Divine and Human Providence: Philosophical, Psychological and Theological Approaches

IF 0.2 0 RELIGION
Ignacio Alberto Silva, Simon Kopf
{"title":"Divine and Human Providence: Philosophical, Psychological and Theological Approaches","authors":"Ignacio Alberto Silva, Simon Kopf","doi":"10.56315/pscf9-23silva","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"DIVINE AND HUMAN PROVIDENCE: Philosophical, Psychological and Theological Approaches by Ignacio Silva and Simon Maria Kopf, eds. New York: Routledge, 2022. 156 pages. Paperback; $52.95. ISBN: 9780367632267. *This volume of nine essays seeks to clarify the meaning of divine providence by employing the analogy of human providence, understood here as the prudent execution of deliberation and planning. Although the contributors cover fields as diverse as philosophy, natural and social sciences, and theology, this review covers only the chapters that engage with contemporary scientific research. *In the fourth chapter, Ignacio Silva is concerned with the ways in which contingent events provide a challenge to our conceptions of divine providence. He develops the thought of Aquinas in contrast to those who locate God's providential acts in the causal gaps in our current scientific understanding of creation (e.g., in quantum mechanics and evolutionary theory). The latter view is taken by those who subscribe to an approach called NIODA (non-interventionist objective divine action). An example of the NIODA approach to divine providence is Thomas Tracy's view that God acts through the structures of nature \"non-miraculously,\" a view which Silva thinks effectively renders God as one cause among countless other causes. Another example of the NIODA approach is Robert Russell's view that at the quantum level God may be seen to act as a cause of both general features and specific events alongside purely natural causes. Silva's primary critique here is that it compromises God's transcendence by making God's causal activity ontologically indistinguishable from natural causation. *To draw out what he thinks are the implications of Aquinas's view of contingent events for our understanding of divine providence, Silva first clarifies Aquinas's understanding of contingency. Indeterminism exists because of the hylomorphic composition of being--that is, matter establishes the range of possibilities for how it will be integrated by the organizing principle called \"form,\" even though the intelligibility of form is irreducible to the material it integrates. Silva provides a brief but helpful analogy from human providence, showing how contemporary military strategy accommodates contingencies by building the occurrence of both foreseen and unforeseen events (the \"material\") into the overall battle plan (the \"form\"). He also finds that Aquinas's understanding of indeterminism is congenial to our new understanding of physical reality. Noting how Heisenberg himself used Aristotle's concepts of potency and act, Silva explains that differently actuated potency explains the existence of indeterminism without the need for complementary (i.e., divine) causation. The indeterminism that permeates the created order is part and parcel of the secondary causes through which God, the primary cause, achieves his intended effect. *In the fifth chapter, Connie Svob examines current findings in psychology on the cognitive mechanisms of memory, judgment, and decision making and how our cognitive (in)capacities might provide a series of metaphors or models for human providence that finds its end in God. Svob begins by highlighting recent psychological research that suggests a great deal of human cognition is irrational (though sometimes beneficially so). Svob summarizes the \"dismal picture of the rational human mind\" with a list of seven \"cognitive illusions\"--including over-confidence, magical thinking, and the tendency to reduce probabilities to certainties--and a note on the unreliability of memory. Perhaps the most interesting insight Svob discovers in the research is how both bottom-up and top-down theories of memory contribute to a model of human providence directed toward finding its end in God: the events that shape our sense of identity can reveal God's providential action, while our sense of self can direct us toward specific ends, including the end of friendship with God. *Another possibly fruitful avenue of research is how involuntary and unconscious memory retrieval might provide a model for how the cultivation of virtues such as prudence can take place even when the subject is not conscious of such cultivation. The tip-of-the-tongue phenomenon provides for Svob an analogy for our dependence on God. Just as we find ourselves helpless when facing the inability to recall a forgotten name and thus must wait upon some external aid, so too we find ourselves helpless in discovering God and so must wait passively upon God's help. Similarly, Svob suggests that as human cognition reaches a limit of self-definition, it may thereby find itself wholly dependent upon God: \"to will consistently to live in the truth requires the grace of God\" (p. 87). In short, Svob's chapter is peppered with fruitful insights into how the life of the mind in relation to its natural objects provides ample analogies for the life of the mind that has God as its supernatural object. *In the sixth chapter, Emily Burdett approaches divine providence from the perspective of developmental psychology, pointing out that despite millennia of writing on divine providence little attention has been given to how individuals develop their understanding of God's action and providence. Burdett's method is to examine how children develop their understanding of God's involvement in the world, finding that from an early age children conceive of God as engaged in the world in active, responsive, and (possibly) benevolent ways. This research suggests to Burdett the existence of an intuitive notion of divine providence among humans that God should act benevolently in the world. By measuring the time infants look at different animate and inanimate objects, psychologists have been able to verify that infants are able to distinguish between agents and non-agents and can grasp the existence of intention motivating observed acts. By the time the child is 3-5 years of age, they can distinguish between ordinary agents (e.g., a parent) and extraordinary agents (e.g., God). Burdett then shows how children distinguish between human and supernatural agency through reference to a fascinating set of studies on children and prayer, which finds that as children grow older, they tend to place greater restrictions on the types of prayers that are acceptable or answerable. Still further research confirms that children at a relatively young age can discern between human and supernatural agency, including Burdett's own research that children believe God can perform acts that they think impossible for humans. Burdett then describes how research has shown that infants and children are drawn to benevolent actors and are averse to malevolent ones, leading Burdett to hypothesize that children are likely to conceive of supernatural agents as benevolent. Burdett concludes with some intriguing suggestions for further research, outlining potential methodologies for testing the above hypothesis. *As is often the case in volumes that incorporate a wide variety of disciplinary approaches, the editors' promise of a cohesive argument--in this case, that human providence functions as an effective analogy of divine providence--is not entirely met. However, this is not a significant weakness of the volume, as many of the essays are in themselves helpful contributions to an understanding of divine providence. What stands out to this reviewer is that, regardless of disciplinary perspective, both the thought of Thomas Aquinas and the method of analogical understanding continue to be rich resources to mine in the development of our understanding of providence, human and divine. *Reviewed by Scott Halse, Lecturer in philosophy and humanities at Vanier College, Montreal, QC H4L 3X9.","PeriodicalId":53927,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith","volume":"64 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.56315/pscf9-23silva","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"RELIGION","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

DIVINE AND HUMAN PROVIDENCE: Philosophical, Psychological and Theological Approaches by Ignacio Silva and Simon Maria Kopf, eds. New York: Routledge, 2022. 156 pages. Paperback; $52.95. ISBN: 9780367632267. *This volume of nine essays seeks to clarify the meaning of divine providence by employing the analogy of human providence, understood here as the prudent execution of deliberation and planning. Although the contributors cover fields as diverse as philosophy, natural and social sciences, and theology, this review covers only the chapters that engage with contemporary scientific research. *In the fourth chapter, Ignacio Silva is concerned with the ways in which contingent events provide a challenge to our conceptions of divine providence. He develops the thought of Aquinas in contrast to those who locate God's providential acts in the causal gaps in our current scientific understanding of creation (e.g., in quantum mechanics and evolutionary theory). The latter view is taken by those who subscribe to an approach called NIODA (non-interventionist objective divine action). An example of the NIODA approach to divine providence is Thomas Tracy's view that God acts through the structures of nature "non-miraculously," a view which Silva thinks effectively renders God as one cause among countless other causes. Another example of the NIODA approach is Robert Russell's view that at the quantum level God may be seen to act as a cause of both general features and specific events alongside purely natural causes. Silva's primary critique here is that it compromises God's transcendence by making God's causal activity ontologically indistinguishable from natural causation. *To draw out what he thinks are the implications of Aquinas's view of contingent events for our understanding of divine providence, Silva first clarifies Aquinas's understanding of contingency. Indeterminism exists because of the hylomorphic composition of being--that is, matter establishes the range of possibilities for how it will be integrated by the organizing principle called "form," even though the intelligibility of form is irreducible to the material it integrates. Silva provides a brief but helpful analogy from human providence, showing how contemporary military strategy accommodates contingencies by building the occurrence of both foreseen and unforeseen events (the "material") into the overall battle plan (the "form"). He also finds that Aquinas's understanding of indeterminism is congenial to our new understanding of physical reality. Noting how Heisenberg himself used Aristotle's concepts of potency and act, Silva explains that differently actuated potency explains the existence of indeterminism without the need for complementary (i.e., divine) causation. The indeterminism that permeates the created order is part and parcel of the secondary causes through which God, the primary cause, achieves his intended effect. *In the fifth chapter, Connie Svob examines current findings in psychology on the cognitive mechanisms of memory, judgment, and decision making and how our cognitive (in)capacities might provide a series of metaphors or models for human providence that finds its end in God. Svob begins by highlighting recent psychological research that suggests a great deal of human cognition is irrational (though sometimes beneficially so). Svob summarizes the "dismal picture of the rational human mind" with a list of seven "cognitive illusions"--including over-confidence, magical thinking, and the tendency to reduce probabilities to certainties--and a note on the unreliability of memory. Perhaps the most interesting insight Svob discovers in the research is how both bottom-up and top-down theories of memory contribute to a model of human providence directed toward finding its end in God: the events that shape our sense of identity can reveal God's providential action, while our sense of self can direct us toward specific ends, including the end of friendship with God. *Another possibly fruitful avenue of research is how involuntary and unconscious memory retrieval might provide a model for how the cultivation of virtues such as prudence can take place even when the subject is not conscious of such cultivation. The tip-of-the-tongue phenomenon provides for Svob an analogy for our dependence on God. Just as we find ourselves helpless when facing the inability to recall a forgotten name and thus must wait upon some external aid, so too we find ourselves helpless in discovering God and so must wait passively upon God's help. Similarly, Svob suggests that as human cognition reaches a limit of self-definition, it may thereby find itself wholly dependent upon God: "to will consistently to live in the truth requires the grace of God" (p. 87). In short, Svob's chapter is peppered with fruitful insights into how the life of the mind in relation to its natural objects provides ample analogies for the life of the mind that has God as its supernatural object. *In the sixth chapter, Emily Burdett approaches divine providence from the perspective of developmental psychology, pointing out that despite millennia of writing on divine providence little attention has been given to how individuals develop their understanding of God's action and providence. Burdett's method is to examine how children develop their understanding of God's involvement in the world, finding that from an early age children conceive of God as engaged in the world in active, responsive, and (possibly) benevolent ways. This research suggests to Burdett the existence of an intuitive notion of divine providence among humans that God should act benevolently in the world. By measuring the time infants look at different animate and inanimate objects, psychologists have been able to verify that infants are able to distinguish between agents and non-agents and can grasp the existence of intention motivating observed acts. By the time the child is 3-5 years of age, they can distinguish between ordinary agents (e.g., a parent) and extraordinary agents (e.g., God). Burdett then shows how children distinguish between human and supernatural agency through reference to a fascinating set of studies on children and prayer, which finds that as children grow older, they tend to place greater restrictions on the types of prayers that are acceptable or answerable. Still further research confirms that children at a relatively young age can discern between human and supernatural agency, including Burdett's own research that children believe God can perform acts that they think impossible for humans. Burdett then describes how research has shown that infants and children are drawn to benevolent actors and are averse to malevolent ones, leading Burdett to hypothesize that children are likely to conceive of supernatural agents as benevolent. Burdett concludes with some intriguing suggestions for further research, outlining potential methodologies for testing the above hypothesis. *As is often the case in volumes that incorporate a wide variety of disciplinary approaches, the editors' promise of a cohesive argument--in this case, that human providence functions as an effective analogy of divine providence--is not entirely met. However, this is not a significant weakness of the volume, as many of the essays are in themselves helpful contributions to an understanding of divine providence. What stands out to this reviewer is that, regardless of disciplinary perspective, both the thought of Thomas Aquinas and the method of analogical understanding continue to be rich resources to mine in the development of our understanding of providence, human and divine. *Reviewed by Scott Halse, Lecturer in philosophy and humanities at Vanier College, Montreal, QC H4L 3X9.
神与人的天意:哲学、心理学和神学方法
简而言之,Svob的章节充满了富有成效的见解,关于精神生活如何与自然对象相关联,为以上帝为超自然对象的精神生活提供了充足的类比。*在第六章中,Emily Burdett从发展心理学的角度来看待神的天意,指出尽管几千年来关于神的天意的著作很少有人关注个人是如何发展他们对神的行动和天意的理解的。伯德特的方法是研究儿童如何发展他们对上帝参与世界的理解,发现儿童从很小的时候就认为上帝以积极、回应和(可能)仁慈的方式参与世界。伯德特认为,这项研究表明,在人类中存在着一种直觉的神性观念,即上帝应该仁慈地在世界上行事。通过测量婴儿看不同的有生命的和无生命的物体的时间,心理学家已经能够证实婴儿能够区分能动者和非能动者,并且能够掌握动机动机的存在。当孩子3-5岁时,他们可以区分普通的主体(如父母)和特殊的主体(如上帝)。然后,伯德特通过一系列关于儿童和祈祷的有趣研究,展示了儿童是如何区分人类和超自然力量的。这些研究发现,随着儿童年龄的增长,他们倾向于对可接受或可回应的祈祷类型施加更大的限制。进一步的研究证实,儿童在相对较小的年龄就能分辨出人类和超自然的力量,包括伯德特自己的研究,儿童相信上帝可以完成他们认为人类不可能完成的事情。Burdett随后描述了研究如何显示婴儿和儿童被善良的演员所吸引,而对恶毒的演员反感,这导致Burdett假设儿童可能会认为超自然的行为者是仁慈的。Burdett总结了一些有趣的进一步研究建议,概述了测试上述假设的潜在方法。*就像在包含各种学科方法的卷中经常出现的情况一样,编辑们承诺的一个有凝聚力的论点——在这种情况下,人类的天意是神的天意的有效类比——没有完全实现。然而,这并不是这本书的一个重要弱点,因为许多文章本身对理解神的旨意有帮助。对于这个评论家来说,最突出的是,无论从哪个学科的角度来看,托马斯·阿奎那的思想和类比理解的方法都是丰富的资源,可以用来挖掘我们对天意、人类和神的理解的发展。* Scott Halse评论,蒙特利尔Vanier学院哲学和人文学科讲师,QC H4L 3X9。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
57.10%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信