The trolley problemBy HallvardLillehammer (Ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2023. ix + 267 pp. £74.99 (hb)/£26.99 (pb) ISBN: 9781009255592

IF 0.6 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Ratio Pub Date : 2023-10-10 DOI:10.1111/rati.12393
Sara van Goozen
{"title":"The trolley problemBy HallvardLillehammer (Ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2023. ix + 267 pp. £74.99 (hb)/£26.99 (pb) ISBN: 9781009255592","authors":"Sara van Goozen","doi":"10.1111/rati.12393","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The Trolley Problem, edited by Hallvard Lillehammer, is worth reading for a number of reasons. The Trolley Problem has sparked heated philosophical debate for over four decades, as well as scientific research, pop-culture references and memes. Sadly, among all this the actual questions the Trolley Problem set out to illustrate sometimes have a tendency to disappear into the background. As several of the authors in this volume point out, the Trolley Problem is sometimes thought to refer to the single case in which a Bystander has to choose whether to turn a runaway trolley onto a side-track. This is somewhat of an (over)simplification. For most writing on it, the Trolley Problem is about finding convincing explanations of the difference in permissibility between different cases featuring trolleys—such as the classic case, where someone is faced with the choice of switching a runaway trolley to a sidetrack, or the ‘Bridge’ case, where someone is faced with the choice of pushing a person off a bridge to stop a trolley. However, there are several different interpretations of the problem in circulation, and this may contribute to the confusion. One reason to recommend this volume, part of Cambridge University Press's ‘Classic Philosophical Arguments’ series, is that it does a genuinely good job of cutting through some of the noise. Its twelve chapters offer a range of reflections on the Trolley Problem, ‘trolleyology’, and related issues. Given the variety of issues covered, space does not permit me to discuss any one chapter in great detail. Instead, for the purposes of this review, I will comment on some more general points. First, however, I will briefly outline the range of topics covered in this volume. It encompasses traditional (deontological) discussions of the Trolley Problem, as well as virtue ethical approaches, moral psychology, cross-cultural empirical analysis, and applied philosophy. The first chapter, by Lillehammer, provides a helpful overview of the history of the Trolley Problem, and includes reflections on Foot, Thomson and Kamm, as well as a response to Barbara Fried's important critique of the Trolley Problem (see Fried, 2012). The first set of chapters, by William J. FitzPatrick, Peter A. Graham, F.M. Kamm, Dana Kay Nelkin and Samuel Rickless, and Fiona Woollard, tackle various aspects of the Trolley Problem from a broadly deontological perspective. In his chapter, FitzPatrick argues that Judith Jarvis Thompson (in)famous change of heart with regards to the classic case was unwarranted. Instead, he suggests that the problem can be explained by appeal to reasonable norms of shared risk. Next, Graham focuses on the question of whether it is merely permissible or obligatory to turn the trolley in the standard case. He takes aim at Helen Frowe, who argues that it is obligatory. Contrary to Frowe, Graham maintains that it is (merely) permissible to turn the trolley by appealing to previous work by Kamm (2007, 2016). Following Graham, Kamm herself agrees and offers a clear and characteristically detailed discussion of some of the key arguments for her view that it is permissible to turn the trolley from an explicitly non-consequentialist perspective. It is a particularly useful and concise overview of some of her recent work on this topic and would therefore serve well to introduce people (for example, students) to her work. Taking a slightly different angle, Nelkin and Rickless, as well as Woollard, focus on the Doctrine of Double Effect (DDE) and Doctrine of Doing and Allowing (DDA)—both often used to attempt to explain the difference in permissibility between various trolley cases. Nelkin and Rickless argue, importantly, that classical formulations of trolley cases fail to take risk into account. By drawing on Warren Quinn's interpretation of the DDE (Quinn, 1989), which distinguishes between direct and indirect harmful agency, they argue that a probabilistic version of the principle can be constructed to deal with these more complex cases. On the other hand, Woollard focuses on the DDA, another principle often wheeled out to help resolve the Trolley Problem. Woollard argues that the relationship between the DDA and the Trolley Problem is, however, considerably more complex. Specifically, the DDA should not be understood as a solution to the problem, but nor should the Trolley Problem be considered a proof that the DDA is morally irrelevant. Rather, her analysis suggests that an additional principle is needed—a sister principle to the DDA—to explain common intuitions about these cases. Following this set of deontological investigations, the contributions to this book take (somewhat) more unexpected approaches. Liezl van Zyl considers the Trolley Problem from a virtue ethical perspective. She makes a number of important points that those writing on Trolley Problems should take into serious consideration. Her virtue ethical analysis of the ‘Bridge’ case is particularly worth noting. Van Zyl claims it is unlikely that a moderately virtuous person would, when faced with such a situation, look at a fellow human being on the bridge and think of them as a ‘heavy object’ that can be used to stop the trolley. As she notes, her students—when presented with a less leading example of the Bridge case—come up with standard suggestions: ‘[the men] should yell out, blow a whistle, wave their arms, run toward the workmen, look for a heavy object further down the track, etc. So far, none of them have proposed that [Bystander] should consider pushing the big man onto the track.’ (p. 128) Her overall argument is that proponents of virtue ethics can support common intuitions about trolley cases, including Bridge. However, this is for very different reasons than those appealed to by deontologists. The next two chapters are an interesting debate between, on the one hand, Guy Kahane and Jim Everett and on the other, Joshua D. Greene. Kahane and Everett consider the use of Trolley Problems in contemporary psychological research, and the way this research has often been framed in terms of a contrast between deontological and utilitarian approaches to morality. They claim this framing is misleading—first, because some of the responses researchers classify as ‘utilitarian’ are at best tangentially utilitarian (and more often self-interested or simply consequentialist) and second, because they suspect it is difficult to generalize from these kinds of cases to more general claims about moral reasoning. Greene, on the other hand, has done extensive psychological research using trolley problems and related cases and he can quite rightly be considered a pioneer in this particular area of the field. Here he argues (pace Kahane and Everett, but also several other critics) that the empirical study of how people react to Trolley Problems has significantly improved our understanding of the psychological mechanics of moral judgment. He claims in particular that his empirical research has demonstrated the evidential or justificatory limitations of intuitions about moral dilemmas. Natalie Gold, in her chapter, also draws on a number of empirical studies, but her interest in those studies looking at how people from different (cultural) backgrounds respond to Trolley Problems. She provides a critical and detailed survey of this literature and shows that the picture that emerges from these studies is mixed. It is possible to conclude from these studies that there do exist differences in judgment about trolley cases between cultures, but the number of studies that can be used for this analysis is relatively small. Moreover, Gold argues, it is plausible to think of these differences as evidence for ethical constructivism. Finally, the last two chapters focus on the application of Trolley Problems to two areas within applied philosophy: Sven Nyholm considers the ethics of self-driving cars, and Ezio Di Nucci considers the Trolley Problem in the context of healthcare, and specifically the COVID-19 pandemic. Both offer interesting, critical, discussions of the use (and occasional abuse) of Trolley Problems in the context of applied ethics, public policy, and law. In this volume, there are a number of overarching themes and issues that come to the fore, which mean that while there certainly is value in picking it up to read just one or the other chapter, it would also be rewarding to read the whole book—or at least the sets of chapters corresponding to one's area of academic interest. This is the second reason why this volume is worth reading. However, as noted at the outset, it is not always clear in the wider literature what the Trolley Problem actually is. And this book, perhaps surprisingly, does not provide a clear answer to that question either. Indeed, it is interesting to note that even in a book about the Trolley Problem, different chapters offer subtly different explanations. For example, Woollard—like Lillehammer and some of the other contributors—points to the issue of explaining the difference in perceived permissibility between the classical case and cases such as Bridge. Thus, in Woollard's words, the real Trolley Problem ‘is to explain why you are permitted to turn the trolley [in the classic trolley case] when there are many cases where intuitively you are not permitted to kill one person to save five’ (p. 101). But FitzPatrick offers a subtly different interpretation: he suggests that the relevant problem is the question ‘What is it about the sort of diversion involved in [the standard case] that makes for an exception to the usual proscription against killing some to save others (assuming we accept some version of that non-consequentialist constraint in the other cases)?’ (p. 27). Finally, going against the grain somewhat, Graham identifies the question of whether it is merely permissible or required to turn the trolley as the central problem of concern. One might perhaps wish that the authors had ensured a bit more consistency between their explanations of what exactly the problem is, and the slight shifts in explanation may confuse someone coming to this area with little background knowledge. That being said, we also have here a great illustration of the complex and somewhat slippery nature of the puzzle posed by the Trolley Problem. Through reading this volume, it becomes clear just how rich a thought experiment Foot and Thomson's invention really is—rather than a single Trolley Problem, it becomes clear there are multiple serious moral issues raised by these apparently simple cases. And as the chapters by Greene and Kahane and Everett highlight, pursuing an empirical, utilitarian approach is not a guarantee you can entirely avoid them—though the issues faced by experimental philosophers and psychologists when trying to make sense of the Trolley Problem may be somewhat different, of course. Whether this is an issue with the volume will depend a lot on the audience, I suspect. As noted, for someone coming at this with little background knowledge, or someone really keen to find out what, precisely, the Trolley Problem is, the ambiguity could create confusion. If assigned as part of, for example, an undergraduate course, it may therefore require some careful explanation by the instructors. However, for philosophers working in ethics, metaethics and relevant areas of applied ethics, this volume is a useful resource on the various issues raised by the Trolley Problem. Finally, this volume—while generally of high quality—contains a number of particularly outstanding or otherwise noteworthy chapters. These alone make it worth picking up, whether for a class or a particular research project. As already mentioned, Kamm's chapter provides a clear and comparatively accessible introduction to her recent work on Trolley Problems. For those interested in the relation between the DDE, the DDA, and Trolley Problems, the chapters by Nelkin and Rickless and Woollard provide plenty of material to work with. The chapters by Kahane and Everett and Greene should be at home on reading lists for many introductions to experimental philosophy or moral psychology. And finally, the chapters by Nyholm and Di Nucci provide interesting insights in their respective areas of applied philosophy. In sum, it is likely not the case that every chapter in this volume will be of interest to everyone, but that is somewhat to be expected with edited volumes which cover a range of areas. What this book does offer is a wide ranging discussion of one of contemporary moral philosophy's most iconic puzzles, which—much like the Trolley Problem itself—can offer many different things to many different people.","PeriodicalId":46553,"journal":{"name":"Ratio","volume":"200 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Ratio","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1111/rati.12393","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

The Trolley Problem, edited by Hallvard Lillehammer, is worth reading for a number of reasons. The Trolley Problem has sparked heated philosophical debate for over four decades, as well as scientific research, pop-culture references and memes. Sadly, among all this the actual questions the Trolley Problem set out to illustrate sometimes have a tendency to disappear into the background. As several of the authors in this volume point out, the Trolley Problem is sometimes thought to refer to the single case in which a Bystander has to choose whether to turn a runaway trolley onto a side-track. This is somewhat of an (over)simplification. For most writing on it, the Trolley Problem is about finding convincing explanations of the difference in permissibility between different cases featuring trolleys—such as the classic case, where someone is faced with the choice of switching a runaway trolley to a sidetrack, or the ‘Bridge’ case, where someone is faced with the choice of pushing a person off a bridge to stop a trolley. However, there are several different interpretations of the problem in circulation, and this may contribute to the confusion. One reason to recommend this volume, part of Cambridge University Press's ‘Classic Philosophical Arguments’ series, is that it does a genuinely good job of cutting through some of the noise. Its twelve chapters offer a range of reflections on the Trolley Problem, ‘trolleyology’, and related issues. Given the variety of issues covered, space does not permit me to discuss any one chapter in great detail. Instead, for the purposes of this review, I will comment on some more general points. First, however, I will briefly outline the range of topics covered in this volume. It encompasses traditional (deontological) discussions of the Trolley Problem, as well as virtue ethical approaches, moral psychology, cross-cultural empirical analysis, and applied philosophy. The first chapter, by Lillehammer, provides a helpful overview of the history of the Trolley Problem, and includes reflections on Foot, Thomson and Kamm, as well as a response to Barbara Fried's important critique of the Trolley Problem (see Fried, 2012). The first set of chapters, by William J. FitzPatrick, Peter A. Graham, F.M. Kamm, Dana Kay Nelkin and Samuel Rickless, and Fiona Woollard, tackle various aspects of the Trolley Problem from a broadly deontological perspective. In his chapter, FitzPatrick argues that Judith Jarvis Thompson (in)famous change of heart with regards to the classic case was unwarranted. Instead, he suggests that the problem can be explained by appeal to reasonable norms of shared risk. Next, Graham focuses on the question of whether it is merely permissible or obligatory to turn the trolley in the standard case. He takes aim at Helen Frowe, who argues that it is obligatory. Contrary to Frowe, Graham maintains that it is (merely) permissible to turn the trolley by appealing to previous work by Kamm (2007, 2016). Following Graham, Kamm herself agrees and offers a clear and characteristically detailed discussion of some of the key arguments for her view that it is permissible to turn the trolley from an explicitly non-consequentialist perspective. It is a particularly useful and concise overview of some of her recent work on this topic and would therefore serve well to introduce people (for example, students) to her work. Taking a slightly different angle, Nelkin and Rickless, as well as Woollard, focus on the Doctrine of Double Effect (DDE) and Doctrine of Doing and Allowing (DDA)—both often used to attempt to explain the difference in permissibility between various trolley cases. Nelkin and Rickless argue, importantly, that classical formulations of trolley cases fail to take risk into account. By drawing on Warren Quinn's interpretation of the DDE (Quinn, 1989), which distinguishes between direct and indirect harmful agency, they argue that a probabilistic version of the principle can be constructed to deal with these more complex cases. On the other hand, Woollard focuses on the DDA, another principle often wheeled out to help resolve the Trolley Problem. Woollard argues that the relationship between the DDA and the Trolley Problem is, however, considerably more complex. Specifically, the DDA should not be understood as a solution to the problem, but nor should the Trolley Problem be considered a proof that the DDA is morally irrelevant. Rather, her analysis suggests that an additional principle is needed—a sister principle to the DDA—to explain common intuitions about these cases. Following this set of deontological investigations, the contributions to this book take (somewhat) more unexpected approaches. Liezl van Zyl considers the Trolley Problem from a virtue ethical perspective. She makes a number of important points that those writing on Trolley Problems should take into serious consideration. Her virtue ethical analysis of the ‘Bridge’ case is particularly worth noting. Van Zyl claims it is unlikely that a moderately virtuous person would, when faced with such a situation, look at a fellow human being on the bridge and think of them as a ‘heavy object’ that can be used to stop the trolley. As she notes, her students—when presented with a less leading example of the Bridge case—come up with standard suggestions: ‘[the men] should yell out, blow a whistle, wave their arms, run toward the workmen, look for a heavy object further down the track, etc. So far, none of them have proposed that [Bystander] should consider pushing the big man onto the track.’ (p. 128) Her overall argument is that proponents of virtue ethics can support common intuitions about trolley cases, including Bridge. However, this is for very different reasons than those appealed to by deontologists. The next two chapters are an interesting debate between, on the one hand, Guy Kahane and Jim Everett and on the other, Joshua D. Greene. Kahane and Everett consider the use of Trolley Problems in contemporary psychological research, and the way this research has often been framed in terms of a contrast between deontological and utilitarian approaches to morality. They claim this framing is misleading—first, because some of the responses researchers classify as ‘utilitarian’ are at best tangentially utilitarian (and more often self-interested or simply consequentialist) and second, because they suspect it is difficult to generalize from these kinds of cases to more general claims about moral reasoning. Greene, on the other hand, has done extensive psychological research using trolley problems and related cases and he can quite rightly be considered a pioneer in this particular area of the field. Here he argues (pace Kahane and Everett, but also several other critics) that the empirical study of how people react to Trolley Problems has significantly improved our understanding of the psychological mechanics of moral judgment. He claims in particular that his empirical research has demonstrated the evidential or justificatory limitations of intuitions about moral dilemmas. Natalie Gold, in her chapter, also draws on a number of empirical studies, but her interest in those studies looking at how people from different (cultural) backgrounds respond to Trolley Problems. She provides a critical and detailed survey of this literature and shows that the picture that emerges from these studies is mixed. It is possible to conclude from these studies that there do exist differences in judgment about trolley cases between cultures, but the number of studies that can be used for this analysis is relatively small. Moreover, Gold argues, it is plausible to think of these differences as evidence for ethical constructivism. Finally, the last two chapters focus on the application of Trolley Problems to two areas within applied philosophy: Sven Nyholm considers the ethics of self-driving cars, and Ezio Di Nucci considers the Trolley Problem in the context of healthcare, and specifically the COVID-19 pandemic. Both offer interesting, critical, discussions of the use (and occasional abuse) of Trolley Problems in the context of applied ethics, public policy, and law. In this volume, there are a number of overarching themes and issues that come to the fore, which mean that while there certainly is value in picking it up to read just one or the other chapter, it would also be rewarding to read the whole book—or at least the sets of chapters corresponding to one's area of academic interest. This is the second reason why this volume is worth reading. However, as noted at the outset, it is not always clear in the wider literature what the Trolley Problem actually is. And this book, perhaps surprisingly, does not provide a clear answer to that question either. Indeed, it is interesting to note that even in a book about the Trolley Problem, different chapters offer subtly different explanations. For example, Woollard—like Lillehammer and some of the other contributors—points to the issue of explaining the difference in perceived permissibility between the classical case and cases such as Bridge. Thus, in Woollard's words, the real Trolley Problem ‘is to explain why you are permitted to turn the trolley [in the classic trolley case] when there are many cases where intuitively you are not permitted to kill one person to save five’ (p. 101). But FitzPatrick offers a subtly different interpretation: he suggests that the relevant problem is the question ‘What is it about the sort of diversion involved in [the standard case] that makes for an exception to the usual proscription against killing some to save others (assuming we accept some version of that non-consequentialist constraint in the other cases)?’ (p. 27). Finally, going against the grain somewhat, Graham identifies the question of whether it is merely permissible or required to turn the trolley as the central problem of concern. One might perhaps wish that the authors had ensured a bit more consistency between their explanations of what exactly the problem is, and the slight shifts in explanation may confuse someone coming to this area with little background knowledge. That being said, we also have here a great illustration of the complex and somewhat slippery nature of the puzzle posed by the Trolley Problem. Through reading this volume, it becomes clear just how rich a thought experiment Foot and Thomson's invention really is—rather than a single Trolley Problem, it becomes clear there are multiple serious moral issues raised by these apparently simple cases. And as the chapters by Greene and Kahane and Everett highlight, pursuing an empirical, utilitarian approach is not a guarantee you can entirely avoid them—though the issues faced by experimental philosophers and psychologists when trying to make sense of the Trolley Problem may be somewhat different, of course. Whether this is an issue with the volume will depend a lot on the audience, I suspect. As noted, for someone coming at this with little background knowledge, or someone really keen to find out what, precisely, the Trolley Problem is, the ambiguity could create confusion. If assigned as part of, for example, an undergraduate course, it may therefore require some careful explanation by the instructors. However, for philosophers working in ethics, metaethics and relevant areas of applied ethics, this volume is a useful resource on the various issues raised by the Trolley Problem. Finally, this volume—while generally of high quality—contains a number of particularly outstanding or otherwise noteworthy chapters. These alone make it worth picking up, whether for a class or a particular research project. As already mentioned, Kamm's chapter provides a clear and comparatively accessible introduction to her recent work on Trolley Problems. For those interested in the relation between the DDE, the DDA, and Trolley Problems, the chapters by Nelkin and Rickless and Woollard provide plenty of material to work with. The chapters by Kahane and Everett and Greene should be at home on reading lists for many introductions to experimental philosophy or moral psychology. And finally, the chapters by Nyholm and Di Nucci provide interesting insights in their respective areas of applied philosophy. In sum, it is likely not the case that every chapter in this volume will be of interest to everyone, but that is somewhat to be expected with edited volumes which cover a range of areas. What this book does offer is a wide ranging discussion of one of contemporary moral philosophy's most iconic puzzles, which—much like the Trolley Problem itself—can offer many different things to many different people.
《电车问题》,哈尔瓦德·利勒哈默著,剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2023年。ix + 267页,74.99英镑(hb)/ 26.99英镑(pb) ISBN: 9781009255592
范·齐尔称,一个品行尚可的人在面对这种情况时,不太可能把桥上的人当成一个可以用来让电车停下来的“重物”。正如她所指出的,她的学生们——当看到一个不那么重要的桥案的例子时——会提出标准的建议:“(男人们)应该大喊大叫,吹口哨,挥舞手臂,向工人跑去,寻找更远的轨道上的重物,等等。”到目前为止,没有人建议(旁观者)应该考虑把这个大个子推到赛道上。(第128页)她的总体论点是,美德伦理学的支持者可以支持电车案例的共同直觉,包括桥牌。然而,这是出于与义务论者所呼吁的完全不同的原因。接下来的两章是一场有趣的辩论,一方是盖伊·卡哈内和吉姆·埃弗雷特,另一方是约书亚·d·格林。Kahane和Everett考虑了电车问题在当代心理学研究中的应用,而这项研究的方式通常是在道德的义务论和功利主义方法之间的对比中进行的。他们声称这种框架具有误导性——首先,因为研究人员归类为“功利主义”的一些反应充其量是切线功利主义(更经常是利己主义或简单的结果主义);其次,因为他们怀疑很难从这些案例中归纳出更普遍的道德推理主张。另一方面,格林利用电车问题和相关案例进行了广泛的心理学研究,他完全可以被认为是这一领域的先驱。在这里,他(佩斯·卡哈恩和埃弗雷特,以及其他几位批评家)认为,对人们如何应对电车问题的实证研究,极大地提高了我们对道德判断的心理机制的理解。他特别声称,他的实证研究已经证明了关于道德困境的直觉的证据性或正当性局限性。娜塔莉·戈尔德(Natalie Gold)在她的章节中也引用了一些实证研究,但她的兴趣在于那些研究来自不同(文化)背景的人如何应对电车问题的研究。她对这些文献进行了批判性和详细的调查,并表明从这些研究中出现的画面是混合的。有可能从这些研究中得出结论,不同文化之间对电车案件的判断确实存在差异,但可用于此分析的研究数量相对较少。此外,戈尔德认为,将这些差异视为道德建构主义的证据是合理的。最后,最后两章重点介绍了电车问题在应用哲学中的两个领域的应用:斯文·尼霍姆(Sven Nyholm)考虑了自动驾驶汽车的伦理,埃齐奥·迪·努奇(Ezio Di Nucci)考虑了医疗保健背景下的电车问题,特别是COVID-19大流行。两者都在应用伦理学、公共政策和法律的背景下,对电车问题的使用(以及偶尔的滥用)进行了有趣、批判性的讨论。在这本书中,有许多重要的主题和问题出现在前面,这意味着虽然拿起它读一章或另一章肯定是有价值的,但读整本书也会有回报——或者至少是与你的学术兴趣领域相对应的章节集。这是本书值得一读的第二个原因。然而,正如一开始所指出的,在更广泛的文献中,并不总是清楚电车问题到底是什么。也许令人惊讶的是,这本书也没有为这个问题提供一个明确的答案。事实上,有趣的是,即使在一本关于电车问题的书中,不同的章节也提供了微妙的不同解释。例如,woolard——像Lillehammer和其他一些贡献者一样——指出了解释经典案例和Bridge等案例之间感知可容许性差异的问题。因此,用伍拉德的话来说,真正的电车问题“是解释为什么(在经典电车情况下)你被允许改变电车方向,而在很多情况下,直觉上你不允许杀死一个人来救五个人”(第101页)。但菲茨帕特里克提出了一个微妙的不同解释:他认为相关的问题是:“(标准情况下)所涉及的这种转移是什么,它使通常禁止杀人救人的禁令成为例外(假设我们在其他情况下接受这种非结果主义约束的某种版本)?”(第27页)。最后,格雷厄姆提出了一个问题,即是否允许或必须让电车转向,这是他所关注的核心问题。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
Ratio
Ratio PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
1.00
自引率
0.00%
发文量
33
期刊介绍: Ratio publishes work of a high quality on a wide variety of topics. It encourages articles which meet the highest standards of philosophical expertise, while at the same time remaining accessible to readers from a broad range of philosophical disciplines. The journal"s main emphasis is on analytic philosophy, but it also includes work from other traditions.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信