The Incomprehensible “Unworlded World”: Nature and Abyss in Heideggerian Thought

IF 1.1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Richard J. Colledge
{"title":"The Incomprehensible “Unworlded World”: Nature and Abyss in Heideggerian Thought","authors":"Richard J. Colledge","doi":"10.1080/00071773.2023.2259435","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTThe complexities of Heidegger’s early accounts of nature provide a privileged perspective from which to understand the evolution of his thought into the 1930s and beyond. This movement seems largely driven by his response to what Karsten Harries has called “the antinomy of being”. In Heidegger’s early writings, Natur is associated with the “theoretical” and the “intraworldly.” However, less attested is an “unworlded” and thus intrinsically “incomprehensible” sense of nature, as the abyssal ground of worlding. This thread is traced through key Marburg period texts, into Being and Time, and beyond it into the 1928 “metontology” appendix and its surprising transformation in the 1929 inaugural lecture. Finally, some cursory observations are made about how this trajectory unfolds in later Heideggerian thought, taking the 1936 Artwork essay as an example, showing how both sides of the antinomy of being come to be incorporated within a more comprehensive framing of the Seinsfrage.KEYWORDS: Heideggernatureworldbeingantinomymetontology Notes1 In terms of English language scholarship alone, it was noted long ago by Hubert Dreyfus in his influential commentary (Dreyfus, 109–115), shortly thereafter in a more detailed way by Bruce Foltz in his study on Heidegger and environmental ethics (Foltz, 31–33 ff), and it has been taken up more recently by Michael Lewis (chapter 1), David Storey (66–79ff), and in papers by other scholars (e.g., Padui; and Cooper).2 The theme of ontological surplus or excess is one that has been broached from a variety of angles in recent Heidegger scholarship, in ways that differ and overlap with the approach taken here. For example, in his fine overview of the theme in Kant and post-Kantian thought, Richard Kearney sees it as culminating in Heidegger’s conception of Dasein and the power of imagination. As will be seen, a very different notion of surplus is developed in this essay. Other approaches are closer to the one developed here, such as those of Polt, Storey, and more broadly, Capobianco (Heidegger’s Way of Being).3 Harries, The Antinomy of Being. See footnote 18, below.4 SZ:158/ BT:200.5 SZ:85/ BT:118; SZ:63/ BT:91; SZ:25/ BT:47.6 SZ:362/ BT:413–414; GA24:457/ BPP:321; GA26: 16/ MFL:13.7 For example, the distinction, made in 1923, between “two basic characteristics” of disclosedness: “fore-appearing [vor-schein]” and “fore-presence [Vorhandenheit], in which the latter is framed not as an inadequate theoretical mode of projection of nature, but rather as the already-present background against which equipment appears (GA63:93/ OHF:71; transl from Kisiel, 331.)8 GA20:269/ HCT:198.9 GA20:269/ HCT:198.10 Cf: “[W]e do not reveal nature in its might and power by reflecting on it, but by struggling against it and by protecting ourselves from it and by dominating it” (GA:25: PIK:21/15). See Scheler’s engagement with Sein und Zeit around this issue of resistance and reality, in Scheler. In terms of more contemporary phenomenological approaches that bear comparison, see Günther Figal’s notion of das Gegenständliche as that which “stands over against [entgegensteht]” and “confronts” us (Objectivity, 3); and Lee Braver’s notion of “transgressive realism” which seems to develop a quite similar position (Braver).11 GA20:269/ HCT:198.12 SZ:70/ BT:100.13 Aristotle, Physics Book 2, 192b.14 SZ:388–89/ BT:440.15 GA20:270–71/ HCT:199.16 GA20:270–71/ HCT:198–99. Heidegger’s italics.17 SZ:71–72/ BT:101–02. Interestingly, there is a certain fluidity in Heidegger’s thinking about these matters in the period between the Marburg lectures and the publication of Being and Time. Whereas in 1925, Heidegger consistently speaks of intraworldly nature as a species of being-present-at-hand (e.g., “already-present” nature is the “Vorhandene in contrast to the zuhanden” [GA20: 270/ HCT:199]), in Being and Time precisely the same phenomena seem to have been incorporated into the ready-to-hand. As Theodore Kisiel puts it, this loss of a “more subtle and richer present-at-hand” in Being and Time, means that the category shrinks back to signify the abstract theoretical attitude alone; to a mere “presence that has been denuded of a world” (Kisiel, 332).18 What Harries identifies through his use of this term is not only the elemental rivalry between hermeneutic and ontic priority, but also their unavoidable mutuality. On the one hand, hermeneutics goes all the way down: there is no access to the real that is not already mediated through worldly dwelling and experience (reality). Indeed, in this sense, the very idea of reality “in itself” is an incoherent notion. But on the other hand, meaning, understanding and experience are only possible because the things of the world are in the first place, independently of their being-experienced. The real is that which is finitely experienced and understood, and so in this sense, talk of reality-as-experienced without the real is absurd. These two positions each have their own robust and undeniable claims to priority. We are therefore left with an aporia, or an antinomy (in a structurally Kantian sense of the term). Further – not coincidently mirroring the strife and the intimate complementarity of world and earth in Heidegger’s Kunstwerk essay – it is not feasible to favour one side of the antinomy over the other. Harries thus makes a systematic case for phenomenological (or hermeneutical) realism that places equal weight on both hermeneutics and realism as complementary poles of the antinomy of being as a whole. (For a further exploration of Harries’ account, see Colledge).19 GA20:298/ HCT:217.20 GA20:356/ HCT:258.21 This perhaps explains Kisiel’s otherwise inexplicable decision to enclose “unworlded” in scare quotes (omitted above) in his translation, where Heidegger’s entweltlichte is not so marked. Other translators, including Dreyfus in his commentary (Being-in-the-World, 205), do indeed render Heidegger’s text as “deworlded.”22 GA20:299/ HCT:218.23 Dostal, 142. Emphasis added.24 In this sense, Niels Bohr’s purported remark that “it is wrong to think that it is the task of physics to find out how nature is … Physics concerns what we can say about nature” (Petersen, 8), is somewhat misleading. Physics (like all the sciences) does concern nature, but its work is to find optimal (if inevitably inadequate) ways of revealing what is disclosed in the encounter. (My thanks to an anonymous reviewer for drawing my attention to this remark.)25 GA15:331/ FS:38.26 Michael Lewis, 2, uses the language of “nature in itself,” a term that (as seen above) has warrant in Heidegger’s own usage concerning the “Seienden als Seiendem an sich.”27 SZ:153/ BT:194.28 Of course, this fecund passage leaves to one side all manner of further questions – that consequently lie beyond the scope of this paper – relating to Heidegger’s understanding of the character and possibility of scientific inquiry and discourse. One might ask, for example, whether Heidegger sees the sciences as dealing with nature as intraworldly or as unworlded. Such a question, I suggest, is premised on the dubious assumption that the two are separable in this way. It would seem that for Heidegger in this passage (and here I put to one side the many ways that he addresses the question of science across the Gesamtausgabe, from the 1912 essay on “The Problem of Reality in Modern Philosophy” to the Le Thor Seminars from the late 1960s), intraworldliness is nothing other than the factical experience of (unworlded) nature. There are not two worlds, but one. Scientific inquiry, as empirical, is entirely dependent on projective understanding of the world as encountered: an encounter with the (unworlded) world. Science is in error, however, when it takes its own (justifiable but profoundly limited) “theoretical” projections of the world as giving it direct and potentially complete access to nature that is thereby stripped of its obscurity and laid bare in its vorhanden openness. In asserting the “incomprehensibility” of (unworlded) nature, and the “inadequacy” of discourses about nature, Heidegger is insisting that all discourses about the world are so partialized that the best we can hope for is a rough glimpse (albeit a potentially productive one) into the overwhelming presencing of nature. Nature as such – the real – is incomprehensible in anything like its full scope. That does not mean that the scientist (or indeed the person in ordinary engagement with the world) are cut off from the real world, cast adrift in a “second” illusory world, for we are all first of all in-the-world. Rather, as Glazebrook puts it, Heidegger’s “commitment to the transcendent actuality of nature goes hand in hand with the thesis that human understanding is projective” (“Heidegger and Scientific Realism”, 362). Finally, none of this says anything specific about the worth (dare I say “truth value”) of any one world projection vis-à-vis others. This important problem of philosophical hermeneutics is one that lies beyond Heidegger’s immediate concern, at least in this passage.29 See: SZ:212/ BT:255.30 The passages at issue in Being and Time are well known: (1) “Beings are quite independently of the experience by which they are disclosed, the acquaintance in which they are discovered, and the grasping in which their nature is ascertained. But Being ‘is’ only in the understanding of those beings to whose Being something like an understanding of Being belongs.” (SZ:183/ BT:228); (2) “Being (not beings [Seienden]) is dependent upon the understanding of Being; that is to say, reality [Realität] (not the Real [des Realen]) is dependent upon care.” (SZ:212/ BT:255); (3) “Being (not beings) is something which ‘there is [gibt es]’ only in so far as truth is.” (SZ:230/ BT:272.) To these can be added even more unequivocal passages from around the same time: e.g., “Beings are in themselves the kinds of beings they are, and in the way they are, even if, for example, Dasein does not exist.” (GA26:194/ MFL:153)31 Albeit with many qualifications, there is certainly a strong family resemblance here with Kant’s advocacy of transcendental idealism alongside empirical realism, a point that at least underlines the deeply transcendental structure of Being and Time.32 GA24:241/ BPP:170; see also, GA24:422/ BPP:297.33 Harries, “The Antinomy of Being”, 192. See also Harries, The Antinomy of Being, 13–17.34 GA24:235/ BPP:165; emphasis added.35 GA24:240/ BPP:169.36 GA24:240/ BPP:169. See also highly kindred passages across other works of this period: GA24:313/ BPP:219; GA25:19–20/ PIK:14; and GA26:250–51/ MFL:194–95; GA29/30: 405/ FCM: 279–80.37 Heidegger’s vacillations on this issue were highlighted by Karl Löwith at Heidegger’s 80th birthday colloquium in Heidelberg in 1969. Löwith complains: [W]hat I missed by the existential mode of inquiry was nature – which is all about us and our selves. When nature is lacking … it cannot be brought in supplementarily afterwards. For what is nature supposed to be if it is not the nature of all beings, whose power of generation permits everything which in any way is – and thus even man – to proceed from it and to pass away again? (Löwith, 311)38 SZ:152/ BT:193–94; translation altered.39 SZ: 35–36/BT: 60; emphasis added.40 SZ:436/ BT:487.41 GA24:33/ BPP:24.42 GA26:199/ MFL:156–57.43 GA9:111/ PM:88.44 GA9:114/ PM:90; translation amended.45 Concerning this “whole of beings,” it should also not go unnoticed that early in Being and Time, Dasein is said to have an “ontico-ontological priority” in relation to the question of being, according to which it possesses “an understanding of the Being of all beings of a character other than its own” (SZ:13/ BT:34).46 Polt, 34, 27; emphasis added. Given terminological confusion around the language of “existence,” Polt prefers to name this thatness, “excess.”47 This shift does not involve any new exclusion of ontic grounds. To the contrary, in 1935, Heidegger can still say frankly and unremarkably that “the building stands there [understood ontically] even if we do not observe it. We can come across it only because it already is.” (GA40:25/ IM:36) It is more that Heidegger’s primary focus was on the opening by which world entry happens on the basis of the given ontic (ungrounded, unworlded) ground.48 GA15:135/ FS:79.49 GA15:101–03/ FS:59–60. It is worth noting that this insight is something already foreshadowed in Heidegger’s discussion of phenomenology in Being and Time: “What is it that phenomenology is to ‘let us see’? … Manifestly, it is something that proximally and for the most part does not show itself at all: it is something that lies hidden, in contrast to that which proximally and for the most part does show itself; but at the same time it is something that belongs to what thus shows itself, and it belongs to it so essentially as to constitute its meaning and its ground … [T]hat which remains hidden … [is] the Being of [beings] (SZ:35/ BT:59).50 GA4:26,59/ EHP:45,82.51 Richard Capobianco (Heidegger’s Way of Being, chapters 5–6 and Heidegger’s Being, chapter 1) has written with great insight on Heidegger’s engagements with the Heraclitus fragments, particularly his insistence on the ineluctable lethic reserve (or hiddenness) of being.52 GA79:5/ BFL:5.53 GA5:28,33/ OBT:21,25.54 GA5:28/ OBT:21.55 GA5:58/ OBT:43.56 GA5:51 / OBT:38.","PeriodicalId":44348,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.1000,"publicationDate":"2023-09-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00071773.2023.2259435","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

ABSTRACTThe complexities of Heidegger’s early accounts of nature provide a privileged perspective from which to understand the evolution of his thought into the 1930s and beyond. This movement seems largely driven by his response to what Karsten Harries has called “the antinomy of being”. In Heidegger’s early writings, Natur is associated with the “theoretical” and the “intraworldly.” However, less attested is an “unworlded” and thus intrinsically “incomprehensible” sense of nature, as the abyssal ground of worlding. This thread is traced through key Marburg period texts, into Being and Time, and beyond it into the 1928 “metontology” appendix and its surprising transformation in the 1929 inaugural lecture. Finally, some cursory observations are made about how this trajectory unfolds in later Heideggerian thought, taking the 1936 Artwork essay as an example, showing how both sides of the antinomy of being come to be incorporated within a more comprehensive framing of the Seinsfrage.KEYWORDS: Heideggernatureworldbeingantinomymetontology Notes1 In terms of English language scholarship alone, it was noted long ago by Hubert Dreyfus in his influential commentary (Dreyfus, 109–115), shortly thereafter in a more detailed way by Bruce Foltz in his study on Heidegger and environmental ethics (Foltz, 31–33 ff), and it has been taken up more recently by Michael Lewis (chapter 1), David Storey (66–79ff), and in papers by other scholars (e.g., Padui; and Cooper).2 The theme of ontological surplus or excess is one that has been broached from a variety of angles in recent Heidegger scholarship, in ways that differ and overlap with the approach taken here. For example, in his fine overview of the theme in Kant and post-Kantian thought, Richard Kearney sees it as culminating in Heidegger’s conception of Dasein and the power of imagination. As will be seen, a very different notion of surplus is developed in this essay. Other approaches are closer to the one developed here, such as those of Polt, Storey, and more broadly, Capobianco (Heidegger’s Way of Being).3 Harries, The Antinomy of Being. See footnote 18, below.4 SZ:158/ BT:200.5 SZ:85/ BT:118; SZ:63/ BT:91; SZ:25/ BT:47.6 SZ:362/ BT:413–414; GA24:457/ BPP:321; GA26: 16/ MFL:13.7 For example, the distinction, made in 1923, between “two basic characteristics” of disclosedness: “fore-appearing [vor-schein]” and “fore-presence [Vorhandenheit], in which the latter is framed not as an inadequate theoretical mode of projection of nature, but rather as the already-present background against which equipment appears (GA63:93/ OHF:71; transl from Kisiel, 331.)8 GA20:269/ HCT:198.9 GA20:269/ HCT:198.10 Cf: “[W]e do not reveal nature in its might and power by reflecting on it, but by struggling against it and by protecting ourselves from it and by dominating it” (GA:25: PIK:21/15). See Scheler’s engagement with Sein und Zeit around this issue of resistance and reality, in Scheler. In terms of more contemporary phenomenological approaches that bear comparison, see Günther Figal’s notion of das Gegenständliche as that which “stands over against [entgegensteht]” and “confronts” us (Objectivity, 3); and Lee Braver’s notion of “transgressive realism” which seems to develop a quite similar position (Braver).11 GA20:269/ HCT:198.12 SZ:70/ BT:100.13 Aristotle, Physics Book 2, 192b.14 SZ:388–89/ BT:440.15 GA20:270–71/ HCT:199.16 GA20:270–71/ HCT:198–99. Heidegger’s italics.17 SZ:71–72/ BT:101–02. Interestingly, there is a certain fluidity in Heidegger’s thinking about these matters in the period between the Marburg lectures and the publication of Being and Time. Whereas in 1925, Heidegger consistently speaks of intraworldly nature as a species of being-present-at-hand (e.g., “already-present” nature is the “Vorhandene in contrast to the zuhanden” [GA20: 270/ HCT:199]), in Being and Time precisely the same phenomena seem to have been incorporated into the ready-to-hand. As Theodore Kisiel puts it, this loss of a “more subtle and richer present-at-hand” in Being and Time, means that the category shrinks back to signify the abstract theoretical attitude alone; to a mere “presence that has been denuded of a world” (Kisiel, 332).18 What Harries identifies through his use of this term is not only the elemental rivalry between hermeneutic and ontic priority, but also their unavoidable mutuality. On the one hand, hermeneutics goes all the way down: there is no access to the real that is not already mediated through worldly dwelling and experience (reality). Indeed, in this sense, the very idea of reality “in itself” is an incoherent notion. But on the other hand, meaning, understanding and experience are only possible because the things of the world are in the first place, independently of their being-experienced. The real is that which is finitely experienced and understood, and so in this sense, talk of reality-as-experienced without the real is absurd. These two positions each have their own robust and undeniable claims to priority. We are therefore left with an aporia, or an antinomy (in a structurally Kantian sense of the term). Further – not coincidently mirroring the strife and the intimate complementarity of world and earth in Heidegger’s Kunstwerk essay – it is not feasible to favour one side of the antinomy over the other. Harries thus makes a systematic case for phenomenological (or hermeneutical) realism that places equal weight on both hermeneutics and realism as complementary poles of the antinomy of being as a whole. (For a further exploration of Harries’ account, see Colledge).19 GA20:298/ HCT:217.20 GA20:356/ HCT:258.21 This perhaps explains Kisiel’s otherwise inexplicable decision to enclose “unworlded” in scare quotes (omitted above) in his translation, where Heidegger’s entweltlichte is not so marked. Other translators, including Dreyfus in his commentary (Being-in-the-World, 205), do indeed render Heidegger’s text as “deworlded.”22 GA20:299/ HCT:218.23 Dostal, 142. Emphasis added.24 In this sense, Niels Bohr’s purported remark that “it is wrong to think that it is the task of physics to find out how nature is … Physics concerns what we can say about nature” (Petersen, 8), is somewhat misleading. Physics (like all the sciences) does concern nature, but its work is to find optimal (if inevitably inadequate) ways of revealing what is disclosed in the encounter. (My thanks to an anonymous reviewer for drawing my attention to this remark.)25 GA15:331/ FS:38.26 Michael Lewis, 2, uses the language of “nature in itself,” a term that (as seen above) has warrant in Heidegger’s own usage concerning the “Seienden als Seiendem an sich.”27 SZ:153/ BT:194.28 Of course, this fecund passage leaves to one side all manner of further questions – that consequently lie beyond the scope of this paper – relating to Heidegger’s understanding of the character and possibility of scientific inquiry and discourse. One might ask, for example, whether Heidegger sees the sciences as dealing with nature as intraworldly or as unworlded. Such a question, I suggest, is premised on the dubious assumption that the two are separable in this way. It would seem that for Heidegger in this passage (and here I put to one side the many ways that he addresses the question of science across the Gesamtausgabe, from the 1912 essay on “The Problem of Reality in Modern Philosophy” to the Le Thor Seminars from the late 1960s), intraworldliness is nothing other than the factical experience of (unworlded) nature. There are not two worlds, but one. Scientific inquiry, as empirical, is entirely dependent on projective understanding of the world as encountered: an encounter with the (unworlded) world. Science is in error, however, when it takes its own (justifiable but profoundly limited) “theoretical” projections of the world as giving it direct and potentially complete access to nature that is thereby stripped of its obscurity and laid bare in its vorhanden openness. In asserting the “incomprehensibility” of (unworlded) nature, and the “inadequacy” of discourses about nature, Heidegger is insisting that all discourses about the world are so partialized that the best we can hope for is a rough glimpse (albeit a potentially productive one) into the overwhelming presencing of nature. Nature as such – the real – is incomprehensible in anything like its full scope. That does not mean that the scientist (or indeed the person in ordinary engagement with the world) are cut off from the real world, cast adrift in a “second” illusory world, for we are all first of all in-the-world. Rather, as Glazebrook puts it, Heidegger’s “commitment to the transcendent actuality of nature goes hand in hand with the thesis that human understanding is projective” (“Heidegger and Scientific Realism”, 362). Finally, none of this says anything specific about the worth (dare I say “truth value”) of any one world projection vis-à-vis others. This important problem of philosophical hermeneutics is one that lies beyond Heidegger’s immediate concern, at least in this passage.29 See: SZ:212/ BT:255.30 The passages at issue in Being and Time are well known: (1) “Beings are quite independently of the experience by which they are disclosed, the acquaintance in which they are discovered, and the grasping in which their nature is ascertained. But Being ‘is’ only in the understanding of those beings to whose Being something like an understanding of Being belongs.” (SZ:183/ BT:228); (2) “Being (not beings [Seienden]) is dependent upon the understanding of Being; that is to say, reality [Realität] (not the Real [des Realen]) is dependent upon care.” (SZ:212/ BT:255); (3) “Being (not beings) is something which ‘there is [gibt es]’ only in so far as truth is.” (SZ:230/ BT:272.) To these can be added even more unequivocal passages from around the same time: e.g., “Beings are in themselves the kinds of beings they are, and in the way they are, even if, for example, Dasein does not exist.” (GA26:194/ MFL:153)31 Albeit with many qualifications, there is certainly a strong family resemblance here with Kant’s advocacy of transcendental idealism alongside empirical realism, a point that at least underlines the deeply transcendental structure of Being and Time.32 GA24:241/ BPP:170; see also, GA24:422/ BPP:297.33 Harries, “The Antinomy of Being”, 192. See also Harries, The Antinomy of Being, 13–17.34 GA24:235/ BPP:165; emphasis added.35 GA24:240/ BPP:169.36 GA24:240/ BPP:169. See also highly kindred passages across other works of this period: GA24:313/ BPP:219; GA25:19–20/ PIK:14; and GA26:250–51/ MFL:194–95; GA29/30: 405/ FCM: 279–80.37 Heidegger’s vacillations on this issue were highlighted by Karl Löwith at Heidegger’s 80th birthday colloquium in Heidelberg in 1969. Löwith complains: [W]hat I missed by the existential mode of inquiry was nature – which is all about us and our selves. When nature is lacking … it cannot be brought in supplementarily afterwards. For what is nature supposed to be if it is not the nature of all beings, whose power of generation permits everything which in any way is – and thus even man – to proceed from it and to pass away again? (Löwith, 311)38 SZ:152/ BT:193–94; translation altered.39 SZ: 35–36/BT: 60; emphasis added.40 SZ:436/ BT:487.41 GA24:33/ BPP:24.42 GA26:199/ MFL:156–57.43 GA9:111/ PM:88.44 GA9:114/ PM:90; translation amended.45 Concerning this “whole of beings,” it should also not go unnoticed that early in Being and Time, Dasein is said to have an “ontico-ontological priority” in relation to the question of being, according to which it possesses “an understanding of the Being of all beings of a character other than its own” (SZ:13/ BT:34).46 Polt, 34, 27; emphasis added. Given terminological confusion around the language of “existence,” Polt prefers to name this thatness, “excess.”47 This shift does not involve any new exclusion of ontic grounds. To the contrary, in 1935, Heidegger can still say frankly and unremarkably that “the building stands there [understood ontically] even if we do not observe it. We can come across it only because it already is.” (GA40:25/ IM:36) It is more that Heidegger’s primary focus was on the opening by which world entry happens on the basis of the given ontic (ungrounded, unworlded) ground.48 GA15:135/ FS:79.49 GA15:101–03/ FS:59–60. It is worth noting that this insight is something already foreshadowed in Heidegger’s discussion of phenomenology in Being and Time: “What is it that phenomenology is to ‘let us see’? … Manifestly, it is something that proximally and for the most part does not show itself at all: it is something that lies hidden, in contrast to that which proximally and for the most part does show itself; but at the same time it is something that belongs to what thus shows itself, and it belongs to it so essentially as to constitute its meaning and its ground … [T]hat which remains hidden … [is] the Being of [beings] (SZ:35/ BT:59).50 GA4:26,59/ EHP:45,82.51 Richard Capobianco (Heidegger’s Way of Being, chapters 5–6 and Heidegger’s Being, chapter 1) has written with great insight on Heidegger’s engagements with the Heraclitus fragments, particularly his insistence on the ineluctable lethic reserve (or hiddenness) of being.52 GA79:5/ BFL:5.53 GA5:28,33/ OBT:21,25.54 GA5:28/ OBT:21.55 GA5:58/ OBT:43.56 GA5:51 / OBT:38.
不可理解的“非世界”:海德格尔思想中的自然与深渊
海德格尔早期对自然的复杂描述提供了一个特殊的视角来理解他的思想在20世纪30年代及以后的演变。这场运动似乎在很大程度上是由他对卡斯滕·哈里斯(Karsten harris)所说的“存在的二律背反”的回应所推动的。在海德格尔的早期作品中,自然与“理论”和“世俗”联系在一起。然而,较少证实的是一种“无世界”,因此本质上是“不可理解”的自然感觉,作为世界的深渊。这条线索可以追溯到马尔堡时期的关键文本,到《存在与时间》,再到1928年的“转喻学”附录,以及1929年就职演讲中令人惊讶的转变。最后,以1936年的《艺术》文章为例,粗略地观察了这一轨迹在海德格尔后来的思想中是如何展开的,展示了存在的矛盾的两个方面是如何被纳入一个更全面的Seinsfrage框架的。注1仅就英语学术而言,很久以前休伯特·德雷福斯(Hubert Dreyfus)就在他的有影响力的评论中提到了这一点(德雷福斯,109-115页),此后不久,布鲁斯·福尔茨(Bruce Foltz)在他对海德格和环境伦理的研究中更详细地提到了这一点(福尔茨,31-33页),最近迈克尔·刘易斯(第1章)、大卫·斯托里(66 - 79页)和其他学者(如帕杜伊;和Cooper)。2本体论盈余或过剩的主题是最近海德格尔学术从各种角度提出的主题,其方式与本文所采用的方法不同或重叠。例如,Richard Kearney在他对康德和后康德思想主题的细致概述中,将其视为海德格尔的此在和想象力的力量概念的高潮。正如我们将看到的,这篇文章提出了一个非常不同的剩余概念。其他的方法更接近于这里发展的方法,如波尔特,斯托里,更广泛地说,卡波比安科(海德格尔的存在方式)《存在的二律背反》。见下文脚注18Sz:158/ bt:200.5 Sz:85/ bt:118;深圳:63 / BT: 91;Sz:25/ bt:47.6 Sz:362/ bt: 413-414;GA24:457 / BPP: 321;GA26: 16/ MFL:13.7例如,1923年对公开的“两种基本特征”的区分:“预先出现(vor-schein)”和“预先存在(Vorhandenheit)”,其中后者的框架不是作为自然投射的不充分的理论模式,而是作为设备出现的已经存在的背景(GA63:93/ OHF:71;8 GA20:269/ HCT:198.9 GA20:269/ HCT:198.10 Cf:“我们不是通过反思自然来揭示自然的力量和力量,而是通过与之斗争,通过保护我们自己免受它的影响,通过支配它”(GA:25; PIK:21/15)。参见舍勒与《Sein and Zeit》围绕抵抗和现实问题的接触。就更现代的现象学方法而言,可以比较,看到g<s:1> nther Figal的das概念Gegenständliche是“反对[entgegensteht]”和“面对”我们的(客观性,3);以及Lee Braver的“越界现实主义”的概念,它似乎发展了一个非常相似的立场(Braver)GA20:269/ HCT:198.12 SZ:70/ BT:100.13亚里士多德,物理书2,1992 b.14Sz: 388-89 / bt:440.15 ga20:270-71 / hct:199.16 ga20:270-71 / hct: 198-99。海德格尔italics.17深圳:71 - 72 / BT: 101 - 02。有趣的是,在马尔堡演讲和《存在与时间》出版之间的这段时间里,海德格尔对这些问题的思考有一定的流动性。然而,在1925年,海德格尔一贯地把世俗的自然说成是一种现成的存在(例如,“已经存在”的自然是“相对于现成的存在”的Vorhandene [GA20: 270/ HCT:199]),而在《存在与时间》中,同样的现象似乎已经被纳入现成的存在。正如Theodore Kisiel所说,在《存在与时间》中失去了“更微妙和更丰富的现在”,这意味着范畴缩小到仅仅表示抽象的理论态度;到仅仅是“被剥夺了世界的存在”(Kisiel, 332)通过使用这个术语,哈里斯不仅指出了解释学和本体优先之间的基本竞争,而且还指出了它们不可避免的相互关系。一方面,解释学是一路向下的:没有任何通往真实的途径,而不是通过世俗的居住和经验(现实)来中介的。的确,在这个意义上,"自在"的实在概念本身就是一个不连贯的概念。但另一方面,意义、理解和经验之所以成为可能,只是因为世界上的事物首先是独立于它们的被经验的。实在是被有限地体验和理解的东西,因此在这个意义上,没有实在而谈论作为经验的实在是荒谬的。 这两种立场各有其强大且不可否认的优先地位。因此,留给我们的是一种不安,或一种矛盾(在康德的结构意义上)。此外——并非巧合地反映了海德格尔的艺术论文中世界和地球的冲突和亲密的互补性——偏袒矛盾的一方而不偏袒另一方是不可行的。因此,哈里斯为现象学(或解释学)现实主义提出了一个系统的案例,该案例将解释学和现实主义作为整体存在二律反的互补两极同等重视。(关于哈里斯的叙述的进一步探索,见《学院》)GA20:298/ HCT:217.20 GA20:356/ HCT:258.21这也许解释了基谢尔在翻译中把“非世界的”(unworld)括在引号里(上面省略了)这一令人莫名其妙的决定,在这里海德格尔的“整体性”(entweltlichte)并没有那么明显。其他翻译家,包括德雷福斯在他的评论(《世界中的存在》,205)中,确实将海德格尔的文本描述为“去世界化的”。[22] GA20:299/ HCT:218.23。强调added.24从这个意义上说,尼尔斯·玻尔所谓的“认为物理学的任务是发现自然是怎样的想法是错误的……物理学关注的是我们对自然的看法”(彼得森,8),这在某种程度上是误导性的。物理学(像所有的科学一样)确实关注自然,但它的工作是找到最优(如果不可避免地不充分)的方式来揭示在遭遇中所揭示的东西。(感谢一位匿名评论者提醒我注意这句话)25 GA15:331/ FS:38.26迈克尔·刘易斯(Michael Lewis), 2,使用了“自然本身”的语言,这个术语(如上所述)在海德格尔自己关于“Seienden als seiendm and sich”的用法中得到了保证。当然,这一丰富的段落将所有进一步的问题——因此超出了本文的范围——放在一边,这些问题与海德格尔对科学探究和话语的特征和可能性的理解有关。例如,有人可能会问,海德格尔是否将科学视为处理自然的属世界的还是非世界的。我认为,这样一个问题的前提是一个可疑的假设,即两者以这种方式可分离。对于海德格尔来说,在这段话中(这里我把他跨越整个《哲学》(Gesamtausgabe)解决科学问题的许多方式放在一边,从1912年的论文《现代哲学中的现实问题》到20世纪60年代末的勒托尔研讨会),内在世界只不过是(非世界的)自然的战术经验。没有两个世界,只有一个世界。作为经验主义的科学探究,完全依赖于对所遇到的世界的投射性理解:与(非世界)世界的相遇。然而,当科学把自己对世界的“理论”预测(合理但极其有限)作为直接和潜在的完全接近自然的途径时,它就错了,从而剥夺了它的晦涩性,暴露在它的vorhanden开放性中。在断言(非世界的)自然的“不可理解性”和关于自然的话语的“不充分性”时,海德格尔坚持认为,所有关于世界的话语都是如此的局部化,以至于我们所能期望的最好的结果是对自然压倒性存在的粗略一瞥(尽管是潜在的生产性的一瞥)。自然本身——真实的——在其全部范围内是不可理解的。这并不意味着科学家(或实际上与世界正常接触的人)与现实世界隔绝,在“第二个”虚幻世界中漂流,因为我们首先都在这个世界上。相反,正如格拉泽布鲁克所说,海德格尔“对自然的先验现实性的承诺与人类理解是投射性的这一命题密切相关”(《海德格尔与科学实在论》,362页)。最后,这些都没有具体说明任何一个世界投影相对于-à-vis其他世界的价值(我敢说“真实价值”)。哲学解释学的这个重要问题是海德格尔所不关心的,至少在这一段中是这样参见:SZ:212/ BT:255.30《存在与时间》中争论的段落是众所周知的:(1)“存在完全独立于它们被揭示的经验,它们被发现的认识,以及它们的本质被确定的把握。但存在只是存在于这些存在的知性中,而这些存在的知性也属于这些存在。“(sz:183/ bt:228);(2)存在(不是存在[Seienden])依赖于对存在的理解;也就是说,现实[Realität](不是真实的[des Realen])依赖于关心。(sz:212/ bt:255);(3)存在(而非存在)是一种只有在真理存在的范围内才有存在的东西。(sz:230/ bt:272)除此之外,还可以添加来自同一时期的更明确的段落:例如:
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.50
自引率
0.00%
发文量
25
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信