The Species as a Reproductive Community Emerging From the Past

W. Maddison, Jeannette Whitton
{"title":"The Species as a Reproductive Community Emerging From the Past","authors":"W. Maddison, Jeannette Whitton","doi":"10.18061/bssb.v2i1.9358","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Biologists and philosophers of science have been unable to fully resolve the decades-long controversy as to what kind of unit of living biodiversity should receive the valued label “species”: reproductive communities (among sexual organisms), genealogical groups, or clusters of organisms that share traits. Among these choices, which represent a spectrum from process to history to observable outcome (respectively), the latter (more operationalist) concepts are not viable. Species of sexual organisms must embody or imply cohesive and integrating processes such as interbreeding and shared ecological pressures if they are to have sufficient power to bear the burden we give them: to predict or explain traits across the genome and among organisms. This commitment to cohesive process is needed whether biologists use species as taxonomic containers to synthesize data, as minimal phylogenetic units, or as actors in evolutionary diversification. These varied uses can be satisfied via a concept of reproductive community, but not the strict Biological Species Concept (BSC). Its two drawbacks are a focus on the contemporary and a restriction to intrinsic factors. Current reproductive compatibility may predict future matings, but it does not explain well the traits and genes that living organisms already have. The organisms alive today were shaped by isolating factors of the past, not those of the present, to whatever extent those differ. The most broadly-useful species concept must therefore see species retrospectively, as reproductive communities of the past. As well, the BSC’s exclusion of extrinsic factors renders each of its units incomplete in explanation and synthesis. Reproductive communities in nature were isolated not just by intrinsic (genetic) differences, but also by purely extrinsic (e.g., geographic) factors. Such reproductive communities were and are real, natural entities whose integrated and self-reinforcing cohesive processes constrained genealogical descent and aligned the distribution of many traits. This Retrospective Reproductive Community Concept (RRCC), formalized mathematically in multispecies coalescent models, justifies the traditional practice of taxonomists using morphological data to seek the echoes of past reproductive cohesion. However, which reproductive communities naturally deserve to be ranked as species, and which as demes or populations, is a vexing question. There is no natural, discrete and broadly informative species rank that applies universally, or perhaps even usually. To whatever extent species rank is justified, it is as justified for asexual organisms as for sexuals. The presence or absence of sex is just one example of the variability biologists confront. Because cohesive processes vary among clades, a useful and broadly-applicable species concept cannot specify detailed cohesive mechanisms. Nor can it perfectly align the named species of taxonomy with units of evolution, because the latter are not structured to match taxonomy’s partition of boxes. Taxonomic species should approximate, but can only approximate, evolutionary units. Settling on retrospection, letting go of a natural meaning for species rank, and accepting taxonomy as approximation allow biology to turn to the far more daunting task: listening to the natural world to understand the many interacting processes that built distinction and identity, that shaped the reproductive communities emerging out of the past into the present day.","PeriodicalId":476538,"journal":{"name":"Bulletin of the Society of Systematic Biologists","volume":"57 3","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-12-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Bulletin of the Society of Systematic Biologists","FirstCategoryId":"0","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.18061/bssb.v2i1.9358","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Biologists and philosophers of science have been unable to fully resolve the decades-long controversy as to what kind of unit of living biodiversity should receive the valued label “species”: reproductive communities (among sexual organisms), genealogical groups, or clusters of organisms that share traits. Among these choices, which represent a spectrum from process to history to observable outcome (respectively), the latter (more operationalist) concepts are not viable. Species of sexual organisms must embody or imply cohesive and integrating processes such as interbreeding and shared ecological pressures if they are to have sufficient power to bear the burden we give them: to predict or explain traits across the genome and among organisms. This commitment to cohesive process is needed whether biologists use species as taxonomic containers to synthesize data, as minimal phylogenetic units, or as actors in evolutionary diversification. These varied uses can be satisfied via a concept of reproductive community, but not the strict Biological Species Concept (BSC). Its two drawbacks are a focus on the contemporary and a restriction to intrinsic factors. Current reproductive compatibility may predict future matings, but it does not explain well the traits and genes that living organisms already have. The organisms alive today were shaped by isolating factors of the past, not those of the present, to whatever extent those differ. The most broadly-useful species concept must therefore see species retrospectively, as reproductive communities of the past. As well, the BSC’s exclusion of extrinsic factors renders each of its units incomplete in explanation and synthesis. Reproductive communities in nature were isolated not just by intrinsic (genetic) differences, but also by purely extrinsic (e.g., geographic) factors. Such reproductive communities were and are real, natural entities whose integrated and self-reinforcing cohesive processes constrained genealogical descent and aligned the distribution of many traits. This Retrospective Reproductive Community Concept (RRCC), formalized mathematically in multispecies coalescent models, justifies the traditional practice of taxonomists using morphological data to seek the echoes of past reproductive cohesion. However, which reproductive communities naturally deserve to be ranked as species, and which as demes or populations, is a vexing question. There is no natural, discrete and broadly informative species rank that applies universally, or perhaps even usually. To whatever extent species rank is justified, it is as justified for asexual organisms as for sexuals. The presence or absence of sex is just one example of the variability biologists confront. Because cohesive processes vary among clades, a useful and broadly-applicable species concept cannot specify detailed cohesive mechanisms. Nor can it perfectly align the named species of taxonomy with units of evolution, because the latter are not structured to match taxonomy’s partition of boxes. Taxonomic species should approximate, but can only approximate, evolutionary units. Settling on retrospection, letting go of a natural meaning for species rank, and accepting taxonomy as approximation allow biology to turn to the far more daunting task: listening to the natural world to understand the many interacting processes that built distinction and identity, that shaped the reproductive communities emerging out of the past into the present day.
物种是一个从过去兴起的繁殖群体
生物学家和科学哲学家一直无法完全解决长达数十年的争论,即什么样的生物多样性单位应该获得有价值的“物种”标签:生殖群落(在有性生物之间),谱系群,或具有共同特征的生物群。在这些选择中,它们分别代表了从过程到历史到可观察结果的范围,后者(更具操作性)的概念是不可行的。有性生物的物种必须体现或暗示着内聚和整合的过程,如杂交和共同的生态压力,如果它们有足够的能力来承担我们赋予它们的负担:预测或解释整个基因组和生物体之间的特征。无论生物学家是将物种作为综合数据的分类容器、最小的系统发育单位,还是作为进化多样化的参与者,都需要这种对内聚过程的承诺。这些不同的用途可以通过生殖群落的概念来满足,而不是严格的生物物种概念(BSC)。它的两大弊端是对时代性的关注和对内在因素的制约。目前的生殖相容性可以预测未来的交配,但它不能很好地解释生物体已经具有的特征和基因。今天活着的生物是由过去的孤立因素塑造的,而不是现在的因素,无论这些因素有多大的不同。因此,最广泛使用的物种概念必须回顾性地看待物种,将其视为过去的生殖群落。同样,平衡记分卡排除了外在因素,使得它的每一个单位在解释和综合上都不完整。自然界中的生殖群落不仅因内在(遗传)差异而被隔离,而且也因纯粹的外在(如地理)因素而被隔离。这样的生殖群落过去和现在都是真实的、自然的实体,其整合和自我强化的凝聚力过程限制了谱系的下降,并使许多特征的分布保持一致。这种回顾性生殖群落概念(RRCC)在多物种凝聚模型中以数学形式形成化,证明了分类学家使用形态学数据寻找过去生殖凝聚的回声的传统做法是正确的。然而,哪些繁殖群体自然地应该被列为物种,哪些是demes或种群,这是一个令人烦恼的问题。没有一种自然的、离散的、信息广泛的物种等级可以普遍适用,甚至可能通常适用。无论物种的等级在多大程度上是合理的,无性生物和有性生物的等级都是合理的。性的存在与否只是生物学家面临的变异性的一个例子。由于进化枝间的内聚过程各不相同,一个有用且广泛适用的物种概念无法详细说明内聚机制。它也不能将分类学的命名物种与进化单位完美地结合起来,因为后者的结构与分类学的盒子划分不匹配。分类学上的物种应该近似,但只能近似,进化单位。立足于回顾,放弃物种等级的自然意义,接受分类学作为近似值,让生物学转向更艰巨的任务:倾听自然世界,理解许多相互作用的过程,这些过程建立了区别和身份,塑造了从过去到现在的生殖群落。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信