务为中心的护理会模仿生产线技术的有害影响(McKeown,1995 年)。从这个意义上说,心理健康护理是一种职业,它与其他任何工作一样,受制于工作的拥有、控制和组织方式的变幻莫测和瞬息万变。尽管有专业的言论和劝诫,但护士是既不能完全控制自己的工作、工作成果,也不能完全控制工作环境的工作者。无论我们在哪里寻找答案,都会发现在对受尊重的专业代理角色的渴望与现实中普遍存在的对完全自主的疏远阻碍之间存在着巨大差距。尽管如此,与病人在日益严格和强制的现代服务中经常受到的异化相比,护士的异化相对较小。重提埃里希-弗洛姆(Erich Fromm,1968)的观点,精神病护理最好被视为被异化的人,由被异化的从业者使用被异化和异化的技术进行护理。从这种负面情况中,我们可以得到一个乐观的启示,那就是员工和患者在战胜异化、对潜在的压迫性技术采取批判或抵制的态度方面可能有着共同的兴趣。根据戴维-格雷伯(David Graeber)的研究,心理健康护理面临着与新自由主义下医疗工作组织中(假定的)技术进步相关的生存威胁(McKeown,2023 年)。对指标的贪得无厌和防御性风险管理实践相结合,导致用于记录的时间激增,而不是更多的关系护理。其他技术,如随身携带的摄像机、闭路电视和远程监控系统,可以说进一步削弱了专业人员对亲情实践和护理伦理的承诺。此外,从患者的角度来看,这些技术本身也与精神压迫的加剧有关,并且一直处于近期护理争议的前沿(例如,Stop Oxevision, 2023)。关系型护理与技术驱动型实践管理的近距离和情感距离之间的紧张关系为护士和患者带来了一系列独特的疏离环境,并预示着护理工作在一个被格雷伯命名为 "公牛化 "的过程中正在受到侵蚀。我们认为,这种趋势的作用是将护士从理想化的专业身份--真正的护理提供者--中疏离出来,并在一定程度上加深了她们对自身人性的疏离,以及随之而来的成为他人生活中积极力量的需要。后者就是卡尔-马克思(Karl Marx)在具体的人文主义分析中所说的 "与物种存在的疏离"。另外,以唐娜-哈拉维(Donna Haraway)的著作为代表的后人文主义理论将人类视为一个独特的兴趣点,并确定了思考技术发展的有趣方式。哈拉维(Haraway,2000 年)以这种方式探讨了半机械人(cyborg)的概念,以揭示人类与技术之间的互动关系,但她敦促说,技术好坏的二元对立是无益的。这样的视角为我们提供了关于护士与机器的实践和本体融合的有趣观察。例如,在精神科病房,计算机的(过度)使用表明了人类与技术的混合:作为电子人的护士可以说提供了一系列天意或危险的有害后果(McKeown,2023 年)。 正如在远距离杀害他人的无人机操作员面临着有害的心理后果(Wilcox,2017)一样,操作远程、非个人化观察技术的心理健康护士可能会经历疏离的痛苦和长期、累积的不安,因为他们开始意识到自己与直接的患者护理在情感上被疏远了。事实上,这里存在着潜在的双重打击,因为这种疏远或技术的侵入,增加了与病人发生冲突的风险,而病人对隐私被侵犯和自主权被践踏的不满是可以理解的。我们认为,只要精神科服务与在新自由主义政体下运作的社会治理体系相联系,那么护士和病人都不能被视为决策的主导者。我们可以采用其他方式来组织社会、心理健康护理和护士工作。这些方式可能包括分布式民主或共同生产概念中提出的更为平等、合作和互助的形式,但迄今为止在精神健康护理或更广泛的社会中尚未充分实现。激进的护士们越来越强烈地呼吁进行这样的改革、转型或废除(见 Dillard-Wright 等人,2023 年),当然,对于日益壮大的服务使用者、幸存者或服务拒绝者运动来说,这样的要求并不陌生(见 Crossley,2004 年)。在更公平、更民主的护理系统中,因缺乏控制权而产生的疏离感会被立即化解,可以说更有可能充分实现双方同意提供护理和支持的专业理想;最大限度地减少对物种存在的疏离感。在这种情况下,我们可能更有能力在精神医疗空间中为技术找到一个可以接受的位置,更好地利用现有技术来达到积极的目的,或者,事实上,拒绝那些被合理地视为压迫性和争议性的技术。最后,我们强调在精神医疗技术问题上采取批判性的矛盾方法的价值和必要性。注意避免对技术的好坏进行二元对立的思考,应能让我们充分认识到这一尖锐争议领域的复杂性、困难性和混乱性。从矛盾的视角出发,我们可以避免过度沉迷于技术的某些观点,摆脱 "令人担忧的确定性政治"(Breslow, 2022)。即使是卢德分子也可能同意,如果纺织品生产的工业化是在社会化经济体系、福利(甚至全民基本收入)、工作组织完全民主化的合作社的背景下进行的,那么从家庭工作到工厂工作的转变就不会促使新技术遭到破坏。我们很自豪地宣布,我们有逐渐成为 "卢德主义者 "的倾向,并敦促心理健康护士和盟友们批判性地思考与技术 "进步 "的共谋关系,努力创造民主、亲情关怀的形式,为积极对话提供空间,讨论哪些技术更可取,以及如何应用这些技术。环境是关键,如果我们想有机会对心理健康技术进行人性化的控制,我们就必须大力改善心理健康技术的运行环境。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
4.70
自引率
3.70%
发文量
75
审稿时长
4-8 weeks
期刊介绍: The Journal of Psychiatric and Mental Health Nursing is an international journal which publishes research and scholarly papers that advance the development of policy, practice, research and education in all aspects of mental health nursing. We publish rigorously conducted research, literature reviews, essays and debates, and consumer practitioner narratives; all of which add new knowledge and advance practice globally. All papers must have clear implications for mental health nursing either solely or part of multidisciplinary practice. Papers are welcomed which draw on single or multiple research and academic disciplines. We give space to practitioner and consumer perspectives and ensure research published in the journal can be understood by a wide audience. We encourage critical debate and exchange of ideas and therefore welcome letters to the editor and essays and debates in mental health.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信