Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Kevin Vallier
{"title":"<i>Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side</i>","authors":"Kevin Vallier","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469629","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Sustaining Democracy is Robert Talisse’s well-argued follow-up to his previous book, Overdoing Democracy. Talisse has argued that American political polarization endangers democracy. The problem occurs when Americans allow their politics to become their identity and, in doing so, lose crosscutting identities, religious, familial, and civic. We not only lose the intrinsic value of those identities; we overdo democracy, and make it worse.In Sustaining Democracy, Talisse explores the political mindset that can sustain a democratic society. How must a citizen regard her opponents? The requisite attitude requires facing up to what Talisse calls the democrat’s dilemma. This is “the tension between the moral requirement to recognize the equality of political opponents and the moral directive to pursue and promote political justice” (4). This state of mind means allowing injustice to win for a time. If citizens do not allow injustice to rule, they must reject the political equality of their opponents. Our opponents see justice differently than we do. They sometimes win elections. If we insist on our own vision of justice, we will want to restrict the political equality of others. So, democratic citizens either allow injustice or violate political equality. What do we do?Talisse argues that sustaining democracy involves honoring political equality. The good citizen must recognize political equality and his biases about justice. Bearing both in mind, the good citizen can allow injustice to prevail for a time. And in doing so, he honors his opponents and sustains democracy with them.Many people fear that we must sometimes suspend democracy to promote justice, but if people are political equals, we cannot do this. Not always.Chapter 1 stresses that democracy involves political equality: politics is how equal persons govern themselves together. So democracy is a moral proposal, not merely a practical one. Citizens have to see others as part of a collective project, which means everyone gets an equal say. Indeed, they are entitled to one. That does not mean one must give in to their opponents’ views, only honor them in the democratic process. There is no complicity in injustice here. Citizens acknowledge a moral burden to discharge their civic duties to promote justice. Nonetheless, chapter 2 explains why democracy requires letting the opposition govern.Chapter 3 shows how belief polarization can exacerbate the democrat’s dilemma. Talisse suggests ways to overcome belief polarization. If Reba resists belief polarization, she can see the values and views she shared with others. Reba’s reflections may reduce her temptation to view political losses as disastrous. So she must scrutinize her own political thinking to locate her biases and correct them where she can (especially biases that lead her to delegitimize electoral victories). The belief that others misunderstand justice does not undermine the legitimacy of an election.Chapter 4 explores strategies to engage those with competing partisan loyalties. These forms of engagement are helpful but not adequate to sustain democratic politics. Indeed, some forms of political engagement can degrade the polity. Talisse invites readers to recognize that they have belief polarization and should respond by engaging reasonable criticisms of their political opinions.The second solution to belief polarization involves putting “political distance” between ourselves and other citizens. Citizens should sometimes step back from political participation, even retreat into social “solitude” on political matters. In the epilogue, Talisse stresses what citizens owe the other side of the political aisle: to become a more moral and effective political opponent.Talisse’s book is a work of public philosophy. Readers should not expect Talisse to engage every objection a professional democratic theorist might offer. But one can still raise concerns.I find Talisse’s articulation of the democrat’s dilemma illuminating. Democratic citizenship does require balancing two moral considerations: that we are right about justice and that others are our political equals. The tension resolves only if citizens allow those with incorrect views about justice to prevail. At least for an election cycle.True, grave injustices might entail restricting democracy. If a democratic president wins election by promising genocide, someone should stop the public from electing him. But in democratic politics, this scenario is rarer than often thought. Talisse argues that people are often mistaken about why others believe as they do, and in many cases, they simply do not know what they believe. One can impute false arguments and motives to them, making our opponents seem scary. The democrat’s dilemma creates genuine cognitive dissonance. But to honor our opponents, we must learn to live in that state of mind. Otherwise, we will undermine, rather than sustain, democratic institutions.The democrat’s dilemma generalizes to other features of open societies. Liberal societies face a related free speech dilemma. Others engage in offensive and immoral speech, but citizens allow it for the sake of other social goods. Markets raise a similar challenge. People may buy and sell goods some dislike. But if citizens want to honor one another’s property rights, even in a mixed economy, they must show forbearance. So, in one way, the dilemma Talisse identifies arises in many contexts, which Talisse might have acknowledged. His argument strengthens if the dilemma is a kind of familiar cognitive tension.I would not characterize the democrat’s dilemma as concerned primarily with disagreements about justice. The dilemma arises for other disagreements. Some citizens might not think about politics within a justice framework. Some Christians believe the Gospel means politics should transcend justice: public policy should focus on care, mercy, and grace. But these Christians will encounter a similar democrat’s dilemma.In Talisse’s defense, claims of justice might have unique properties. Injustice provokes emotional responses and actions in ways that other disagreements do not. Justice must be done. And when someone commits an injustice, citizens must spring into action. Many social philosophers have recognized this, and so, if we want to defend Talisse, one can argue that injustice renders the dilemma acute.The reader need also consider a broader array of responses to the democrat’s dilemma than Talisse offers. Imagine you find Roe v. Wade just. But you also know that when judges decide contentious issues, they distort our politics. People will vote for otherwise odious politicians based on judicial nominees alone and so ignore other vital issues.Citizens face the democrat’s dilemma in the near term: sometimes a pro-life or pro-choice president will win, and their judges prevail. But one might argue that the democrat’s dilemma dissolves at the federal level if the public decentralizes abortion policy. Citizens can set abortion aside in national elections, and neither side must convince themselves to tolerate an unjust abortion regime. They relocate the dispute to states, which contain more internal consensus on the issue. This is not odd. Democratic societies often decentralize political decisions to resolve conflicts.One might take issue with another matter—namely, Talisse’s focus on personal ethics. Yes, citizens must face the tension between true justice and respect for political equality. And yes, they must learn to live with it. But most people’s ordinary attitudes will not change by reflecting on the democrat’s dilemma. Talisse knows that social factors determine our political attitudes. In light of this, I found it a bit odd that Talisse’s recommendations focus so much on the individual. If the reader buys Talisse’s arguments, she may still find it too challenging to resist tribal forces. Her environment must change to ensure she can develop the necessary mindset.Here Talisse can again recommend that we develop crosscutting identities. Then we can free ourselves from tribalism if we affiliate with another one of our groups. That’s good advice. But I still worry that unilateral action lacks proper realism. Theorists and policy makers must also examine institutional reforms that improve democracy, such as adopting electoral procedures that generate more than two parties. With three or more options, people might develop more nuanced political attitudes. This and other suggestions can add up. The implication is that these institutional reforms may sustain democracy far better than individual action.Talisse’s sage advice may become practical only if it accompanies institutional reforms. Yes, perhaps one must begin with attitude change. But I am not sure. Some polarization-reducing and trust-raising reforms may work even in the current political environment.Some argue that campaign finance reform can reduce polarization. Agenda setters in legislatures engage in negative agenda setting: preventing votes, often to benefit donors and friends. With negative agenda setting, legislatures can resolve disputes through deliberation and voting. They cannot vote on legislation that addresses pressing social problems.But negative agenda setting is not (yet) a polarized issue. Indeed, few people know about it. But reforms here could greatly improve the democratic process.I agree with Talisse’s solution. But Talisse overemphasizes disagreement about justice, and his solution places excess weight on personal ethics. Nonetheless, Sustaining Democracy is an insightful, clear work from a seasoned democratic theorist with much to teach the reflective democratic public.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469629","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Sustaining Democracy is Robert Talisse’s well-argued follow-up to his previous book, Overdoing Democracy. Talisse has argued that American political polarization endangers democracy. The problem occurs when Americans allow their politics to become their identity and, in doing so, lose crosscutting identities, religious, familial, and civic. We not only lose the intrinsic value of those identities; we overdo democracy, and make it worse.In Sustaining Democracy, Talisse explores the political mindset that can sustain a democratic society. How must a citizen regard her opponents? The requisite attitude requires facing up to what Talisse calls the democrat’s dilemma. This is “the tension between the moral requirement to recognize the equality of political opponents and the moral directive to pursue and promote political justice” (4). This state of mind means allowing injustice to win for a time. If citizens do not allow injustice to rule, they must reject the political equality of their opponents. Our opponents see justice differently than we do. They sometimes win elections. If we insist on our own vision of justice, we will want to restrict the political equality of others. So, democratic citizens either allow injustice or violate political equality. What do we do?Talisse argues that sustaining democracy involves honoring political equality. The good citizen must recognize political equality and his biases about justice. Bearing both in mind, the good citizen can allow injustice to prevail for a time. And in doing so, he honors his opponents and sustains democracy with them.Many people fear that we must sometimes suspend democracy to promote justice, but if people are political equals, we cannot do this. Not always.Chapter 1 stresses that democracy involves political equality: politics is how equal persons govern themselves together. So democracy is a moral proposal, not merely a practical one. Citizens have to see others as part of a collective project, which means everyone gets an equal say. Indeed, they are entitled to one. That does not mean one must give in to their opponents’ views, only honor them in the democratic process. There is no complicity in injustice here. Citizens acknowledge a moral burden to discharge their civic duties to promote justice. Nonetheless, chapter 2 explains why democracy requires letting the opposition govern.Chapter 3 shows how belief polarization can exacerbate the democrat’s dilemma. Talisse suggests ways to overcome belief polarization. If Reba resists belief polarization, she can see the values and views she shared with others. Reba’s reflections may reduce her temptation to view political losses as disastrous. So she must scrutinize her own political thinking to locate her biases and correct them where she can (especially biases that lead her to delegitimize electoral victories). The belief that others misunderstand justice does not undermine the legitimacy of an election.Chapter 4 explores strategies to engage those with competing partisan loyalties. These forms of engagement are helpful but not adequate to sustain democratic politics. Indeed, some forms of political engagement can degrade the polity. Talisse invites readers to recognize that they have belief polarization and should respond by engaging reasonable criticisms of their political opinions.The second solution to belief polarization involves putting “political distance” between ourselves and other citizens. Citizens should sometimes step back from political participation, even retreat into social “solitude” on political matters. In the epilogue, Talisse stresses what citizens owe the other side of the political aisle: to become a more moral and effective political opponent.Talisse’s book is a work of public philosophy. Readers should not expect Talisse to engage every objection a professional democratic theorist might offer. But one can still raise concerns.I find Talisse’s articulation of the democrat’s dilemma illuminating. Democratic citizenship does require balancing two moral considerations: that we are right about justice and that others are our political equals. The tension resolves only if citizens allow those with incorrect views about justice to prevail. At least for an election cycle.True, grave injustices might entail restricting democracy. If a democratic president wins election by promising genocide, someone should stop the public from electing him. But in democratic politics, this scenario is rarer than often thought. Talisse argues that people are often mistaken about why others believe as they do, and in many cases, they simply do not know what they believe. One can impute false arguments and motives to them, making our opponents seem scary. The democrat’s dilemma creates genuine cognitive dissonance. But to honor our opponents, we must learn to live in that state of mind. Otherwise, we will undermine, rather than sustain, democratic institutions.The democrat’s dilemma generalizes to other features of open societies. Liberal societies face a related free speech dilemma. Others engage in offensive and immoral speech, but citizens allow it for the sake of other social goods. Markets raise a similar challenge. People may buy and sell goods some dislike. But if citizens want to honor one another’s property rights, even in a mixed economy, they must show forbearance. So, in one way, the dilemma Talisse identifies arises in many contexts, which Talisse might have acknowledged. His argument strengthens if the dilemma is a kind of familiar cognitive tension.I would not characterize the democrat’s dilemma as concerned primarily with disagreements about justice. The dilemma arises for other disagreements. Some citizens might not think about politics within a justice framework. Some Christians believe the Gospel means politics should transcend justice: public policy should focus on care, mercy, and grace. But these Christians will encounter a similar democrat’s dilemma.In Talisse’s defense, claims of justice might have unique properties. Injustice provokes emotional responses and actions in ways that other disagreements do not. Justice must be done. And when someone commits an injustice, citizens must spring into action. Many social philosophers have recognized this, and so, if we want to defend Talisse, one can argue that injustice renders the dilemma acute.The reader need also consider a broader array of responses to the democrat’s dilemma than Talisse offers. Imagine you find Roe v. Wade just. But you also know that when judges decide contentious issues, they distort our politics. People will vote for otherwise odious politicians based on judicial nominees alone and so ignore other vital issues.Citizens face the democrat’s dilemma in the near term: sometimes a pro-life or pro-choice president will win, and their judges prevail. But one might argue that the democrat’s dilemma dissolves at the federal level if the public decentralizes abortion policy. Citizens can set abortion aside in national elections, and neither side must convince themselves to tolerate an unjust abortion regime. They relocate the dispute to states, which contain more internal consensus on the issue. This is not odd. Democratic societies often decentralize political decisions to resolve conflicts.One might take issue with another matter—namely, Talisse’s focus on personal ethics. Yes, citizens must face the tension between true justice and respect for political equality. And yes, they must learn to live with it. But most people’s ordinary attitudes will not change by reflecting on the democrat’s dilemma. Talisse knows that social factors determine our political attitudes. In light of this, I found it a bit odd that Talisse’s recommendations focus so much on the individual. If the reader buys Talisse’s arguments, she may still find it too challenging to resist tribal forces. Her environment must change to ensure she can develop the necessary mindset.Here Talisse can again recommend that we develop crosscutting identities. Then we can free ourselves from tribalism if we affiliate with another one of our groups. That’s good advice. But I still worry that unilateral action lacks proper realism. Theorists and policy makers must also examine institutional reforms that improve democracy, such as adopting electoral procedures that generate more than two parties. With three or more options, people might develop more nuanced political attitudes. This and other suggestions can add up. The implication is that these institutional reforms may sustain democracy far better than individual action.Talisse’s sage advice may become practical only if it accompanies institutional reforms. Yes, perhaps one must begin with attitude change. But I am not sure. Some polarization-reducing and trust-raising reforms may work even in the current political environment.Some argue that campaign finance reform can reduce polarization. Agenda setters in legislatures engage in negative agenda setting: preventing votes, often to benefit donors and friends. With negative agenda setting, legislatures can resolve disputes through deliberation and voting. They cannot vote on legislation that addresses pressing social problems.But negative agenda setting is not (yet) a polarized issue. Indeed, few people know about it. But reforms here could greatly improve the democratic process.I agree with Talisse’s solution. But Talisse overemphasizes disagreement about justice, and his solution places excess weight on personal ethics. Nonetheless, Sustaining Democracy is an insightful, clear work from a seasoned democratic theorist with much to teach the reflective democratic public.
维持民主:我们对对方的亏欠
《维持民主》是罗伯特·塔利斯继其上一本书《过度民主》之后的又一部颇有争议的著作。塔利斯认为,美国的政治两极分化危及民主。当美国人允许他们的政治成为他们的身份时,问题就出现了,在这样做的过程中,他们失去了跨领域的身份,宗教的,家庭的和公民的。我们不仅失去了这些身份的内在价值;我们过度民主,使它变得更糟。在《维持民主》一书中,塔利斯探讨了能够维持民主社会的政治心态。一个公民该如何看待她的对手?这种必要的态度要求直面塔利斯所说的民主党的困境。这就是“承认政治对手平等的道德要求与追求和促进政治正义的道德指示之间的紧张关系”(4)。这种心态意味着允许不公正在一段时间内获胜。如果公民不允许不公正统治,他们就必须拒绝对手的政治平等。我们的对手对正义的看法与我们不同。他们有时会赢得选举。如果我们坚持自己的正义观,我们就会想要限制他人的政治平等。因此,民主公民要么允许不公正,要么违反政治平等。我们该怎么办?塔利斯认为,维持民主需要尊重政治平等。好公民必须认识到政治平等和他对正义的偏见。考虑到这两点,好公民可以允许不公正盛行一段时间。在这样做的过程中,他尊重他的对手,并与他们一起维持民主。许多人担心我们有时必须暂停民主以促进正义,但如果人们在政治上是平等的,我们就不能这样做。不总是正确的。第一章强调民主涉及政治平等:政治是平等的人如何共同管理自己。因此,民主是一种道德建议,而不仅仅是一种实践建议。公民必须将他人视为集体项目的一部分,这意味着每个人都有平等的发言权。事实上,他们有资格这样做。这并不意味着一个人必须屈服于对手的观点,只是在民主进程中尊重他们。这里不存在不公正的共犯。公民认识到履行公民义务促进正义的道德责任。尽管如此,第二章解释了为什么民主需要让反对派执政。第三章阐述了信仰极化如何加剧了民主党人的困境。塔利斯提出了克服信念两极分化的方法。如果热巴能抵制信仰两极分化,她就能看到自己与他人共有的价值观和观点。热巴的反思可能会减少她将政治失败视为灾难性的诱惑。因此,她必须仔细审视自己的政治思维,找出自己的偏见,并在可能的地方纠正它们(尤其是那些导致她使选举胜利失去合法性的偏见)。认为别人误解了正义,并不会破坏选举的合法性。第4章探讨了吸引那些具有竞争党派忠诚的人的策略。这些形式的接触是有益的,但不足以维持民主政治。事实上,某些形式的政治参与会降低政体。塔利斯邀请读者认识到他们有信仰两极分化,应该对他们的政治观点进行合理的批评。第二个解决信念两极分化的方法是在我们自己和其他公民之间拉开“政治距离”。公民有时应该退出政治参与,甚至在政治问题上退居社会“孤独”。在结语中,塔利斯强调了公民对另一方的责任:成为一个更有道德、更有效的政治对手。塔利斯的书是一部公共哲学著作。读者不应期望塔利斯对专业民主理论家可能提出的每一个反对意见都予以反驳。但人们仍然可以提出担忧。我觉得塔利斯对民主党困境的阐述很有启发性。民主公民身份确实需要平衡两种道德考虑:我们对正义的看法是正确的,其他人在政治上与我们平等。只有当公民允许那些对正义有错误看法的人占上风时,紧张局势才会得到解决。至少在选举周期内是这样。诚然,严重的不公正可能会限制民主。如果一个民主总统通过承诺种族灭绝赢得选举,应该有人阻止公众选举他。但在民主政治中,这种情况比通常想象的要少。塔利斯认为,人们常常会误解别人为什么会相信自己,而且在很多情况下,他们根本不知道自己相信什么。我们可以把错误的论点和动机归咎于他们,使我们的对手看起来很可怕。民主党的困境造成了真正的认知失调。但为了尊重我们的对手,我们必须学会以那种心态生活。否则,我们将破坏而不是维持民主制度。 民主党人的困境也适用于开放社会的其他特征。自由社会面临着一个相关的言论自由困境。有些人发表冒犯性和不道德的言论,但公民为了其他社会利益而允许这样做。市场也提出了类似的挑战。人们可以买卖一些不喜欢的商品。但如果公民想要尊重彼此的财产权,即使是在混合经济中,他们也必须表现出宽容。所以,在某种程度上,塔利斯所指出的困境出现在许多情境中,塔利斯可能已经承认了。如果这种困境是一种熟悉的认知紧张,他的论点就会得到加强。我不会把民主党人的困境描述为主要涉及对正义的分歧。其他分歧也带来了这种困境。一些公民可能不会在司法框架内思考政治。一些基督徒认为福音意味着政治应该超越正义:公共政策应该关注关怀、怜悯和恩典。但这些基督教徒将遇到类似的民主困境。在塔利斯的辩护中,正义的主张可能具有独特的属性。不公正会激发情绪反应和行动,而其他分歧不会。正义必须得到伸张。当有人犯下不公正的罪行时,公民必须立即行动起来。许多社会哲学家已经认识到这一点,因此,如果我们想为塔利斯辩护,人们可以辩称,不公正使这种困境变得尖锐。读者还需要考虑对民主党困境的更广泛的回应,而不是塔利斯所提供的。想象一下你发现罗伊诉韦德案只是。但你也知道,当法官决定有争议的问题时,他们扭曲了我们的政治。人们只会根据司法候选人投票给那些令人讨厌的政客,从而忽视了其他重要问题。公民们在短期内面临着民主党的困境:有时反堕胎或支持堕胎的总统会获胜,他们的法官会获胜。但有人可能会说,如果公众将堕胎政策下放,民主党的困境在联邦层面就会消失。公民可以在全国选举中把堕胎问题搁置一边,双方都不能说服自己容忍不公正的堕胎制度。他们将争端转移到各国,这些国家在这个问题上有更多的内部共识。这并不奇怪。民主社会经常分散政治决策来解决冲突。人们可能会对另一件事产生异议——即塔利斯对个人道德的关注。是的,公民必须面对真正的正义与尊重政治平等之间的紧张关系。是的,他们必须学会与之共存。但大多数人的普通态度不会因为反思民主党的困境而改变。塔利斯知道社会因素决定了我们的政治态度。有鉴于此,我发现塔利斯的建议如此注重个人,这有点奇怪。如果读者相信塔利斯的观点,她可能仍然会觉得抵抗部落势力太有挑战性。她的环境必须改变,以确保她能养成必要的心态。在这里,塔利斯再次建议我们开发横切身份。然后,如果我们加入另一个群体,我们就能从部落主义中解脱出来。这是个好建议。但我仍然担心,单边行动缺乏适当的现实主义。理论家和政策制定者还必须研究改善民主的制度改革,例如采用产生两个以上政党的选举程序。有了三个或更多的选择,人们可能会形成更微妙的政治态度。这一点和其他建议可以加起来。言下之意是,这些制度改革可能比个人行动更能维持民主。只有伴随着制度改革,塔利斯的明智建议才有可能成为现实。是的,也许一个人必须从改变态度开始。但我不确定。即使在当前的政治环境下,一些减少两极分化和提高信任的改革也可能奏效。一些人认为,改革竞选资金可以减少两极化。立法机构的议程设定者参与消极的议程设定:阻止投票,通常是为了让捐赠者和朋友受益。通过消极议程设置,立法机关可以通过审议和投票来解决争议。他们不能对解决紧迫社会问题的立法投票。但消极的议程设置(还)不是一个两极分化的问题。事实上,很少有人知道它。但这里的改革可以极大地改善民主进程。我同意塔利斯的解决方案。但塔利斯过分强调了对正义的分歧,他的解决方案过分强调了个人道德。尽管如此,《维持民主》是一位经验丰富的民主理论家写的一部深刻而清晰的作品,可以给善于反思的民主公众带来很多启示。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信